Many political theorists and statesmen argue that the U.S. Government’s military involvement in Afghanistan and Iraq is wrong. They also argue that we ought to support our troops who are fighting in those areas. This apparently contradictory position is made tenable by the underlying claim that combatants are not responsible for their country’s decision to go to war; they are only responsible for acting in accordance with the rules of warfare. For example, Private Johnson cannot influence U.S. policy. All he can do is follow the orders passed down by his superiors, refrain from targeting noncombatants, and refrain from breaking other widely accepted rules of jus in bello (justice in warfare). So long as Johnson follows his orders, does not target noncombatants, and does not break the other statutes of jus in bello—such as proportionality, necessity, etc.—he has acted justly; the fact that he is persecuting an arguably unjust war does not change the moral status of his wartime actions.
At least, so say traditional just war theorists; as Michael Walzer argues in his canonical Just and Unjust Wars, the justice of going to war and acting justly in war are both conceptually and practically distinct.1 We can, and in fact do, distinguish between holding a country’s military and political leaders accountable for persecuting unjust wars, and holding ordinary soldiers accountable for their actions in such wars. As Jeff McMahan puts it, “most people in virtually all cultures at all times believed that a person does not act wrongly by fighting in an unjust war, provided that he obeys the principles governing the conduct of war.”2
McMahan, having summarized the traditional view thusly, goes on in his Killing in War to argue against that claim. Combatants, he claims, only act justly when they fight on the right, or just, side of a war. Combatants fighting on the wrong, or unjust, side of a war do not act justly even if they follow their orders, do not target noncombatants, and do not break any of the other jus in bello statutes. In today’s information-saturated world, these combatants have the resources to know that the war they are persecuting is unjust. Because they either do know better or should have known better, they act wrongly
While this conclusion is in itself intriguing and worth further discussion, McMahan does not stop there; rather, he goes on to argue that, although it is true that combatants who fight unjust wars act wrongly, we should not seek to publicize or legalize this fact. He claims to have uncovered the “deep morality” of war, but concludes that we should not integrate this deep morality into our military and international public policies and laws, because of the possible negative consequences of doing so. In effect, McMahan is arguing that just war theory ought to be entirely divorced from military and international public policy and law. Considering that the just war tradition historically has had quite a large impact on both military and international public policy and law, this is a very unique move, and one that has significant implications for normative political philosophy more generally. I first question—on the basis of feminist epistemology—whether McMahan is right to think that publicizing and legalizing the deep morality of war will have the negative consequences that he claims, and then I argue that he is wrong to think that we ought to de-couple the theory of just war from the practice of military and international public policy and law. To do so, after all, would be to give up entirely on one of the just war tradition’s stated projects: that of preventing morally unnecessary wars.4
1 McMahan’s Argument for Engaging in a Cover-Up
The suggestion that the received just war tradition is incorrect about the distinction between jus ad bellum and jus in bello is an intriguing one, and has been taken up by a number of theorists. Such theorists, known as revisionists, argue for a massive shift in how war is understood at the moral level; they argue, roughly, that there is no moral difference between everyday life and war,
McMahan’s argument for this claim is that publicizing this fact, and changing military policy and law in response to it, would have widespread negative consequences. He argues that combatants have a tendency to believe that their side is the just one—a belief that military commanders and political leaders, among others, foster—and that this belief, in conjunction with the belief that combatants on the unjust side of a war act wrongly by engaging in fighting at all, would lead combatants to treat enemy combatants more like rogue criminals or terrorists than like fellow combatants to whom certain rules and restrictions apply. In particular, McMahan worries that, if the laws of war were to come to reflect his conclusions regarding the morality of war, then the torture of enemy combatants would become more acceptable, the protections traditionally offered to pows would be eroded, and the use of cruel and unusual weapons of war, such as biological and chemical weaponry, and perhaps nuclear weapons themselves, would gradually become allowed, if not commonplace.7 In short, McMahan worries that codifying his moral view in military policy and domestic and international law would lead to the in-practice relaxation of current restrictions that keep wartime fighting from being even worse, and more vicious, than it currently is.
In addition, McMahan’s moral view entails that non-combatants, or civilians, on the unjust side of the war are also, in some cases, liable to defensive attack by just combatants, because they are sometimes at least partially morally responsible for the objectively unjustified harms that are suffered by both the
Put broadly, McMahan worries that publicizing and legalizing the truth about the moral asymmetry of warfare will lead combatants on both sides to cast off the constraints of the jus in bello tradition, which currently operate both policy-wise and legally to limit the harming and killing of enemy combatants and enemy civilians. From a straightforwardly consequentialist point of view, this would be extremely bad, because it would make it more likely that a much higher number of people, including many who are not liable to be harmed or killed, would be harmed and killed in war. As McMahan puts it, it “would be worse [to have] an in bello law that would be as asymmetric as in bello morality. … [such a law] would be exploited by the unjust and inevitably abused by the just, leading to greater violence, and in particular to more and worse violations of the rights of the innocent, than a [symmetric] law that prohibits these forms of actions to all.”10 So, given the present epistemic circumstances of combatants (that is, that their knowledge of the relevant facts is limited, that they are likely to be biased towards believing their commanders, and that they are usually disinclined to seek out the truth of the matter), when considering what
In addition to the direct effect that it would have on combatants and their wartime actions, McMahan also worries about the effect that publicizing and legalizing his revisionist conclusions would have on the already-difficult transition from war to peace. Traditionally, enemy combatants—except in cases where they have broken standard, traditional rules of jus in bello—are not put on trial after wars, because they are not regarded either by international law or by enemy militaries or political leaders as having acted unjustly merely by fighting. This legal policy, in addition to being morally correct according to the traditionalist view of war, has a number of good consequences according to McMahan: combatants are more willing to fight, and more importantly, are more willing to surrender, because they believe that they will not be penalized or punished merely for the act of fighting, and that they will be allowed to return to civilian life without censure after the war is over. Revising the laws of war to reflect the moral asymmetry of combatants would almost demand that those combatants who are determined (perhaps by an independent tribunal, such as the International Criminal Court (icc)) to have been unjust combatants be censured, penalized, or punished for the act of fighting.12 McMahan worries that this will lead combatants to be both less willing to fight in all cases—for fear of fighting on the wrong side and so being punished afterwards—and less willing to surrender—for fear that surrender will simply lead to a humiliating punishment, censure, or penalization, regardless of the actual morality of their actions. Again, the worry is that the negative consequences of changing the laws of war to match the morality of war will vastly outweigh the positive consequences of doing so. As McMahan concludes, “In current conditions, the law of war cannot aspire to congruence with the morality of war. It must be formulated with a pragmatic concern for the consequences of its implementation.”13
2 Dire Predictions: a Feminist History and Explanation
Of course, consequences do matter; so, McMahan is right to consider the consequences of codifying his moral conclusions in military policy and law.
Consider first the passage of the 19th Amendment to the United States Constitution. The 19th amendment states that “The right of citizens of the United States to vote shall not be denied or abridged by the United States or by any State on account of sex.”15 The initial proposal, and the lead-up to the passage, of the 19th amendment is a good test case for our purposes, because it shares three relevant similarities with the case from the just war tradition described above: first, it is about bringing the law into line with morality,16 and second, it is about giving formal power and discretion to a large group of people who previously lacked such power and discretion. And third, although most, if not all, people would agree now, if asked, that the good consequences of the 19th amendment far outweigh the negative ones, when the amendment was first proposed, it was widely denigrated and opposed for fear of its bad consequences.
Critics worried that the amendment, if passed, would destroy society in a number of ways. In particular, they argued that it would be bad for women, men, and children, would destroy the institution of the family, and would destroy the overall American social order. The National Association Opposed to
Much like McMahan’s argument above, the formal arguments against legalizing and implementing women’s suffrage from anti-suffrage groups claimed that it would harm women and men (the combatants, in our analogy), children, the institution of the family, and the economy (all innocent civilians, or bystanders, in our analogy), and that the resultant political structure would lead to worse outcomes for all citizens (in much the same way that legalizing asymmetric jus in bello laws would lead combatants to make worse choices overall). Less systematically but still importantly, prominent individuals spoke out against women’s suffrage, as well. William Taft argued that the “enfranchisement of women would increase the proportion of the hysterical element of the electorate to such a degree as to be injurious to the public welfare.”20 Other anti-suffragists, also drawing on biological views of women and womanhood, argued that “female enfranchisement would sexualize politics and unsex women, confusing the proper boundaries of masculine and feminine, public and private, domestic and political, by which the natural complementarity of a harmonious social order was maintained.”21 In other words, because of what women are like, letting them get a chance at the polls would harm, or even destroy, society. Again, this mirrors McMahan’s argument above that, because of
Of course, these dire predictions did not come to pass; women have had the vote for nearly a hundred years in the United States, and nuclear families, the economy, and society as a whole are still present and operating. While there have been a number of cultural and political changes in the intervening years, women and men still manage to cooperate socially, politically, and professionally, and have loving relationships (of all kinds) interpersonally. The anti-suffragists’ fears of societal and political collapse, to put it simply, were unfounded. Still, this is not to say that those fears are inexplicable; people often fear and thus vilify change, especially large-scale political and legal change. However, I contend that there is more behind the anti-suffragists’ arguments than a simple fear of change. Following Alison Jaggar, Lorraine Code, and others, I argue that anti-suffragists, or at least their arguments, were epistemically biased in particular ways, and so it is not surprising that they had negative intuitions, and thus made particular knowledge claims, about the likely consequences of the passage of the nineteenth amendment.
Feminist epistemology seeks to acknowledge and understand “the ways knowledge is embodied, emotional, socially situated, and informed by specific experiences and goals. …[F]eminist epistemologies focus on the social and historical circumstances that determine knowledge in particular contexts, and on the relationships between knowledge production and forms of power.”22 The overall point is that often what passes for objective knowledge and reasoning is in fact subjective and biased in various ways, in that it is at the very least influenced, and at the very most determined, by the personal, social, and political position and circumstances of the knower/reasoner. It is possible to read feminist epistemology in a more or less radical tone: there are important debates about whether objective knowledge is impossible because no one can completely overcome their own standpoint,23 or whether such knowledge is possible, albeit very difficult,24 or whether such knowledge is plausible, if a bit
As Alison Jaggar persuasively argues, western philosophy, and western society more generally, understands reason in opposition to emotion. Reason is associated with men and male competence, while emotion is linked to women and feminine appetites. As Jaggar puts it,
Although there is no reason to suppose that the thoughts and actions of women are any more influenced by emotion than the thoughts and actions of men, the stereotypes of cool men and emotional women continue to flourish…[this myth] functions to bolster the epistemic authority of the currently dominant groups, composed largely of white men, and to discredit the observations and claims of the currently subordinate groups including, of course, the observations and claims of many people of color and women. The more forcefully and vehemently the latter groups express their observations and claims, the more emotional they appear and so the more easily they are discredited.26
Women have been historically, and in many ways still are, viewed as irrational and hysterical, and as constitutionally unable to make reasonable, rational, informed decisions. (This is true to the extent that, when women are seen to be making reasonable, rational, informed decisions, they are often either praised as an “honorary man,” as “a member of the boy’s club,” or are denigrated as “cold,” “unfeeling,” or as “not a real woman.”) Given this epistemic bias against women—women-as-irrational-and-hysterical—it is unsurprising that
Following in this vein, Lorraine Code argues that women, as a group, are often viewed as objects of study rather than knowers in their own right. As she puts it, “women—and other ‘others’—are produced as objects of knowledge by S-knows-that-p epistemologies and the philosophies of science/social science that they inform.”28 Rather than being regarded as subjects who acquire knowledge, women have been viewed, both in western philosophy and in western science and social science, as objects to be known about. And as objects, women’s subjectivity is erased and they are assumed to have “interchangeable, observable features.”29 In light of this epistemological view of women—women-as-interchangeable-non-knowers—the anti-suffragist claims that women would simply double their husband’s vote, and that women having the vote would be both offensive to men’s sensibilities and straightforwardly harmful to men and children, make sense. It is important to note again that these claims about women are both false and pernicious; but given prominent sexist epistemic biases, they are perfectly understandable. As Alison Bailey and Chris Cuomo point out, “oppressive power relations are often reinforced by epistemological theories and methods.”30 Taking it for granted that early 20th century America was a culture of male dominance and female subordination (among many other relations of dominance and subordination),31 it is not surprising, and in fact is to be expected, that there were strong epistemic biases against women, and that these biases influenced social and political thought and action.
Ultimately, the dire political and social predictions of anti-suffragists, (to the extent that they believed what they were saying and writing), were the direct result of their epistemic biases against women. Because women were viewed as emotional, hysterical, non-knowers, the conclusion drawn was that
3 McMahan and Epistemic Bias
As we have seen, the anti-suffragists’ fears and predictions were not founded on sociological or psychological or historical data, but on a strong set of sexist epistemic biases. Analogously, McMahan’s dire predictions about the consequences of legalizing his moral conclusions regarding jus in bello can be traced to classist epistemic biases. Combatants are, after all, by-and-large members of the lower classes.33 This is not to say that McMahan consciously has such biases; but it is to suggest that, absent any other firm data-driven foundation for his consequentialist conclusions, epistemic bias may well be playing a (conscious or unconscious) role in his argument. I thus follow the general feminist strategy of being suspicious whenever theorists make large claims about what groups of people, in general, are likely to do.34
Recall that McMahan argues that combatants, absent existing symmetric laws of war that keep them in check, will turn into murderers; they will “exploit” or “inevitably abuse” asymmetric laws of war (that is, laws that match what McMahan considers to be the correct moral view of war), leading to greater, and unjustified, violence against both enemy combatants and enemy
But we should be wary of these claims about the epistemic position of combatants. At first glance, it reads as a strongly paternalistic argument: combatants don’t have the intellectual capacities to question what they are told (they cannot, or are highly unlikely to be able to, distinguish between propaganda and the truth), and so we must lie to them via the law and public policies (we must maintain the currently-existing symmetric laws of war), for their own good (so that combatants on both sides do not cast off the practical restraints that the “moral equality of combatants” legal doctrine places on them). This matches closely with well-known epistemic biases against members of the lower classes, that they are “too stupid” to grasp the truth, and so elites ought to lie to them, for their own good. Such a bias can be seen as far back as Plato’s infamous myth of the metals.37 Plato claims that this myth protects the lower classes from having to grapple with philosophical matters that would only confuse them. Because the lower classes are not ruled by reason, they ought not be told the truth, because they are likely to misunderstand and mis-apply it.38 More recently, Joanna Kadi persuasively argues that our entire society
McMahan is undoubtedly correct that the fog of war makes it difficult for combatants to determine the right course of action. However, as we saw above, he moves from this claim to the conclusion that, given asymmetric laws of war, combatants will simply assume that all enemy combatants and civilians are liable to defensive attack, and will act accordingly. But it is not clear that combatants are never able to make fine-grained moral distinctions in war: there is both historical and contemporary evidence that combatants can, and often do, make complex moral judgments during military campaigns.42 To suggest otherwise sounds similar to another epistemic bias commonly employed against
McMahan also contends that asymmetric jus in bello laws would have negative consequences on the transition from war to peace. Combatants will either refuse to fight or, more importantly, refuse to surrender, for fear of being punished after the war for fighting in it. Interestingly, this worry of McMahan’s is in tension with his overall view; he should, we might think, want combatants to be more unwilling to fight, given both the likelihood that their side is unjust, and the general trend of just war theorists to want to eliminate most, if not all, wars.45 So why does he worry about the unwillingness of combatants here? Presumably, because he worries that they will refuse to fight and surrender in all wars because of their fear of punishment, not simply the unjust ones, and thus will fail to do what they morally ought to do. But why think combatants’ fears will stop them from surrendering? This strand of argumentation closely matches an often-invoked classist epistemic bias, that the poor are “bullheaded,” that they are stubborn and unable to give up particular ideas, propositions, projects, or battles. (To see this bias, consider the many op-eds claiming that there is no point in trying to convince poor white voters to change their minds, because they have picked their position, and will stick to it forever,
As we have seen, epistemic biases tend to discourage giving groups of people formal power and discretion who previously lacked such power and discretion, even when morality supports doing so. Such epistemic biases do this by operating as hidden premises in arguments that conclude that the consequences of providing such power and discretion would be disastrous for all concerned. And this is precisely what we see in McMahan’s argument; he concludes that we ought not legally provide combatants with formal power and discretion by passing and implementing asymmetric laws of war, even though he argues that the morality of war is asymmetric, for fear of the dire consequences of such a legal change. Whether McMahan himself is consciously epistemically biased or not, there are predictable classist epistemic biases embedded as hidden premises in his argument, ones that lead it partially, if not fully, astray.
4 Morality and the Law
But perhaps this line of reasoning is mistaken, and McMahan’s argument for de-coupling the morality of war from the law of war is not infected with (conscious or unconscious) epistemic biases. However, even if he is correct that changing the laws of war will have the negative effects that he claims, I contend that we still should be wary of accepting his conclusion that we ought not incorporate the morality of war into our military and international public policies and laws. One of the stated goals of the western just war tradition is to prevent morally unnecessary wars. While just war theorists differ from pacifists in that they argue that it is possible for wars to be morally justified, they align with pacifists in that they argue that morality does apply to war, and that morally unjustified wars should be prevented and avoided. Because of this, the moral theory of war always has been, and in general has sought to be, closely linked to actual policies and laws surrounding war. Consider the Geneva Conventions; they are strongly based on the western just war tradition that was elucidated partially as a legal theory and partially as a moral theory by Thomas Aquinas, Grotius, and Vitoria (among others), and have been ably defended by many theorists as both a legally correct and a morally correct doctrine in the modern era.48 Speaking generally, traditionalist arguments about the morality of war standardly reference the actual laws and policies surrounding war for support, and arguments about the actual laws and policies surrounding war standardly reference traditionalist just war theory for support. To put it another way, the common presumption is that the laws of war do—or, if they don’t, they should seek to—match the morality of war.49,50
This puts just war theorists in the important position of being relevant to real-world political, legal, and military debates about what the laws and policies surrounding war should be. Military practitioners, advisors, and lawyers read and reference just war theorists’ research, as do international jurists and political scientists. But if McMahan is correct that we ought not publicize or legalize the “deep morality” of war, then this means that just war theorists—insofar as they accept McMahan’s revisionist moral conclusions—are no longer in a position to advocate honestly for particular international laws and military policies as morally apt. Just war theorists could advocate in bad faith, of course, but this would necessitate going against where the moral theory has led, and any reasonably adept public policy maker would be able to quickly ferret out the difference between their public and private stances. This could (and we have some evidence that it does51) lead to a widespread loss of trust in just war theorists, which might make it even less likely that public policy makers, international legal theorists, and military decision-makers will listen to just war theorists. And this is bad for the stated goal of just war theory. If those involved in the creation and implementation of military policy and international law no longer listen to just war theorists, then those theorists will be unable to advocate successfully for the prevention of morally unnecessary wars. At the risk of being myopic, war is one real-world arena where philosophers have a say, and are listened to; it is not clear that we should engage in practices that are likely to reduce that influence, especially given the amount of good that we could do.52 Ultimately, to be a moral revisionist without being a legal revisionist is to give up the (admittedly limited, but real) practical influence that just
5 Coda: on Lying (Even by Omission)
Thus far, I have presented two arguments, one theoretical, one pragmatic, against McMahan’s view that we ought neither publicize nor (more importantly) legalize what he terms the “deep morality” of war. In this section, I would like to discuss, much more tentatively, a third consideration. McMahan’s conclusion that we should lie, or at the very least remain publicly and legally silent—i.e., lie by omission—about the revisionist morality of war (i.e., about his conclusions that combatants are morally unequal, that some civilians are liable to defensive attack, that some unjust combatants are liable to punishment after war, etc.) should give us some reason to question the success of his argument. Much like the infamous theory of government house utilitarianism, if you have to lie about it, that is some reason—although not decisive—to think that perhaps the theory is not correct. In much the way that Plato’s “noble lie” casts suspicion on his entire theory of justice, McMahan’s contention that we ought not change international law and military policy casts suspicion on his entire revisionist theory of war.
Of course, suspicion is not an argument. And sometimes, lying is necessary, as we learn from the many responses to Kant’s “murderer at the door” case. But there does seem to be a difference between lying in particular cases, and lying about an entire domain of human endeavor. Specific, one-off lies can be easily and straightforwardly justified; but it is not clear that the same is true of lies about an entire sub-domain of morality. Ultimately, it reads as somewhat hypocritical to argue for a moral position and then contend that the world should not strive to be moral. But perhaps, in the end, such large-scale mismatches between the law and morality are justified; I have certainly not put forward a positive argument against this view here. I have merely suggested that such mismatches ought to draw increased attention and interrogation, if not general suspicion. McMahan advocates for a combination of moral revisionism and legal traditionalism on purely pragmatic grounds; but, as I have shown, there are at least two, and possibly three, reasons to reject his pragmatic argument for covering up the so-called “deep morality” of war.
Bibliography
Alcoff Linda Martín. “How Is Epistemology Political?” In The Feminist Philosophy Reader, edited by Alison Bailey and Chris Cuomo, 705–18. New York: McGraw-Hill, 2008.
Alcoff Linda Martín. “The Problem of Speaking for Others.” In Theorizing Feminisms: A Reader, edited by Elizabeth Hackett and Sally Haslanger, 78–92. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006.
Anderson Elizabeth. “Feminist Epistemology: An Interpretation and a Defense.” Hypatia 10, no. 3 (1995): 50–84.
Bailey Alison and Chris Cuomo. “Feminist Epistemologies.” In The Feminist Philosophy Reader, edited by Alison Bailey and Chris Cuomo, 669–71. New York: McGraw-Hill, 2008.
Benbaji Yitzhak. “Culpable Bystanders, Innocent Threats and the Ethics of Self-Defense.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 35, no. 4 (2005): 585–622.
Boyle Richard. GI Revolts: The Breakdown of the U.S. Army in Vietnam.San Francisco: United Front Press, 1973.
CAPE (Center for the Army Profession and Ethic). http://cape.army.mil.
Code Lorraine. “Taking Subjectivity into Account.” In The Feminist Philosophy Reader, edited by Alison Bailey and Chris Cuomo, 718–41. New York: McGraw-Hill, 2008.
Collins Patricia Hill. “The Politics of Black Feminist Thought.” In Theorizing Feminisms: A Reader, edited by Elizabeth Hackett and Sally Haslanger, 51–65. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006.
Cortright David. Soldiers in Revolt: GI Resistance During the Vietnam War.Chicago: Haymarket Books, 2005.
Dodd Lynda G. “The Rhetoric of Gender Upheaval During the Campaign for the Nineteenth Amendment.” Boston University Law Review 93, no. 3 (2013): 709–27.
DuBois W.E.B. The Souls of Black Folk. Chicago: A.C. McClurg & Co., 1903.
Fabre Cécile. Cosmopolitan Peace. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016.
Fricker Miranda. “Introduction.” Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007.
Frowe Helen. Defensive Killing. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014.
Harding Sandra. “Rethinking Standpoint Epistemology: What Is “Strong Objectivity”?” In The Feminist Standpoint Theory Reader: Intellectual and Political Controversies, edited by Sandra Harding, 127–40. New York: Routledge, 2004.
Horn Daniel. German Naval Mutinies of World War i. New Jersey: Rutgers University Press, 1969.
Jaggar Alison. “Feminist Politics and Epistemology: The Standpoint of Women.” In The Feminist Standpoint Theory Reader: Intellectual and Political Controversies, edited by Sandra Harding, 55–66. New York: Routledge, 2004.
Jaggar Alison. “Love and Knowledge: Emotion in Feminist Epistemology.” In The Feminist Philosophy Reader, edited by Alison Bailey and Chris Cuomo, 687–705. New York: McGraw-Hill, 2008.
Just and Unjust Warriors: The Moral and Legal Status of Soldiers, edited by David Rodin and Henry Shue. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008.
Kadi Joanna. “Stupidity ‘Deconstructed.’” In Theorizing Feminisms: A Reader, edited by Elizabeth Hackett and Sally Haslanger, 40–50. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006.
Kruse Michael. “Johnstown Never Believed Trump Would Help. They Still Love Him Anyway.” Politico, November 8, 2017. https://www.politico.com/magazine/story/2017/11/08/donald-trump-johnstown-pennsylvania-supporters-215800.
Lazar Seth. “Just War Theory: Revisionists versus Traditionalists.” Annual Review of Political Science 20 (2017): 37–54.
Marcotte Amanda. “No regrets for Trump voters: The media needs to stop looking for buyer’s remorse.” Salon, June 21, 2017. https://www.salon.com/2017/06/21/no-regrets-for-trump-voters-the-media-needs-to-stop-looking-for-buyers-remorse/.
May Larry. Contingent Pacifism: Revisiting Just War Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015.
McMahan Jeff. Killing in War. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009.
McMahan Jeff. “The Morality of War and the Law of War.” In Just and Unjust Warriors: The Moral and Legal Status of Soldiers, edited by David Rodin and Henry Shue, 19–43. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008.
Mill John Stuart. On Liberty. Indiana: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc. 1978.
Orend Brian. The Morality of War.Ontario: Broadview Press, 2006.
Pamphlet distributed by the National Association Opposed to Women’s Suffrage, Library of Congress.
Plato. The Republic. Translated by Reeve C.D.C. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc, 2004.
Raleigh Standard, as quoted in the New York Times, January 22, 1864. http://www.learnnc.org/lp/editions/nchist-civilwar/4685.
Rodin David. War and Self-Defense.Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002.
Saturday Evening Post, Vol. 188, No. 11, p. 3, Sept. 11, 1915. New York Times, Sept. 9, 1915. Cited in McClure, Wallace. State Constitution-making, with Especial Reference to Tennessee: A Review of the More Important Provisions of the State Constitutions and of Current Thought Upon Constitutional Development and Problems in Tennessee. Nashville: Marshall and Bruce Company, 1916.
Scholz Sally J. “War Rape’s Challenge to Just War Theory.” In Intervention, Terrorism, and Torture: Contemporary Challenges to Just War Theory, edited by S.P. Lee, 273–88. New York: Springer, 2007.
Tickner Lisa. The Spectacle of Women: The Suffrage Campaign 1907–14.Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988.
United Nations. Implementing the responsibility to protect: Report of the Secretary-General [A/63/677]. Geneva: United Nations, 2009. Available at: http://responsibilitytoprotect.org/implementing%20the%20rtop.pdf.
Walzer Michael. Just and Unjust Wars. New York: Basic Books, 1977.
Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars (New York: Basic Books, 1977), 21–2.
Jeff McMahan, Killing in War (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 104.
Ibid., 182–8.
While this is not the only project of the just war tradition, it is oft-cited as a reason for engaging in just war theory. Such theorists argue that it is only by drawing moral lines around war that humanity can restrain warfare as a whole. Just war theorists, while not pacifists, often tend towards pacifism rather than political realism. See, among others, Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars, especially the Afterword; Larry May, Contingent Pacifism: Revisiting Just War Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015); and Cecile Fabre, Cosmopolitan Peace (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016).
See, among others, Jeff McMahan, Killing in War; Helen Frowe, Defensive Killing (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014); and Seth Lazar, “Just War Theory: Revisionists versus Traditionalists,” Annual Review of Political Science 20 (2017): 37–54.
This is the analogy that McMahan uses throughout Killing in War, and especially in Chapter 1.
Jeff McMahan, “The Morality of War and the Law of War,” in Just and Unjust Warriors: The Moral and Legal Status of Soldiers, ed. David Rodin and Henry Shue (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008), 30.
McMahan, Killing in War, 221–4.
Ibid., 234–5.
Ibid., 108–9, emphasis in original.
So much for fiat justitia ruat caelum, then.
At the very least, McMahan argues that objectively unjust combatants are liable to such censure, punishment, or penalization. McMahan, Killing in War, 190.
Ibid., 234.
Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pressing me on this point.
19th Amendment, U.S. Constitution.
I take it as uncontroversial that the 19th Amendment brought U.S. law more in line with morality.
Pamphlet distributed by the National Association Opposed to Women’s Suffrage, Library of Congress.
Ibid.
Lynda G. Dodd, “The Rhetoric of Gender Upheaval During the Campaign for the Nineteenth Amendment,” Boston University Law Review 93, no. 3 (2013): 718–20.
Saturday Evening Post, Vol. 188, No. 11, p. 3, Sept. 11, 1915. New York Times, Sept. 9, 1915. Cited in Wallace McClure, State Constitution-making, with Especial Reference to Tennessee: A Review of the More Important Provisions of the State Constitutions and of Current Thought Upon Constitutional Development and Problems in Tennessee (Nashville: Marshall and Bruce Company, 1916), 109.
Lisa Tickner, The Spectacle of Women: The Suffrage Campaign 1907–14 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988), 154.
Alison Bailey and Chris Cuomo, “Feminist Epistemologies,” in The Feminist Philosophy Reader, ed. Alison Bailey and Chris Cuomo (New York: McGraw-Hill, 2008), 669.
Linda Martin Alcoff seems, at times, to take up this view, as does Sandra Harding. Linda Martin Alcoff, “The Problem of Speaking for Others,” in Theorizing Feminisms: A Reader, ed. Elizabeth Hackett and Sally Haslanger (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), 78–92; Sandra Harding, “Rethinking Standpoint Epistemology: What Is “Strong Objectivity”?,” in The Feminist Standpoint Theory Reader: Intellectual and Political Controversies, ed. Sandra Harding (New York: Routledge, 2004), 127–40.
Patricia Hill Collins seems to have this view, as does Alison Jaggar. Patricia Hill Collins, “The Politics of Black Feminist Thought,” in Theorizing Feminisms: A Reader, ed. Elizabeth Hackett and Sally Haslanger (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), 51–65; Alison Jaggar, “Feminist Politics and Epistemology: The Standpoint of Women,” in The Feminist Standpoint Theory Reader: Intellectual and Political Controversies, ed. Sandra Harding (New York: Routledge, 2004), 55–66.
Elizabeth Anderson seems to have something close to this view. See her “Feminist Epistemology: An Interpretation and a Defense,” Hypatia 10, no. 3 (1995): 50–84.
Alison Jaggar, “Love and Knowledge: Emotion in Feminist Epistemology,” in The Feminist Philosophy Reader, ed. Alison Bailey and Chris Cuomo (New York: McGraw-Hill, 2008), 696.
Anti-suffrage groups included both men and women. However, this should not cast doubt on my analysis of anti-suffragists as epistemically biased against women, because as we learn from W.E.B. DuBois and others, one of the results of oppression is that members of the oppressed group tend to internalize and then propagate (as a survival mechanism) the viewpoint and stance of the privileged/oppressive group vis-à-vis the subjugated/oppressed group. W.E.B. DuBois, The Souls of Black Folk (Chicago: A.C. McClurg & Co., 1903), 10–5.
Lorraine Code, “Taking Subjectivity into Account,” in The Feminist Philosophy Reader, ed. Alison Bailey and Chris Cuomo (New York: McGraw-Hill, 2008), 730. Emphasis in original.
Ibid., 730.
Alison Bailey and Chris Cuomo, “Feminist Epistemologies,” 670.
Linda Martin Alcoff, “How Is Epistemology Political?,” in The Feminist Philosophy Reader, ed. Alison Bailey and Chris Cuomo (New York: McGraw-Hill, 2008), 705–718.
Jaggar, “Love and Knowledge,” 696.
While the bulk of combatants are from the lower classes, some in the officer corps and military high command are not. And perhaps not surprisingly, McMahan in places suggests that it is the officer corps and high command who will be doing the propagandizing to the rest of the troops—the implication being that they are “in” on the true morality of war, but are choosing to ignore morality for their own purposes. While this is a negative moral view of the officer corps and military high command, it is not the same as the negative epistemic view that McMahan’s argument seems to display towards those everyday combatants who are at the lower ends of the chains of command, who are, for the most part, on the receiving end of military orders.
Miranda Fricker, “Introduction,” Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).
McMahan, “The Morality of War and the Law of War,” 28. McMahan, Killing in War, 151.
McMahan, Killing in War, 185–6.
This is also sometimes called Plato’s “noble lie.” Plato, The Republic, trans. C.D.C. Reeve (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc, 2004), 414c.
Many philosophers have written critically about Plato’s “noble lie,” but only some have rejected his epistemic premises. Notably, John Stuart Mill argues against paternalism on utilitarian grounds, not epistemic ones; he allows that some people might be too stupid to reach the truth or make good decisions, but argues that they will be happier if they are allowed to make their own choices, and so defends anti-paternalism (for the most part). John Stuart Mill, On Liberty (Indiana: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc. 1978), Chapter 4, Section 4.
Joanna Kadi, “Stupidity ‘Deconstructed,’” in Theorizing Feminisms: A Reader, ed. Elizabeth Hackett and Sally Haslanger (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), 41.
And like Plato, the rich often justify this lie as being for the lower classes’ own good; better to be poor in a capitalist society, they say, than to live in a socialist or communist society. (That is, “Better dead than red!”)
And furthermore, it is to ignore military history. There are several historical cases of everyday combatants recognizing that the war that they were fighting was unjust. Famously, southern Confederate soldiers were the first to call the U.S. Civil War “a rich man’s war and a poor man’s fight.” Op-ed in the Raleigh Standard, as quoted in the New York Times, January 22, 1864, http://www.learnnc.org/lp/editions/nchist-civilwar/4685. In addition, one of the reasons that Germany signed the wwi armistice was because the ordinary sailors of the German Navy, against their commanders’ orders, refused to continue fighting. This mutiny spread to other military and industrial bases across Germany, and was closely followed by the Kaiser’s abdication and the end of the war. Daniel Horn, German Naval Mutinies of World War i (New Jersey: Rutgers University Press, 1969).
Michael Walzer hammers this point home in Just and Unjust Wars, especially Chapters 3, 8, 9, and 19. In addition, the cape (Center for the Army Profession and Ethic) website, run by the U.S. Army, has over 200 case studies regarding combat behavior alone, and hundreds more regarding non-combat wartime combatant behavior. This suggests that, contrary to the popular view of combatants as “lugheads” or “grunts,” complex ethical thinking and decision-making is very much a feature of the combatant experience. cape, http://cape.army.mil, accessed November 5, 2017.
Kadi, “Stupidity ‘Deconstructed,’” 43.
This is not to say that no combatants are brutes, or that no combatants act brutishly; rather, it is to make the point that we cannot simply assume that combatants, en masse, are all brutes.
More on this general goal of the just war tradition below; although this is not the only project of just war theory, it is one of the oft-recognized and oft-repeated overall goals of the theory. In this way, just war theory is sympathetic to pacifism.
See, among others, Amanda Marcotte, “No regrets for Trump voters: The media needs to stop looking for buyer’s remorse,” Salon, June 21, 2017, https://www.salon.com/2017/06/21/no-regrets-for-trump-voters-the-media-needs-to-stop-looking-for-buyers-remorse/, and Michael Kruse, “Johnstown Never Believed Trump Would Help. They Still Love Him Anyway,” Politico, November 8, 2017, https://www.politico.com/magazine/story/2017/11/08/donald-trump-johnstown-pennsylvania-supporters-215800.
German troops rebelled and refused to continue fighting in October and November 1918, precipitating the end of wwi, despite threats of treason charges from the Kaiser and other members of the German high command. (See note 41.) In addition, once the circumstances of the Vietnam War became apparent, several American combatants and draftees refused to fight in that war, despite threats of death, court-martialing, jail time, deportation, and/or massive fines. At some points, whole units of the U.S. Army in Vietnam refused to continue fighting, attempted to surrender, and even attacked and killed (fragged) their commanding officers. Richard Boyle, GI Revolts: The Breakdown of theU.S.Army in Vietnam (San Francisco: United Front Press, 1973); David Cortright, Soldiers in Revolt: GI Resistance During the Vietnam War (Chicago: Haymarket Books, 2005), esp. 127–33.
The tenets of the Geneva Conventions are perhaps most famously defended as a moral code by Michael Walzer, in his canonical Just and Unjust Wars. But he is not alone here; other contemporary defenders include Yitzhak Benbaji, “Culpable Bystanders, Innocent Threats and the Ethics of Self-Defense,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 35, no. 4 (2005): 585–622; Brian Orend, The Morality of War (Ontario: Broadview Press, 2006); David Rodin, War and Self-Defense (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002); and Seth Lazar, “Just War Theory: Revisionists versus Traditionalists,” among others.
Although this is the common presumption, it is certainly not unchallenged. For a good survey of this newly emerging debate, see Just and Unjust Warriors: The Moral and Legal Status of Soldiers, ed. David Rodin and Henry Shue (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008).
Of course, morality and the law can, in general, come apart, and in many domains, it is important that they be clearly separated. What is interesting about the western just war tradition, though, is that it has explicitly sought to link the morality of war to the laws of war, in order to help prevent and avoid morally unnecessary wars. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pressing me on this point.
Often, this is labeled as hypocrisy, and it has led to the downfall of many politicians and other public figures, as well as to a general loss of trust in government institutions as a whole. This is not to say that hypocrisy is the only reason for the rising mistrust of government; however, it does seem to have played a contributory role.
This is perhaps too optimistic of a view of the relationship between just war theorists and those involved in the creation and implementation of international law and military policy; however, I do not think that it is wholly impossible, given that cadets in all U.S. military academies read and study Walzer’s work, and that just war theorists have, in recent years, been invited to address the U.N. and its related bodies. In addition, consider the newly-accepted view of the U.S. Department of Defense that war rape is a form of ethnic cleansing and genocide (a position advocated tirelessly for by just war theorist Sally Scholz, among others), as well as the escalation of force cards carried by members of the U.S. military on deployment, which were designed based on just war theorists’ work on the nature of threats. Sally J. Scholz, “War Rape’s Challenge to Just War Theory,” in Intervention, Terrorism, and Torture: Contemporary Challenges to Just War Theory, ed. S.P. Lee (New York: Springer, 2007), 273–88; United Nations, Implementing the responsibility to protect: Report of the Secretary-General [A/63/677] (Geneva: United Nations, 2009), http://responsibilitytoprotect.org/implementing%20the%20rtop.pdf; David Rodin, War and Self-Defense.