The Structural Injustice of Forced Migration and the Failings of Normative Theory

in Perspectives on Global Development and Technology
Restricted Access
Get Access to Full Text
Rent on DeepDyve

Have an Access Token?



Enter your access token to activate and access content online.

Please login and go to your personal user account to enter your access token.



Help

Have Institutional Access?



Access content through your institution. Any other coaching guidance?



Connect

Abstract

I propose to criticize two strands of argument—contractarian and utilitarian—that liberals have put forth in defense of economic coercion, based on the notion of justifiable paternalism. To illustrate my argument, I appeal to the example of forced labor migration, driven by the exigencies of market forces. In particular, the forced migration of a special subset of unemployed workers lacking other means of subsistence (economic refugees) cannot be redeemed paternalistically as freedom or welfare enhancing in the long run. Further, contractarian and utilitarian approaches are normatively incapable of appreciating this fact because the kinds of reasons that they adduce for justifying the long-term freedom-enhancing consequences of forced migration are not ones that would be acceptable to the migrants themselves. I conclude that only a discourse ethical approach, which mandates direct, empathetic communication between would-be migrants and members of potential host communities, captures the full range of reasons that would be acceptable to both migrants and members of these communities. These reasons—appealing both to agency-enhancing communal attachments as well as to agency-enhancing freedom of choice—fully reveals the extent to which a global capitalist system composed of relatively closed national communities coerces the world’s poorest migrants.

The Structural Injustice of Forced Migration and the Failings of Normative Theory

in Perspectives on Global Development and Technology

Sections

References

  • BaconD. Illegal people: How globalization creates immigration and criminalizes immigrants 2008 Boston Beacon Press

  • BenhabibS. The rights of others 2003 Cambridge Cambridge University Press

  • CarensJ. KymlickaW. “Aliens and citizens” The rights of minority cultures 1995 Oxford Oxford University 331 345

  • DworkinG. SartoriusR. “Paternalism: Some second thoughts” Paternalism 1983 Minneapolis University of Minnesota

  • HonnethA. The struggle for recognition: The moral grammar of social conflicts 1996 Cambridge, MA MIT Press

  • IngramD. “Immigration and social justice” Peace Studies Review 14 4 403 414

  • IngramD. “Of sweatshops and subsistence: Habermas on human rights” Ethics and Global Politics 2 3 193 217

  • IngramD. “Exceptional justice? A discourse-ethical contribution to the immigrant question” Critical Horizons 2009 10 1 1 30

  • KayeJ. Moving millions: How coyote capitalism fuels global I\immigration 2010 Hoboken, N.J. Wiley & Sons

  • NozickN. Anarchy state and utopia 1973 New York Basic Books

  • PoggeT. World poverty and human rights: Cosmopolitan responsibilities and reforms 2002 Cambridge Polity Press

  • RawlsJ. Justice as fairness: A restatement 2001 Cambridge Cambridge University

  • SchweickartD. “Global poverty: Alternative perspectives on what we should do and why” Journal of Social Philosophy 2008 39 4 471 491

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • SterbaJ. “From liberty to welfare” Social Theory and Practice 1985 11 3 285 305

  • WalzerM. Spheres of justice: A defense of pluralism and equality 1983 New York Basic Books

  • WalzerM. “The communitarian critique of liberalism” Political Theory 1990 18 1 6 23

  • YoungI. M. “Responsibility, social connectedness, and global labor justice” Global Challenges: war self-Determination and responsibility for justice 2007 Cambridge Polity Press 159 186

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • 2

    Gerald Dworkin (1983) notes that “hard” cases of paternalism—in which the rational competence of the coerced agent is not impugned by ignorance or cognitive and emotional deficiencies—are difficult to justify precisely because of the voluntary nature of the action that is suppressed. In cases such as these—where the nature of the act itself (its irreversibility as in the case of suicide or its severe risk to the health of the actor) and not the competency of the agent is what is at issue—the coercer might justly appeal non-paternalistically to the potential harm caused to society. For example a society where persons are legally entitled to sell themselves into slavery voluntarily imposes unconscionable burdens on those who would be required to return run-away slaves. But perhaps voluntary acts like these can also be forbidden on “soft” paternalistic grounds as being contrary to the “good” of the agent (here we assume something like the divided-will theory noted above in which an agent’s failure to appreciate fully what is really in her best interest impugns the fully voluntary nature of her act).

  • 3

    D. Schweickart (2008) argues (with Marx) that the need to maintain labor discipline and heighten profitability by lowering wage costs through labor-saving technology that is endemic to capitalism leads to chronic domestic crises of un- and underemployment (and corresponding overproduction) which are solved by opening up new markets abroad. The dumping of cheaply produced goods in developing economies and the corresponding replacement of sustainable labor-intensive domestic agriculture with high-tech export-oriented agribusiness reinforces and exacerbates poverty and unemployment in these economies.

Index Card

Content Metrics

Content Metrics

All Time Past Year Past 30 Days
Abstract Views 34 32 4
Full Text Views 54 54 1
PDF Downloads 7 7 2
EPUB Downloads 0 0 0