The author defends the claim that there are cases in which we should promote irrationality by arguing (1) that it is sometimes better to be in an irrational state of mind, and (2) that we can often (purposefully) influence our state of mind via our actions. The first claim is supported by presenting cases of irrational belief and by countering a common line of argument associated with William K. Clifford, who defended the idea that having an irrational belief is always worse than having a rational one. In support of the second claim, the author then explains how the control we have over our beliefs could look like. In conclusion, the author suggests that the argument of this essay is not restricted to the irrationality of beliefs, but can be applied to irrational states of mind in general (like desires, intentions, emotions, or hopes). In an outlook on the “ethics of belief” debate, the author points out that the argument of this essay need not conflict with evidentialism, but does so when combined with another plausible claim about the meaning of doxastic ought-statements.
Purchase
Buy instant access (PDF download and unlimited online access):
Institutional Login
Log in with Open Athens, Shibboleth, or your institutional credentials
Personal login
Log in with your brill.com account
Bennett Jonathan 1990. “Why Is Belief Involuntary?” Analysis 50, 87–107.
Chrisman Matthew 2008. “Ought to Believe.” The Journal of Philosophy 105, 346–370.
Clifford William K. 1877. “The Ethics of Belief.” In: The Ethics of Belief. And other Essays. ny: Prometheus Books 1999, 70–96.
Fingarette Herbert 1969. Self-deception. Berkeley / la / London: ucp2000.
Hazlett Allan 2013. A Luxury of the Understanding. On the Value of True Belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
James William 1896. “The Will to Believe.” In: The Will to Believe. And other Essays in popular Philosophy, and Human Immortality. Dover / ny: Dover Publishing 1956, 1–31.
Kelly Thomas 2003. “Epistemic Rationality as Instrumental Rationality: A Critique.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66, 612–640.
McCormick Miriam S. 2015. Believing Against the Evidence. Agency and the Ethics of Belief. London / ny: Routledge.
Owens David J. 2000. Reason without Freedom. The Problem of Epistemic Normativity. London / ny: Routledge.
Owens David J. 2017. “Value and Epistemic Normativity.” In: Normativity and Control. Oxford: Oxford University Press (forthcoming).
Papineau David 2013. “There Are No Norms of Belief.” In: Chan Timothy (ed.), The Aim of Belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 64–79.
Parfit Derek 1984. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press 1987.
Parfit Derek 2001. “Rationality and Reasons.” In: Egonsson Dan et al. (eds.), Exploring Practical Philosophy: From Action to Values. Aldershot: Ashgate, 17–39.
Pascal Blaise 1670. Gedanken. (Übersetzt von Ulrich Kunzmann, kommentiert von Eduard Zwierlein). Berlin: Suhrkamp, 2012.
Schmidt Sebastian 2016. “Können wir uns entscheiden, etwas zu glauben? Zur Möglichkeit und Unmöglichkeit eines doxastischen Willens.” Grazer Philosophische Studien 93, 571–582.
Shah Nishi 2006. “A New Argument for Evidentialism.” The Philosophical Quarterly 56, 481–498.
Walgenbach Simon 2016. “Können wir uns dazu entscheiden, etwas zu glauben?” Grazer Philosophische Studien 93, 583–592.
All Time | Past Year | Past 30 Days | |
---|---|---|---|
Abstract Views | 481 | 66 | 2 |
Full Text Views | 280 | 0 | 0 |
PDF Views & Downloads | 112 | 3 | 0 |
The author defends the claim that there are cases in which we should promote irrationality by arguing (1) that it is sometimes better to be in an irrational state of mind, and (2) that we can often (purposefully) influence our state of mind via our actions. The first claim is supported by presenting cases of irrational belief and by countering a common line of argument associated with William K. Clifford, who defended the idea that having an irrational belief is always worse than having a rational one. In support of the second claim, the author then explains how the control we have over our beliefs could look like. In conclusion, the author suggests that the argument of this essay is not restricted to the irrationality of beliefs, but can be applied to irrational states of mind in general (like desires, intentions, emotions, or hopes). In an outlook on the “ethics of belief” debate, the author points out that the argument of this essay need not conflict with evidentialism, but does so when combined with another plausible claim about the meaning of doxastic ought-statements.
All Time | Past Year | Past 30 Days | |
---|---|---|---|
Abstract Views | 481 | 66 | 2 |
Full Text Views | 280 | 0 | 0 |
PDF Views & Downloads | 112 | 3 | 0 |