In this article, I analyze the idea of “stepping into the void” (κενεµβατεῖν), which can be traced in the thinking of both Proclus and Damascius, but which sets their perspectives apart. Thus, I show how Proclus warns us that to speak about the absolute principle, taking it as an object of thought, is a negative “stepping into the void” that should be avoided. On the contrary, I show that Damascius starts from this warning and tries to prove that the only adequate manner in which we can trace the absolute principle and approach it is precisely through “stepping into the void,” yet, this time, in a positive sense, as a constant attempt to understand that the principle is an absolute void which reverses our discourse.
Purchase
Buy instant access (PDF download and unlimited online access):
Institutional Login
Log in with Open Athens, Shibboleth, or your institutional credentials
Personal login
Log in with your brill.com account
Damascius Combès J. , L. G. Westerink (ed), Traité des premiers principes , (Les Belles Lettres , Paris 1986-1991 ) 3 vols. .
Damascius Ahbel-Rappe Sara , Problems and Solutions Concerning First Principles , (Oxford University Press , Oxford 2010 ).
Plato Grube G. M. A. & Plato , Republic , (Hackett Publishing Company , Indianapolis/Cambridge 1997 ) Complete works, edited, with introduction and notes, by John M. Cooper .
Plato Gill Mary Louise, Ryan Paul & Plato , Parmenides , (Hackett Publishing Company , Indianapolis/Cambridge 1997 ) Complete works, edited, with introduction and notes, by John M. Cooper .
Plotinus Armstrong A. H. , Enneads , (Harvard University Press , London 1966-1988 ) (Loeb Classical Library) 7 vols. .
Proclus , Wilhelm Kroll (ed), In Rem Publicam Commentarii , (Teubner , Leipzig 1903-1906 ) 2 vols. .
Proclus Festugière A.-J. , Commentaire sur la République , (Vrin , Paris 1970 ) 3 vols. .
Proclus , Hermann Diels (ed), In Platonis Timaeum , (Teubner , Leipzig 1903-1906 ) 3 vols. .
Proclus , Commentary on Plato’s Timaeus , (Cambridge University Press , Cambridge 2006 ) translation with introduction and notes by Harold Tarrant .
Proclus , Carlos Steel (ed), In Platonis Parmenidem Commentaria , (Oxford University Press , Oxford 2009 ).
Proclus Morrow Glenn R. & Dillon John M. , Commentary on Plato’s Parmenides , (Princeton University Press , Princeton 1987 ).
Proclus Dodds E. R. , The Elements of Theology , (Clarendon Press , Oxford 1963 ).
Proclus Saffrey H. D. & Westerink L. G. , Théologie platonicienne , (Les Belles Lettres , Paris 1968-1997 ) 6 vols. .
Athanassiadi P. , La lutte pour l’orthodoxie dans le platonisme tardif de Numenius à Damascius , (Les Belles Lettres , Paris 2006 ).
Béguin V. , '‘Ineffable et indicible chez Damascius’ ' (2013 ) 4 Les Études philosophiques : 553 -569 .
Combès J. , '‘L’un humain selon Damascius. L’objet de la troisième hypothèse du Parménide’ ' (1978 ) 62 (161-164 ) Revue des Sciences Philosophiques et Théologiques : 189 -197 reprinted in Combès (1989) .
Combès J. , '‘Proclus et Damascius’ ', in G. Boss & G. Seel (eds), Proclus et son influence. Actes du colloque de Neuchâtel, juin 1985 , (Grand Midi , Zürich 1987 ) 245 -271 reprinted in Combès (1989) .
Combès J. , Études néoplatoniciennes , (Jérôme Millon , Grenoble 1989 ).
Dillon J. , '‘Damascius on the Ineffable’ ' (1996 ) 78 Archiv für die Geschichte der Philosophie : 120 -129 .
Gersh S. , Being Different. More Neoplatonism after Derrida , (Brill , Leiden-Boston 2014 ).
Hoffmann Ph. , '‘L’expression de l’indicible dans le néoplatonisme grec, de Plotin à Damascius’ ', in C. Lévy & L. Pernot (eds), Dire l’évidence , (L’Harmattan , Paris 1997 ) 335 -390 .
Lavaud L. , '‘L’ineffable et l’impossible: Damascius au regard de la deconstruction’ ' (2007 ) 96 Philosophie : 46 -66 doi: 10.3917/philo.096.0046. .
Metry-Tresson C. , L’aporie ou l’expérience des limites de la pensée dans le Péri Archôn de Damaskios , (Brill , Leiden-Boston 2012 ).
Napoli V. , Επέκεινα τοῦ ἑνός. Il principio totalmente ineffabile tra dialettica ed esegesi in Damascio , (Officina di Studi Medievali , Catania 2008 ).
O’Meara D. , '‘Notes on the Aporetics of the One in Greek Neoplatonism’ ', in J.-M. Narbonne & A. Reckermann (eds), Pensées de l’Un dans l’histoire de la philosophie. Études en hommage au professeur Werner Beierwaltes , (Presses de l’Université Laval / Vrin , Laval / Paris 2004 ) 98 -107 .
Opsomer J. , '‘Syrianus, Proclus, and Damascius’ ', in J. Warren & F. Sheffield (eds), The Routledge Companion to Ancient Philosophy , (Routledge , London 2014 ) 1479 -1518 .
Rappe S. , Reading Neoplatonism: Non-Discursive Thinking in the Texts of Plotinus, Proclus and Damascius , (Cambridge University Press , Cambridge 2000 ).
Rappe S. , '‘Scepticism in the sixth century? Damascius’ ' (1998 ) 36 Doubts and Solutions Concerning First Principles’. Journal of the History of Philosophy : 337 -363 .
Steel C. , '‘“Negatio negationis”. Proclus on the Final Lemma of the First Hypothesis of the Parmenides’ ', in J. J. Cleary (ed), Traditions of Platonism. Essays in Honour of John Dillon , (Ashgate , Alsershot, Brookfield 1999 ) 351 -368 .
Trabattoni F. , '‘Le ‘silence de Platon’, ou le renversement du discours dialectique chez Damascius’ ' (2011 ) Argument from Hypothesis in Ancient Philosophy : 413 -435 Elenchos, 59, Napoli, Bibliopolis .
Van Riel G. , '‘Damascius’ ', in L. P. Gerson (ed), The Cambridge History of Philosophy in Late Antiquity , (Cambridge University Press , Cambridge 2010 ) 667 -696 .
Vlad M. , '‘De principiis: de l’aporétique de l’Un à l’aporétique de l’Ineffable’ ' (2004 ) 2 Chora, Revue d’études anciennes et médiévales: philosophie, théologie, sciences : 125 -148 .
Vlad M. , '‘Damascius et la divination du principe incoordonné’ ' (2013 ) 111 (3 ) Revue Philosophique de Louvain : 469 -490 DOI: 10.2143/RPL.111.3.2998042. .
Vlad M. , '‘Discourse and suppression of discourse in Damascius’ De principiis’ ' (2014 ) 2 Rhizomata. A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science : 187 -233 doi: 10.1515/rhiz-2014-0009. .
Vlad M. , '‘Damascius and Dionysius on prayer and silence’ ', in J. Dillon & A. Timotin (eds), Platonic Theories of Prayer , (Brill , Leiden/Boston 2016 ) 192 -212 doi: 10.1163/9789004309005_012. .
Westerink L. G. , '‘Damascius, Commentateur de Platon’ ', in Le Néoplatonisme, Actes du colloque international du Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique, Royaumont, 9-13 juin 1969 , (CNRS , Paris 1971 ) 253 -260 .
Proclus, Commentary on Plato’s Parmenides, 1097. 17-20: Ἢ ἔστιν ἐπέκεινα τοῦ ἑνὸς, ἢ οὐδέν ἐστιν, ἢ οὐχ ἓν, ἑκάτερον δὲ ἄτοπον. Τὸ ἄρα πρῶτόν ἐστι τὸ ὡς ἀληθῶς ἓν καὶ ὁ πάντων βασιλεὺς καὶ τἀγαθόν. (translation by Glenn R. Morrow and John M. Dillon, p. 444).
Trabattoni (2011) argues that, for Damascius, the first principle implies a certain contradiction between coordination and incoordination, this contradiction being the distinctive sign of the real first principle. “Le principe qui a la qualité requise, en effet, doit être la non-coordination en tant que telle; mais c’est exactement cette qualité qui crée la contradiction. Dans ce cas, en effet, il n’est pas logiquement possible que la non-coordination absolue maintienne une coordination avec les non-coordinations partielles” (p. 428). Yet, we should notice that, for Damascius, the incoordination is not a quality describing he principle’s nature; in this sense, the principle surpasses any discursive contradiction. See for instance De principiis, R. I, 10. 24-11. 1; W. I, 13. 20-24 (οὐδὲ ταῦτα φύσις αὐτοῦ [. . .] τὸ ἀσύντακτον πρὸς πάντα).
Gersh (2014) notices that the discussion of the Ineffable “is supplemented by briefer references to it as not a principle, as both a principle and not a principle, and as neither a principle nor not a principle, this alternation providing a classic illustration of the reversal of discourse of which he constantly speaks” (pp. 134-135).
Gersh (2014) considers the Ineffable as “the ultimate referent of discourse” (p. 126). See also Opsomer (2014), who notices: “Damascius proposes to get rid of all reference to oneness when thinking about the highest. Yet his attempt, too, fails. For Damascius has to find some linguistic expression to refer to it.” (p. 1507). And yet, Damascius does not really refer to this principle, but rather tries to prove that the Ineffable is non-referential. Damascius is actually trying to suggest the Ineffable as that to which we cannot refer in any way, not even through negations. In fact, not even negations can identify the Ineffable as such, as an actual object of negation, as a “denied” (τὸ ἀποφατόν), because “even the denied is a thing, while it [the Ineffable] is nothing, hence, it is not even denied” (De principiis, R. I, 15. 20-21; W. I, 21. 15-16: καὶ τὸ ἀποφατὸν πρᾶγµα, τὸ δὲ οὐδὲν, οὐδὲ ἄρα ἀποφατόν). Accordingly, nothing we say succeeds in really making of it an actual “referent” of the discourse, despite the fact that anything we say tends to keep this structure of a discourse referring to something.
Metry-Tresson (2012) considers that κενεµβατεῖν has a rather pejorative sense for Damascius: “Ce terme porté à un niveau métaphysique exprime en fin de compte la transcendance de ce qui est suressentiel. Damaskios reprend lui aussi cette signification, mais lui confère un sens péjoratif vis-à-vis de la valeur épistémologique de la négation. Tout raisonnement qui tente de saisir le non-être et l’Un est condamné à marcher dans le vide et parce qu’il ne peut rien toucher de ce qui dépasse l’être et engendrer un raisonnement viable, il l’appelle bâtard.” (p. 220) Yet, for Damascius, stepping into the void (κενεµβατεῖν) does not simply indicate the fact that negations uselessly try to seize the principle. On the contrary, he systematically practices this stepping into the void because, for him, the extent to which the principle is ungraspable can only be grasped through realizing that we cannot say anything about it, either affirmatively, or negatively.
Napoli (2008) suggests that κενεµβατεῖν consists in “un cadere nel nulla constituito dal principio unico del tutto” (p. 334).
See also Hoffmann (1997), who notices: “La tonalité du Traité des premiers principes, qui à bien des égards tient lieu d’un commentaire de la première hypothèse, est pessimiste, angoissée. Un lecteur attentif y relève des notations presque «existentielles»: les ὠδῖνες de l’âme semblent ne devoir jamais être satisfaites, le discours humain est voué à un renversement (περιτροπή) qui condamne nos pensées et nos opinions à marcher dans le vide (κενεµβατεῖν) parce qu’elles sont vaines” (p. 339).
See for instance Lavaud (2007): “Damascius introduit cette notion [le renversement] en faisant le constat que le discours négatif n’est pas plus apte à exprimer le premier principe que le discours positif. Nier, en effet, c’est déjà introduire une délimitation entre une qualité et son absence, et c’est donc inévitablement déterminer, enclore dans une nature particulière. En ce sens, le premier principe n’est pas plus indicible que dicible, si l’on entend par indicible ce qui est le simple contradictoire du dicible.” (p. 53).
Metry-Tresson (2012) describes stepping into the void as an annihilation of our thinking, which ceases to exist: “Là où il n’y a plus de point d’appui pour elle, là où il n’y a plus aucun objet, la pensée cesse tout bonnement d’être. [. . .] Lorsque la pensée «marche dans le vide» - image chère à Damaskios - elle n’est plus que néant au sein du néant. Il n’y plus ni métaphysique, ni dialectique. Si tout a été dépassé, et donc les apories aussi, nous ne sommes plus que néant de connaissance et d’inconnaissance. [. . .] Les pensées et les mots ont éclaté.” (p. 74). “Ce verbe «marcher dans le vide» exprime une expérience insolite et très déstabilisante pour la pensée, celle du «sans-objet» et du sans appui, du vide, et du vertige.” (p. 80).
All Time | Past 365 days | Past 30 Days | |
---|---|---|---|
Abstract Views | 727 | 78 | 11 |
Full Text Views | 762 | 3 | 0 |
PDF Views & Downloads | 131 | 1 | 0 |
In this article, I analyze the idea of “stepping into the void” (κενεµβατεῖν), which can be traced in the thinking of both Proclus and Damascius, but which sets their perspectives apart. Thus, I show how Proclus warns us that to speak about the absolute principle, taking it as an object of thought, is a negative “stepping into the void” that should be avoided. On the contrary, I show that Damascius starts from this warning and tries to prove that the only adequate manner in which we can trace the absolute principle and approach it is precisely through “stepping into the void,” yet, this time, in a positive sense, as a constant attempt to understand that the principle is an absolute void which reverses our discourse.
All Time | Past 365 days | Past 30 Days | |
---|---|---|---|
Abstract Views | 727 | 78 | 11 |
Full Text Views | 762 | 3 | 0 |
PDF Views & Downloads | 131 | 1 | 0 |