It is a well-established opinion in the literature that the immediate circle of Plato’s disciples maintained that the generation of the cosmos described in the Timaeus was to be understood as an illustrative, or educational metaphor. On this account, Plato’s students were the first to hold an eternalist, metaphorical reading of the generation of the world, challenged by the Peripatos. When criticising their position in the De Caelo, however, Aristotle describes Early Academic philosophers as holding the more nuanced view that the world is ‘indestructible and yet generated’ (ἄφθαρτον μὲν […] γενόμενον δέ). Is it possible to make any sense of this formulation and restore a different position for Early Academic philosophers? In this paper, I claim that the standard reading can be challenged and that there is ground to believe that Speusippus and Xenocrates held that the world is generated but everlasting. What they denied having happened in time and said should be understood as an illustrative metaphor is the transition from the absence of an order to order or, in other words, the cosmogonic process itself.
Purchase
Buy instant access (PDF download and unlimited online access):
Institutional Login
Log in with Open Athens, Shibboleth, or your institutional credentials
Personal login
Log in with your brill.com account
Ademollo, F. (2012). ‘The Platonic Origins of Stoic Theology’, osap 43: 217–243.
Baltes, M. (1976). Die Weltentstehung des platonischen Timaios nach den antiken Interpreten.
Baltes, M. (1999). Γέγονεν (Platon, Tim. 28 B 7). Ist die Welt real entstanden oder nicht?’. In Id. Dianoemata. Kleine Schriften zu Platon und zum Platonismus, Teubner, 303–325.
Baltussen, H. (2003). ‘Early Reactions to Plato’s Timaeus. Polemic and Exegesis in Theophrastus and Epicurus’, Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies, 49–71.
Bénatouïl, T. (2018). ‘Speusippe et Xénocrate ont-ils systématisé la cosmologie du Timée?’. In. M.-A. Gavray, A. Michalewski (eds.), Les Principes Cosmologiques du Platonisme. Origines, Influences et Systématisation, Turhout: Brepols, 19–38.
Bonazzi, M. (2007). ‘Eudorus of Alexandria and early imperial Platonism’. Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies, 365–377.
Boys-Stones, G. (2018). Platonist Philosophy. 80 bc to ad 250. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Broadie, S. (2009). ‘The Possibilities of Being and Not-Being in De Caelo 1.11–12’. In A.C. Bowen, C. Wildberg (eds.), New Perspectives on Aristotle’s De Caelo, Leiden/Boston: Brill, 29–50.
Broadie, S. (2012). Nature and Divinity in Plato’s Timaeus. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Cardullo, R. L. (2010). ‘Creazionismo, Eternalismo e Causalità del Primo Principio. Platone, Aristotele e Alcuni Interpreti Neoplatonici’. Annali della facoltà di Scienze della formazione, 17–74.
Centrone, B. (2010). ‘L’esegesi del Timeo nell’antica Accademia’. In F. Celia, A. Ulacco (eds.). Il “Timeo”: esegesi greche, arabe, latine. Pisa: Pisa University Press, 57–80.
Chase, M. (2011). ‘Discussions On The Eternity Of The World In Late Antiquity’. Schole, 111–173.
Chiaradonna, R. (2012). ‘Platonist approaches to Aristotle: from Antiochus of Ascalon to Eudorus of Alexandria (and beyond)’. In M. Schofield (ed.) Aristotle, Plato and Pythagoreanism in the first century BC. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 28–52.
Chiaradonna, R. (2014). ‘Plotinus Metaphorical Reading of the Timaeus: Soul, Mathematics, Providence’. In P. d’Hoine and G. Van Riel (eds.) Fate, Providence, and Moral Responsibility in Ancient, Medieval and Early Modern Thought. Leuven: Leuven University Press, 187–210.
Cornford, F. M. (1937). Plato’s Cosmology: The ‘Timaeus’ of Plato. Indianapolis-Cambridge: Hackett Publishing.
Dillon, J. (2003). The Heirs of Plato: A Study of the Old Academy (347-274 BC). Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Dillon, J. (2012). ‘The Timaeus in the Old Academy’. In Id. The Platonic Heritage. Further Studies in the History of Platonism and Early Christianity. London: Routledge, 80–94.
Donini, P. (2010). ‘I fondamenti della fisica e la teoria delle cause in Plutarco’. In Id. Bonazzi (ed.), Commentary and Tradition, Aristotelianism, Platonism, and Post-Hellenistic Philosophy. Berlin: De Gruyter, 341–357.
Dörrie, H., Baltes, M. (1998) Der Platonismus in der Antike. Die philosophisce Lehre des Platonismus. Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt.
Ferrari, F., Baldi, L. (a cura di) (2002). Plutarco. La generazione dell’anima nel Timeo. Napoli: M. D’Auria Editore.
Ferrari, F. (2015). ‘Lucio Calveno Tauro e l’interpretazione didascalica della cosmogenesi del Timeo’. In L. Cardullo, D. Iozzia (eds.), Bellezza e Virtù. Studi in onore di Maria Barbanti. Catania: Bonanno, 307–19.
Fronterotta, F. (2012). ‘‘Principio’ del cosmo e ‘inizio’ del discorso. Una nuova ipotesi intorno all’ ‘origine’ del mondo nel Timeo platonico’. In L. Palumbo (a cura di) Λόγον διδόναι. La filosofia come esercizio del rendere ragione. Studi in onore di Giovanni Casertano. Napoli: Loffredo, 661–79.
Gosilits, P. (2018). ‘Simplicius, Syrianus and the Harmony of Ancient Philosopher’. In B. Strobel (ed.) Die Kunst Der Philosophischen Exegese Bei Den Spätantiken Platon- Und Aristoteles-Kommentatoren. Berlin: De Gruyter, 69–100.
Guldentops, G. (2005). ‘Plato’s Timaeus in Simplicius’ De Caelo. A Confrontation with Alexander’. In T. Leinkauf, C. Steel (eds.) Plato’s Timaeus and the Foundations of Cosmology in Late Antiquity, the Middle Ages and Renaissance. Leuven: Leuven University Press, 195–212.
Horky, P.S. (2013). ‘Theophrastus on Platonic and ‘Pythagorean’ Imitation’. Classical Quarterly, 686–712.
Isnardi Parente, M. (1980) Speusippo. Testimonianze e Frammenti. Napoli: Bibliopolis.
Isnardi Parente, M. (1981). Senocrate. Testimonianze e Frammenti. Napoli: Bibliopolis.
Isnardi Parente, M. (2012). Senocrate e Ermodoro. Testimonianze e Frammenti (edizione rivista e aggiornata a cura di Tiziano Dorandi). Pisa: Edizioni della Normale.
Kouremenos, T. (2005). ‘Aristotle’s argument against the parallel between the Timaeus cosmogony and geometric διαγράμματα (Cael. 279b32 – 280a2)’. Wiener Studien, 49–65.
Luna, C., Segonds, A., Endress, P. (2012). ‘Proclus de Lycie’. In R. Goulet (ed.) Dictionnaire des Philosophes Antiques. Paris: CNRS Éditions, 1564–1674.
Moraux, P. (1954) ‘Notes sur la Tradition Indirecte du ‘De Caelo’ D’Aristote’. Hermes, 145–182.
Moraux, P. (1965). Aristote. Du Ciel. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.
Moraux, P. (1967). ‘Le Parisinus graecus 1853 (ms. E) d’Aristote’. Scriptorium, 17–41.
Mueller, I. (2011). Simplicius. On Aristotle On the Heavens 1.2–3. Bristol: Bristol Classical Press.
Ronconi, F. (2012). ‘Le corpus aristotélicien du Paris. gr. 1853 et les cercles érudits à Byzance. Un cas controversé’. Studia Graeco-Arabica, 201–225.
Tarán, L. (1981). Speusippus of Athens. A Critical Study with a Collection of the Related Texts and Commentary. Leiden: Brill.
Tarrant, H. (2020). ‘One Academy? The Transition from Polemo and Crates to Arcesilaus’ Kalligas et alia (eds.). Plato’s Academy. Its Working and Its History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 200–219.
Petrucci, F.M. (2016). ‘Argumentative Strategies for Interpreting Plato’s Cosmogony: Taurus and the Issue of Literalism in Antiquity’. Phronesis, 43–59.
Petrucci, F.M. (2018). Taurus of Beirut. London: Routledge.
Petrucci, F.M., Ferrari, F. (2022). Platone, Timeo (Introduzione di F.F., testo, traduzione e note a cura di F.M.P.). Fondazione Lorenzo Valla: Mondadori.
Reydams-Schils, G. (ed.) (2003), Plato’s Timaeus as Cultural Icon. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.
Reydams-Schils, G. (2012). ‘The Academy, the Stoics and Cicero on Plato’s Timaeus’. In A.G. Long (ed.) Plato and the Stoics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sedley, D. (2002). ‘The Origins of Stoic God’. In D. Frede-A. Laks (eds.) Traditions of Theology: Hellenistic Theology, Its Background and Aftermath. Leiden-Boston-Köln: Brill, 41–83.
Sedley, D. (2021). ‘Xenocrates’ Invention of Platonism’. In M. Erler, J.E. Heßler, F.M. Petrucci (eds.), with the collaboration of M. McOsker. Authority and Authoritative Texts in the Platonist Tradition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 12–37.
Sorabji, R. (1983). Creation and the Continuum: Theories in Antiquity and the Early Middle Ages. London: Duckworth.
Steel, C. (2016). ‘Proclus’ Defence of the Timaeus against Aristotle: A Reconstruction of a Lost Polemical Treatise’. In Id., R. Sorabji (eds.) Aristotle Re-Interpreted. New Findings on Seven Hundred Years of the Ancient Commentators, 327–352.
Vlastos, G. (1995). ‘Disorderly Motion in the Timaeus’. In D.W. Graham, (ed.) Studies in Greek Philosophy. Gregory Vlastos. Vol ii: Socrates, Plato and their Tradition, Princeton-New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 247–264.
All Time | Past 365 days | Past 30 Days | |
---|---|---|---|
Abstract Views | 283 | 143 | 20 |
Full Text Views | 95 | 4 | 2 |
PDF Views & Downloads | 173 | 15 | 4 |
It is a well-established opinion in the literature that the immediate circle of Plato’s disciples maintained that the generation of the cosmos described in the Timaeus was to be understood as an illustrative, or educational metaphor. On this account, Plato’s students were the first to hold an eternalist, metaphorical reading of the generation of the world, challenged by the Peripatos. When criticising their position in the De Caelo, however, Aristotle describes Early Academic philosophers as holding the more nuanced view that the world is ‘indestructible and yet generated’ (ἄφθαρτον μὲν […] γενόμενον δέ). Is it possible to make any sense of this formulation and restore a different position for Early Academic philosophers? In this paper, I claim that the standard reading can be challenged and that there is ground to believe that Speusippus and Xenocrates held that the world is generated but everlasting. What they denied having happened in time and said should be understood as an illustrative metaphor is the transition from the absence of an order to order or, in other words, the cosmogonic process itself.
All Time | Past 365 days | Past 30 Days | |
---|---|---|---|
Abstract Views | 283 | 143 | 20 |
Full Text Views | 95 | 4 | 2 |
PDF Views & Downloads | 173 | 15 | 4 |