Pseudo-Plato on Names

in Phronesis
Restricted Access
Get Access to Full Text
Rent on DeepDyve

Have an Access Token?



Enter your access token to activate and access content online.

Please login and go to your personal user account to enter your access token.



Help

Have Institutional Access?



Access content through your institution. Any other coaching guidance?



Connect

The pseudo-Platonic Definitions seems to ascribe to ὄνοµα, ‘name’, the function of signifying two kinds of predicate. This is problematic, and I propose an emendation of the text, arguing that a definition of ῥῆµα, ‘verb’, has fallen out.

Phronesis

A Journal for Ancient Philosophy

Sections

References

AckrillJ. L., Aristotle: Categories and De Interpretatione, (Oxford 1963).

AdamR., '‘Über eine unter Platos Namen erhaltene Sammlung von Definitionen’' (1925) 80 Philologus: 366-76.

AdemolloF., '‘Names, Verbs, and Sentences in Ancient Greek Philosophy’', in M. Cameron and R. Stainton (eds), Linguistic Content: New Essays on the History of Philosophy of Language, (Oxford 2015) 33-54.

F. Aronadio (ed), Dialoghi spuri di Platone, (Turin 2008).

J. Barnes (ed), The Complete Works of Aristotle. The Revised Oxford Translation, (Princeton 1984) 2 vols.

BarnesJ., Aristotle: Posterior Analytics, (Oxford 1993).

BarnesJ., Porphyry: Introduction, (Oxford 2003).

BarnesJ., Truth, Etc., (Oxford 2007).

BrissonL., Écrits attribués à Platon, (Paris 2014).

I. Burnet (ed), Platonis Opera, (Oxford 1907).

CarliniA., Studi sulla tradizione antica e medievale del Fedone., (Rome 1972).

ChiaradonnaR., '‘La teoria dell’individuo in Porfirio e l’ἰδίως ποιόν stoico’' (2000) 21 Elenchos: 303-31.

CodeA., '‘Aristotle: Essence and Accident’', in R. E. Grandy and R. Warner (eds), Philosophical Grounds of Rationality, (Oxford 1986) 411-39.

CornariusJ., Platonis Atheniensis, philosophi summi ac penitus divini opera, quae ad nos extant, omnia, (Basel 1561).

FicinoM., Divus Plato, (Venice 1491).

FredeM., '‘Aristotle on Nouns and Verbs in De Interpretatione’' () unpublished.

HutchinsonD. H., 'Definitions', in J. M. Cooper (ed), Plato: Complete Works, (Indianapolis / Cambridge 1997) 1677-1686.

IngenkampH.-G., Untersuchungen zu den pseudoplatonischen Definitionen, (Wiesbaden 1967).

LuzzattoM. J., '‘Emendare Platone nell’antichità. Il caso del Vaticanus gr. 1’' (2008) 68 Quaderni di storia: 29-85.

MenchelliM., '‘Il Vaticano Palatino gr. 173 di Platone e il Parigino gr. 1665 di Diodoro’' (1991) 12 Bollettino dei Classici: 93-117.

MenchelliM., '‘Osservazioni sulle forme della lettura di Platone tra gli eruditi bizantini e sulla trasmissione del testo della Appendix degli apocrifi del corpus platonico (con note paleografiche sul Vat. Pal. gr. 173 e sul Vat. Pal. gr. 174)’', in J. Signes Codoñer and I. Pérez Martín (eds), Textual Transmission in Byzantium: Between Textual Criticism and Quellenforschung, (Turnhout 2014) 199-230.

MennS., '‘The Stoic Theory of Categories’' (1999) 17 Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy: 215-47.

L. Minio-Paluello (ed), Aristotelis Categoriae et Liber De Interpretatione, (Oxford 1949).

MontanariE., La sezione linguistica del Peri hermeneias di Aristotele., (Florence 1988) 2 vols.

PetrucciF. M.AronadioF.TulliM.Petrucci, '‘Note critiche: tradizione del testo’', in [Plato]: Epinomis, (Naples 2013) 179-206.

PetrucciF. M., '‘Il Vat. gr. 1029 di Platone: struttura codicologica e dinamiche di allestimento’' (2014) 12 Segno e Testo: 333-69.

PostL. A., The Vatican Plato and Its Relations, (Middletown, Conn. 1934).

RossW. D., Aristotle’s Physics, (Oxford 1936).

C. E. C. Schneider (ed), Platonis Opera, (Paris 1900).

SedleyD. N., '‘Aristote et la signification’' (2004) 4 Philosophie Antique: 5-25.

SouilhéJ., Platon, Oeuvres completes. Vol. xiii.3: Dialogues apocryphes, (Paris 1930).

G. Uhlig (ed), Dionysii Thracis ars grammatica. Grammatici Graeci, (Leipzig 1883).

WaitzT., Aristotelis Organon Graece, (Leipzig 1844).

WedinM. V., Aristotle’s Theory of Substance. The Categories and Metaphysics Zeta, (Oxford 2000).

WeidemannH., Aristoteles: Peri hermeneias, (Berlin 2014a).

H. Weidemann (ed), Aristoteles, De interpretatione., (Berlin / Boston 2014b).

WhitakerC. W. A., Aristotle’s De interpretatione: Contradiction and Dialectic, (Oxford 1996).

2

On A, see Carlini 1972, 145-6, 160; Post 1934, 6-8; Petrucci 2013, 177-82. On P, see Post 1934, 4, 46-7, 74-5; Carlini 1972, 173-5; Menchelli 1991; 2014, 172-7. On O, see Post 1934, 8-14; Luzzatto 2008; Petrucci 2013, 182-201. On L, see Post 1934, 69 (where it is initially introduced as δ). On V, see Post 1934, 78 (where it is labelled ‘R’) and Petrucci 2014.

5

Post 1934, 4 regards P (which contains excerpts from the Laws) as ‘Too freely paraphrased to be useful. Independent of A and O.’

8

See Whitaker 1996, 5-7; Sedley 2004.

12

Cf. Cornarius 1561: quidvis quod non per seipsum dicitur.

13

Tr. Barnes 1993, modified.

14

Hutchinson’s (1997) translation of παντὸς τοῦ µὴ καθ᾿ ἑαυτὸ λεγοµένου as ‘everything which is not said of a thing in its own right’ invokes another use of ‘by itself’, according to which for X to hold of Y ‘by itself’ is for X to be essentially predicated of Y (see APo. 1.4, 73a34-7, Metaph. Δ.18, 1022a27-9). This must be understood in the context of Hutchinson’s translation of τοῦ … κατὰ τῆς οὐσίας κατηγορουµένου as ‘what is predicated in the essence’: the outcome is that a name signifies either essential or non-essential predicates. Apart from the illegitimacy, which I pointed out above, of translating κατὰ τῆς οὐσίας as ‘in the essence’, this outcome is open to two of the criticisms I advance in the text below: the function of ‘everything’ is unclear; and it is very odd that a name should be defined only as an expression for predicates of various kinds, to the exclusion of proper names for substances.

19

See Code 1986, 419 and n. 11.

20

On the Stoic definitions, see Brunschwig 1984. Apollonius Dyscolus seems to have endorsed a modified version, according to which a name is a part of speech ἑκάστου τῶν ὑποκειµένων σωµάτων ἢ πραγµάτων κοινὴν ἢ ἰδίαν ποιότητα ἀπονέµον, literally ‘which assigns a common or peculiar quality of each of the underlying bodies or objects’ (Uhlig 1883, pp. lxxxiii-lxxxiv). See De pron. [Gramm. Gr. ii.1.1], 105.18-19 Schneider; Synt. [Gramm. Gr. ii.2], 142.1-4, 155.45 Uhlig; Priscian, Inst. [Gramm. Lat. ii], 56.28-57.1 Hertz; Partitiones [Gramm. Lat. iii], 2.481.2-4 Keil; Schol. in Dion. Thr. [Gramm. Gr. i.3], 524.8-12 Hilgard (cf. 358.29-32).

21

Tr. Barnes 2003. See Barnes 2003, 78-9, 325-7 on individual predicates in Porphyry and Aristotle. A difficulty in connection with Porphyry is that it is unclear whether his predicates are meant to be expressions or entities: see Barnes 2003, 68-70.

24

Translation after Ackrill 1963.

28

See Ackrill 1963, 118-9; Whitaker 1996, 58; Weidemann 2014a, 173-4; Frede unpublished.

32

Ackrill 1963, 76. Whether this is correct as an interpretation of Aristotle is a question that need not concern us here.

34

Tr. after Barnes 2007, 103.

Information

Content Metrics

Content Metrics

All Time Past Year Past 30 Days
Abstract Views 17 17 11
Full Text Views 8 8 8
PDF Downloads 3 3 3
EPUB Downloads 2 2 2