Models of Organic Organization in Montpellier Vitalism


in Early Science and Medicine
Restricted Access
Get Access to Full Text
Rent on DeepDyve

Have an Access Token?



Enter your access token to activate and access content online.

Please login and go to your personal user account to enter your access token.



Help

Have Institutional Access?



Access content through your institution. Any other coaching guidance?



Connect

The species of vitalism discussed here is a malleable construct, often with a poisonous reputation (but one which I want to rehabilitate), hovering in between the realms of the philosophy of biology, the history of medicine, and the scientific background of the Radical Enlightenment (case in point, the influence of vitalist medicine on Diderot). This is a more vital vitalism, or at least a more ‘biologistic,’ ‘embodied,’ medicalized vitalism. I distinguish between what I would call ‘substantival’ and ‘functional’ forms of vitalism, as applied to the eighteenth century. Substantival vitalism presupposes the existence of something like a (substantive) vital force which either plays a causal role in the natural world as studied by scientific means, or remains a kind of hovering, extra-causal entity. Functional vitalism tends to operate “post facto,” from the existence of living bodies to the desire to find explanatory models that will do justice to their uniquely ‘vital’ properties in a way that fully mechanistic models (such as Cartesian mechanism) cannot. I discuss some representative figures of the Montpellier school as being functional rather than substantival vitalists, particularly as regards the models of organic organization which they develop, and make some suggestions as to how these relate to the then-nascent science of biology.


Models of Organic Organization in Montpellier Vitalism


in Early Science and Medicine

Sections

References

7

 Moritz Schlick“Naturphilosophie,” in Lehrbuch der Philosophievol. 2: Die Philosophie in ihren Einzelgebieten ed. Max Dessoir (Berlin 1925) 393-492.

12

 Scott Gilbert and Sahotra Sarkar“Embracing Complexity: Organicism for the 21st Century,” Developmental Dynamics 219 (2000) 1-9 at 1.

14

 Paul-Joseph BarthezNouveaux éléments de la science de l’homme2. vols.(2nd ed. Paris 1806) 1 Chapter III 82-111

16

 BarthezNouveaux éléments de la science de l’homme1:27 107 83.

28

 See Tobias Cheung“From the Organism of a Body to the Body of an Organism: Occurrence and Meaning of the Word ‘Organism’ from the Seventeenth to the Nineteenth Centuries,” British Journal for the History of Science39:3 (2006) 319-39; Charles T. Wolfe “The Organism as Ontological Go-Between. Hybridity Boundaries and Degrees of Reality in its Conceptual History” Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 48 (2014) 151-61; and on the animal economy as an organism concept Wolfe and Terada “Animal Economy.”

36

 Denise Leduc-Fayette“La Mettrie et Descartes,” Europe56(1978) 37-48 at 45. In his Vitalizing Nature in the Enlightenment Peter Hans Reill also opposes vitalism to in his case Naturphilosophie on similar grounds; see the useful discussion in Gaukroger “‘The Enlightenment Revolt Against Rationalism:’ Critical Notice of Peter Hanns Reill Vitalizing Nature in the EnlightenmentAustralian Review of Public Affairs 26 (2005) last accessed 01/04/2016; and John Zammito “From Vital Materialism to Naturphilosophie: The Question of Historical Continuity” in Life Forms in the Eighteenth Century eds. Keith Baker and Jenna Gibb (Toronto 2016) 70-91. In this respect I follow Reill’s opposition between a more metaphysical position (Naturphilosophie) and a more heuristically oriented inquiry into life (vitalism); this maps onto my distinction between substantival and functional vitalism. However scholars of Romanticism will object that it was quite empirically oriented: see e.g. R. Mitchell’s Experimental Life: Vitalism in Romantic Science and Literature (Baltimore 2013). In earlier work on the topic I opposed the Montpellier vitalist notion of organization to other concepts of organism in terms of materialism-friendly perspectives versus ones which appealed to a foundational interiority; here I am simply suggesting that we should distinguish between two approaches to structure and organization in which the Montpellier vitalist approach which I have described as structural and relational (one could also say ‘organizational’ at the risk of sounding tautologous) is less hostile to mechanism and to the power of reductionist explanations of components than we might think.

37

 BertalanffyModern Theories of Development48.

42

 BordeuŒuvres2:670.

43

 Ménuret“Ténesme,” Encyclopedie 16:137a.

Index Card

Content Metrics

Content Metrics

All Time Past Year Past 30 Days
Abstract Views 24 24 15
Full Text Views 10 10 10
PDF Downloads 2 2 2
EPUB Downloads 0 0 0