I argue that, for Aristotle, virtue of character is a state of the non-rational part of the soul that makes one prone to making and acting on decisions in virtue of that part’s standing in the right relation to (correct) reason, namely, a relation that qualifies the agent as a true self-lover. In effect, this central feature of virtue of character is nothing else than love of practical wisdom. As I argue, it not only explains how reason can hold direct authority over non-rational desires but also why Aristotle defines virtue of character as hexis prohairetikē.
Purchase
Buy instant access (PDF download and unlimited online access):
Institutional Login
Log in with Open Athens, Shibboleth, or your institutional credentials
Personal login
Log in with your brill.com account
Allan, D. J. (1953), ‘Aristotle’s Account of the Origin of Moral Principles’, Actes du XIe Congrès Internationale de Philosophie 12: 120-127. [Reprinted in J. Barnes, M. Schofield and R. Sorabji (eds.) Essays on Aristotle vol. 2 (London, 1977), 72-8.]
Angioni, L. (2009), ‘Notas sobre a definição de virtude moral em Aristóteles (EN 1106b36-1107a2)’, Journal of Ancient Philosophy 3: 1-17.
Annas, J. (1993), The Morality of Happiness. Oxford.
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1965), ‘Thought and Action in Aristotle’ in R. Bambrough (ed.), New Essays on Plato and Aristotle (London), 143-158.
Aubenque, P. (1965), ‘La prudence aristotélicienne porte-t-elle sur la fin ou sur les moyens?’, Revue des Études Grecques 78: 40-51.
Bobonich, C. (1991), ‘Persuasion, Compulsion and Freedom in Plato’s Laws’, The Classical Quaterly 41: 365-388.
Bodeüs, R. (2004), Aristote. Éthique à Nicomaque. Paris.
Broadie, S. (1991), Ethics with Aristotle. Oxford.
Burnyeat, M. F. (1980), ‘Aristotle on Learning to be Good’ in A. O. Rorty (ed.), Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics (Berkeley), 69-92.
Cagnoli Fiecconi, E. (2018), ‘Aristotle on the Structure of Akratic Action’, Phronesis 63: 229-256.
Caston, V. (2002), ‘Aristotle on consciousness’, Mind 111: 751-815.
Charles, D. (1984), Aristotle’s Theory of Action. Ithaca.
Charles, D. (2015), ‘Aristotle on Practical and Theoretical Knowledge’, in D. Henry and K. M. Nielsen, Bridging the Gap Between Aristotle’s Science and Ethics (Cambridge), 71-93.
Coope, U. (2012), ‘Why does Aristotle think that ethical virtue is required for practical wisdom?’, Phronesis 57: 142-163.
Cooper, J. (1975), Reason and Human Good in Aristotle. Cambridge.
Cooper, J. (1999 a), Reason and Emotion: Essays on Ancient Moral Psychology and Ethical Theory. Princeton.
Cooper, J. (1999b), ‘Some Remarks on Aristotle’s Moral Psychology’ in Cooper 1999a, 237-252.
Cooper, J. (1999c), ‘An Aristotelian Theory of the Emotions’ in Cooper 1999a, 406-445.
Corcilius, K. (2008), Streben und Bewegen: Aristoteles’ Theorie der animalischen Ortsbewegung. Berlin.
Corcilius, K. (2011), ‘Aristotle’s Definition of Non-Rational Pleasure and Pain and Desire’ in J. Miller (ed.), Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: A Critical Guide (Cambridge), 117-143.
Curzer, H. J. (2002), ‘Aristotle’s Painful Path to Virtue’, Journal of the History of Philosophy 40: 141-162.
Dahl, N. O. (1984), Practical Reason, Aristotle, and Weakness of Will. Minneapolis.
Fortenbaugh, W. W. (2002), Aristotle on Emotion. 2nd edn. London.
Gourinat, J.-B. (2002), ‘Délibération et choix dans l’éthique aristotélicienne’ in G. Aubry and G. Romeyer-Dherbey (eds.), L’excellence de la vie: sur l’ “Éthique à Nicomaque” et l’ “Éthique à Eudème” d’Aristote (Paris), 95-124.
Gottlieb, P. (2009), The Virtue of Aristotle’s Ethics. Cambridge.
Grönroos, G. (2007), ‘Listening to Reason in Aristotle’s Moral Psychology’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 32: 251-271.
Grönroos, G. (2015), ‘Wish, Motivation and the Human Good in Aristotle’, Phronesis 60: 60-87.
Hutchinson, D. S. (1986), The Virtues of Aristotle. London.
Irwin, T. H. (1975), ‘Aristotle on Reason, Desire, and Virtue’, Journal of Philosophy 72: 567-578.
Irwin, T. H. (2007), The Development of Ethics: A Historical and Critical Study. Oxford.
Kennett J. and M. Smith (1996), ‘Frog and Toad Lose Control’, Analysis 56: 63-73.
Kosman, L. A. (1980), ‘Being Properly Affected: Virtues and Feelings in Aristotle’s Ethics’ in A. O. Rorty (ed.), Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics (Berkeley), 103-116.
Lawrence, G. (2011), ‘Acquiring Character: Becoming Grown-Up’ in M. Pakaluk and G. Pearson (eds.), Moral Psychology and Human Action in Aristotle (Oxford), 233-283.
Liu, W. (2012), ‘Creating Character: Aristotle on Habituation, the Cognitive Power of Emotion, and the Role of Prudence’, Frontiers of Philosophy in China 7: 533-549.
Liu, W. (2016), ‘Aristotle on Prohairesis’, Labyrinth 18: 50-74.
Loening, R. (1903), Die Zurechnungslehre des Aristoteles. Jena.
Lorenz, H. (2006), The Brute Within: Appetitive Desire in Plato and Aristotle. Oxford.
Lorenz, H. (2009), ‘Virtue of Character in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 37: 177-212.
McDowell, J. (1998), ‘Some Issues in Aristotle’s Moral Psychology’ in S. Everson (ed.), Ethics (Cambridge), 107-128.
Mele, A. (1981), ‘Choice and Virtue in the Nicomachean Ethics’, Journal of the History of Philosophy 19: 405-423.
Mele, A. (1984), ‘Aristotle’s Wish’, Journal of the History of Philosophy 22: 139-156.
Mele, A. (1997), ‘Underestimating Self-control: Kennett and Smith on Frog and Toad’, Analysis 57: 119-123.
Morel, P.-M. (2017), ‘Vertu éthique et rationalité pratique chez Aristote. Note sur la notion d’hexis proairetikê’, Philonsorbonne 11: 141-153.
Moss, J. (2012), Aristotle on the Apparent Good: Perception, Phantasia, Thought, and Desire. Oxford.
Moss, J. (2014), ‘Right Reason in Plato and Aristotle: On the Meaning of Logos’, Phronesis 59: 181-230.
Müller, A. W. (1982), Praktisches Folgern und Selbsgestaltung nach Aristoteles. Freiburg / München.
Müller, J. (2015), ‘Aristotle on Vice’, British Journal for the History of Philosophy 23: 459-477.
Müller, J. (2016), ‘What Aristotelian Decisions Cannot Be’, Ancient Philosophy 36: 173-195.
Natali, C. (1988), ‘Les fins et les moyens: un puzzle aristotélicien’, Revue de Philosophie Ancienne 6: 107-146.
Natali, C. (2001), The Wisdom of Aristotle. Albany.
Natali, C. (2016), ‘La vertu selon Aristote’ in E. Berti and M. Crubellier (eds.), Lire Aristote (Paris), 61-175.
Nielsen, K. M. (2017), ‘Vice in the Nicomachean Ethics’, Phronesis 62: 1-25.
Pakaluk, M. (2005), Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: An Introduction. Cambridge.
Price, A. W. (2011 a), Virtue and Reason in Plato and Aristotle. Oxford.
Price, A. W. (2011 b), ‘Aristotle on the Ends of Deliberation’ in M. Pakaluk and G. Pearson (eds.), Moral Psychology and Human Action in Aristotle (Oxford), 135-158.
Rapp C. (2002), Aristoteles: Rhetorik. Berlin.
Reeve, C. D. C. (2013), Aristotle on Practical Wisdom. Cambridge, Mass.
Segvić, H. (2009), ‘Deliberation and Choice in Aristotle’ in From Protagoras to Aristotle: Essays in Ancient Moral Philosophy (Princeton), 144-171.
Sorabji, R. (1980), ‘Aristotle on the Role of Intellect in Virtue’ in A. O. Rorty (ed.) Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics (Berkeley), 201-219.
Sripada, C. (2014), ‘How is Willpower Possible? The Puzzle of Synchronic Self-control and the Divided Mind’, Noûs 48: 41-74.
Smith, A. D. (1996), ‘Character and Intellect in Aristotle’s Ethics’, Phronesis 41: 56-74.
Viano, C. (2002), ‘Passions, désirs et plaisirs de rivalité chez Aristote’ in G. Aubry (ed.) L’Excellence de la vie. Sur l’Ethique à Nicomaque et l’Ethique à Eudème d’Aristote (Paris), 237-252.
Walter, J. (1874), Die Lehre von der praktischen Vernunft in der griechischen Philosophie. Jena.
Warren, J. (2014), The Pleasures of Reason in Plato, Aristotle, and the Hellenistic Hedonists. Cambridge.
Wiggins, D. (1980), ‘Deliberation and Practical Reason’ in A. O. Rorty (ed.), Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics (Berkeley), 221-240.
Williams, B. (1981), ‘Utilitarianism and Moral Self-Indulgence’ in his Moral Luck (Cambridge), 40-53.
Winters, J., Christoff, K. and Gorzalka, B. B. (2009), ‘Conscious Regulation of Sexual Arousal in Men’ The Journal of Sex Research 46: 330-343.
All Time | Past 365 days | Past 30 Days | |
---|---|---|---|
Abstract Views | 2510 | 216 | 41 |
Full Text Views | 535 | 18 | 1 |
PDF Views & Downloads | 595 | 45 | 2 |
I argue that, for Aristotle, virtue of character is a state of the non-rational part of the soul that makes one prone to making and acting on decisions in virtue of that part’s standing in the right relation to (correct) reason, namely, a relation that qualifies the agent as a true self-lover. In effect, this central feature of virtue of character is nothing else than love of practical wisdom. As I argue, it not only explains how reason can hold direct authority over non-rational desires but also why Aristotle defines virtue of character as hexis prohairetikē.
All Time | Past 365 days | Past 30 Days | |
---|---|---|---|
Abstract Views | 2510 | 216 | 41 |
Full Text Views | 535 | 18 | 1 |
PDF Views & Downloads | 595 | 45 | 2 |