For over a century, theorists and activists have made connections between pacifism and feminism. For example, during the late 1800s and early 1900s pacifist feminism emerged in Great Britain, and Jane Addams was advocating for women’s suffrage and world peace in the United States.1 Less well known is the new approach of nonkilling philosophy and its benefits for strengthening such an alliance through its efforts to unite peace studies and gender studies or at least making available to them augmented and strengthened terminology and methodology.
I am a pacifist. I am a feminist. Of course, this list goes on. For example, I am also an advocate for lgbtq rights and for prison reform. However, when asked to give such a list, I usually begin by saying I am a pacifist and I am a feminist. In this chapter, however, while I will address aspects of pacifism and feminism, I am going to place them in the background to a discussion of the nonkilling perspective initiated by Glenn Paige and its reliance on the violentology perspective initiated by Francisco Muñoz. I will also address the initiation of nonkilling philosophy by Irene Comins Mingol and Sonia París Albert. I am doing so to present how these perspectives can provide practical and even more radical ways to advance and possibly even unite peace studies and gender studies than do pacifism and feminism. At the same time, I will contend that while nonkilling philosophy is not hampered by stereotypes that often thwart acceptance of pacifism and feminism, it relies on important aspects of both of feminism and pacifism.
1 Pacifism in Peace Studies and Feminism in Gender Studies: Current Partial Connection
Pacifism has long been a frequent, though not the paradigmatic, orientation in Peace Studies. Likewise, feminism is closely associated with Gender Studies, though it is not the sole perspective informing Gender Studies. For purposes of this chapter, I will note briefly important expressions of nonviolence and pacifism developed by Robert Holmes and Duane Cady and of feminism developed by Betty Reardon and Karen Warren and related developments in care ethics.
1.1 Nonviolence and Pacifism of Holmes and Cady
While the traditions of nonviolence and pacifism can be traced back to antiquity, in modern times they are often associated Gandhi and King.2 Within recent philosophy, two of the most careful treatments can be found in the work of Robert Holmes and Duane Cady. I want to note how Holmes distinguishes violentist and nonviolentist approaches and how this distinction differs from the violentology perspective in nonkilling philosophy. I also want to note how Cady lays out a continuum of pacifism that highlights types that allow for some lesser levels of violence and show how most of these types are consistent with nonkilling philosophy.
Holmes distinguishes violentists (ones who accept use of violence) and nonviolentists (advocates of nonviolence). For Holmes, the nonviolent perspective can be based on principled or pragmatic grounds, and he gives strong arguments in favor of the principled version over the pragmatic one. Moreover, given these definitions, he can distinguish nonviolentists from pacifists. He states:
Pacifism is opposition to war, nonviolence [is] opposition to violence. While one cannot be a nonviolentist without being a pacifist, one can be a pacifist without being a nonviolentist. One can, that is, oppose warfare without necessarily opposing other modes of violence.3
For my purposes, the point I want to stress is that the violentism that Holmes criticizes is distinct from the violentology perspective criticized within the
Spanish peace researcher Francisco Muñoz coined the term “violentology perspective” (perspectiva violentológica) to refer to the problem that research focused on violence, even when undertaken by advocates of nonviolence, makes violence appear to be more pervasive than it is.4 Pacifists and feminists can fall victim to the cognitive dissonance that Muñoz describes. In their cases, while they desire peace and gender equality, they often give more attention to conceptualizing and criticizing the large-scale violence of war and the widespread occurrence of violence against women. While the violentology perspective is descriptive of how we take for granted the practicality of and the justification for violence—what some would call violentism—it also calls for greater emphasis on the diverse and extensive occurrences of nonviolence and for their expansion. Even advocates of nonviolence need to move to the next level. Prescriptively, while we need to expose the various types of physical violence and killing and the structural and cultural forms that support them, we also need to develop alternative discourses and practices that advance nonkilling and nonviolence. Like some other orientations toward peacemaking, the nonkilling perspective helps us move forward with a focus on ways in which so much in the lives of individuals and societies takes place apart from violence.
Beyond confusing the violentist and the violentology perspectives, many people also incorrectly equate pacifism and passivism. In his highly influential book Between Warism and Pacifism, originally published in 1989, Cady clarifies how pacifists are activists, not passivists, and also makes a distinction between deontological and consequentialist pacifists.5 As far as I can tell, his distinction relies on the same philosophical distinction that Holmes makes between principled and pragmatic nonviolentists. The difference is that Cady refers only to grounds for the moral opposition to war and includes versions that Holmes likely would say are violentist. In brief, Cady distinguishes three types of deontological pacifists and three types of consequentialist pacifists. In my interpretation, only the absolute type of deontological pacifist would qualify as a nonviolentist, since Cady presents all other pacifists as allowing for the moral use of some levels of violence—not only nonlethal violence, but also, in some cases, lethal violence. However, for Cady, all pacifists are united in a moral opposition to war. Cady’s distinctions are important for at least two reasons. First,
1.2 Care Ethics and the Feminism of Reardon and Warren
Like the traditions of nonviolence and pacifism, feminism also has a long history. Much of the history of the contribution of women is largely unknown to us, though within philosophy Karen Warren has helped recover some of these contributions.6 To compound recognition of the contribution of women is the fact that the term “feminism” came into use only fairly recently. The French word “feminisme,” coined by Charles Fourier, was taken over into English during the 1890s within the movement for equal rights for women, though I would be remiss if I failed to note the earlier contributions of Mary Wollestonecraft in the late 18th century who, while not having available the term feminism, made important arguments for the rights of women well before those of John Stuart Mill in the late 19th century.7 For purposes of this chapter, however, I will simply comment on care ethics and the work of Betty Reardon since both are important influences on nonkilling philosophy. Also, I will discuss briefly how Karen Warren links concerns about women and peace to ones about the environment, which is also a concern within nonkilling philosophy.
Carol Gilligan initiated care ethics in 1982 with her groundbreaking book In a Different Voice.8 She termed as “Justice Ethics” the abstract and retributive approach traditionally favored in philosophy. Alternatively, she termed as “Care Ethics” a relational approach to morality that avoids generalization in favor of particularity and connection. Gilligan describes and affirms how individuals are entangled in a web of dynamic relationships, not all of which are freely chosen. Among the feminist philosophers who have influenced nonkilling philosophy, Sara Ruddick made an important application of care ethics in her 1995 Maternal Thinking: Toward a Politics of Peace.9 Nevertheless, Ruddick does not understand that pacifists can advocate non-lethal force and even lethal force and still oppose war and other large-scale military action. She says,
Nonkilling philosophy correctly credits Betty Reardon as the feminist who challenged gender studies to address the structural relation between sexism and the war system and who also argued for the centrality of issues of gender within peace studies. Among her most important works are Sexism and the War System (1985), Women and Peace (1993), Education for a Culture of Peace in Gender Perspective (2001), and the collection Betty A. Reardon: Key Texts in Gender and Peace (2015).13 Dale Snauwaert, in summarizing the importance of her work, says:
Reardon’s groundbreaking work argues that a feminist, holistic, and gendered perspective can serve as the conceptual core of a transformation of our present global system of patriarchy, and its culture of violence and war. Her comprehensive work in this area has uncovered the profound symbiotic relationship between patriarchy and the war system, and she calls for a global inquiry into alternatives to the patriarchal paradigm. She argues for a gender-equal and socially just society based on a cosmopolitan ethic of human rights. For Reardon, this vision of a positive human and planetary future is realized through achieving a transformational, fundamental shift in worldview towards a paradigm of peace informed by a gender perspective.14
Nonkilling philosophy stresses Reardon’s view that “above all a culture of peace would be a culture of caring.”15
Since nonkilling philosophy aspires to avoid the destruction not only of human beings but also of other species and the environment, I will end this brief survey by noting the relevance of the work of Karen Warren. In several of her books, Warren has introduced ecological feminism.16 Among other goals, ecological philosophy wants to stop destruction of the environment and feminist philosophy wants to stop violence against women. Militarism also is destructive to the environment and to human beings.17 So, not surprisingly, Warren applied her views to the war system in Bringing Peace Home: Feminism, Violence, and Nature, her 1996 book with Duane Cady.18 They contend that serious consideration of feminism should lead to philosophical discussions of peace that incorporate feminist insights on relations among women, nature, and war. They make detailed connections across six areas. One of the central connections is with language, which has been of ongoing concern to me.19 Concerning language, they criticize “sexist-naturist-warist” discourse as “language which inferiorizes women and nonhuman nature by naturalizing women and feminizing nature, and then gets used in discussions of war and nuclear issues.”20 While their collection allows a variety of voices to speak on these issues, I find their contribution to be especially important for bringing together peace studies and gender studies, since, like nonkilling philosophy, it also includes concerns about the environment.
The problem of violence is a common denominator to pacifism, feminism, and environmentalism. I have long maintained that we need an alliance of these movements and have advocated nonviolence on personal through
2 The Contribution of the Nonkilling Perspective
The pioneering work of American political scientist Glenn Paige and the multi-disciplinary Center for Global Nonkilling that he founded have largely defined the nonkilling movement. Put briefly, the nonkilling perspective maintains that human beings can live in societies in which they do not kill other human beings and perhaps also not kill members of many other species and do not cause serious harm to the environment. The Center for Global Nonkilling, located in Honolulu, coordinates interdisciplinary research on the goal of nonkilling by demonstrating its feasibility and the achievement of nonkilling by developing methods for its progressive implementation. The work of this center currently spans over two dozen disciplines and has been supported and expanded by the publication of many books that have brought together the research of over 600 scholars in over 70 countries.22
To someone unfamiliar with the nonkilling perspective, this vision of a “killing-free world” may sound as quixotic as do the aims of pacifism and feminism to persons who are equally unfamiliar with what they really assert. So, just as pacifists and feminists spend a lot of time trying to correct misperceptions of their views and prospects, even so do advocates of the nonkilling perspective face an initial reaction of disbelief and dismissal. Nevertheless, I aim to show that by reducing such misperceptions, pacifists and feminists may find a vocabulary, a perspective, and a method that provide a fresh and beneficial means to advance their aims.
The main work by Glenn Paige is Nonkilling Global Political Science.23 Since the 1990s he has addressed key objections to the nonkilling perspective and has
3 The Work of Comins Mingol and París Albert
3.1 Initiation of Nonkilling Philosophy
Beginning in 2009, Spanish philosophers and peace researchers Irene Comins Mingol and Sonia París Albert initiated nonkilling philosophy in a manner that provides a philosophical treatment of the moral and ethical foundations of the nonkilling perspective and one that also has promise for uniting peace studies and gender studies or at least making available to them augmented and strengthened terminology and methodology.25 Recently, I began introducing their work to U.S. philosophers.26 So, in this chapter I will treat only lightly how they ground their support for nonkilling philosophy on works in discourse ethics and care ethics. A philosophical treatment of the moral and ethical foundations of the nonkilling perspective requires a prescriptive model of the need to speak nonviolently and act nonviolently. While I have elsewhere addressed prescriptively these issues in relation to discourse and behavior, here I will simply note the type of philosophical support that discourse ethics and care ethics provide within the nonkilling perspective.
Within discourse ethics, Comins Mingol and París Albert primarily utilize the work of Jürgen Habermas, especially his views that discourse presupposes truth as an ideal and, to a lesser extent, the work of John Austin. For Habermas, the ideal of truth that underlies discourse should be operative in (or can serve for the assessment of) our statements, our intentions, and our actions. Comins Mingol and París Albert reveal their reliance on Habermas when they state that discourse ethics “presupposes the liberty and equality of all speakers” and
Within care ethics, Comins Mingol and París Albert mainly rely on Carol Gilligan, Sara Ruddick, and Betty Reardon and stress how care ethics facilitates
I turn now to a summary of the position Comins Mingol and París Albert develop on the basis of the philosophical support provided by discourse ethics and care ethics. In particular, Comins Mingol and París Albert stress that we generally have alternative nonviolent responses available during conflict and after conflict and that we should train for and make use of these alternatives. Traditional academic approaches to conflict resolution and conflict management are negative. These approaches are negative because they aim to either eliminate or administer conflict. Resolution or elimination of conflict is not feasible to the extent that conflict is built into how diverse individuals and cultures approach differences. Management or administration of conflict also has limits to the extent that it operates as an external authority in relation to conflict. Conflict transformation aims to operate within conflict, rather than being imposed upon conflict. Conflict transformation accepts conflict and places in the hands of those involved the responsibility for seeking to implement nonviolent practices. To facilitate conflict transformation, Comins Mingol and París Albert propose that we “disaccustom ourselves to violence” and instead cultivate the practice and then the habit of what they term “conflict transformation.”37 In place of efforts to eliminate or administer conflict, conflict transformation prepares the persons involved in conflict to seek “peaceful
Comins Mingol and París Albert conclude by asserting “a nonkilling philosophy is necessarily a philosophy committed to the recuperation of and the recognition of human potential for peace.”40 In this regard, they stress that human beings have capacities for “harmonious coexistence, for reciprocal care and the peaceful transformation of conflicts.”41 In my terminology, they aim to move from the language of war and linguistic violence to the language of peace and linguistic nonviolence.42 In addressing the needed language and behaviors for such a transition, París Albert elsewhere responds to the problem of indignation that is experienced by so many oppressed peoples.43 Though she draws from Hegel’s famous treatment of recognition in his master-slave dialectic, she also goes beyond the usual stress on how the struggle for recognition can lead to domination—to the risking of life and even the taking of life—and the misguided view that forcing recognition through violence works. To present a different possible outcome, she relies on work of Paulo Friere that addresses how to move from fear to hope.44 She contends that the indignation that many people feel in the face of injustice and which can lead to violent responses can be transformed by nonviolent social movements, such as nonkilling philosophy, that incorporate “mutual recognition into the processes of empowerment of the oppressed to transform the oppressive situations they suffer.”45 Such mutual recognition, coupled with nonviolent action, may displace fear with hope and through this practice of conflict transformation may elevate the quest for freedom to a higher plane in the quest to overcome oppression and achieve social justice.
3.2 Nonkilling Philosophy and the Neuroscience of Ethics
Pacifists and feminists and other advocates of nonviolence and social justice often hear one refrain or another to the effect of “You can’t change human
In order to locate the challenges for advocates of nonviolence that are posed in some neurophilosophy or neuroethics, one needs to begin by understanding the distinction typically made between the ethics of neuroscience and the neuroscience of ethics. The difference between these two approaches is significant. The ethics of neuroscience is more commonly done within applied philosophy and examines ethical issues relating to the clinical practice of neuroscience or to experimental research in neuroscience. By contrast, the neuroscience of ethics focuses generally on human behavior but also sometimes focuses more narrowly on what is purported to be human nature. These efforts that go beyond the original narrow confines of neuroscience suggest to some the possible eclipse of philosophy. Patricia Churchland first challenged this overreach in her 1990 book Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind/Brain.47 She situates this overreach of neuroscience within the overly reductionist tendencies in modern science that rely almost exclusively on mathematization and experimentation that thereby lapse into partial accounts that are often naively positivistic.
In their 2013 article “Epistemological and Anthropological Thoughts on Neurophilosophy,”48 París Albert and Comins Mingol respond to claims in the
In their response to these developments, especially within the neuroscience of ethics, París Albert and Comins Mingol occasionally rely on insightful humor and regularly employ careful logical analysis. At the outset, they quip “Similarly to how phrenologists were determined to reduce the analysis of human nature to the shape of the skull, neurologists seem determined to reduce it to the functioning of neurons.”49 In contradistinction to such mono-causal models, they stress evidence of what they term “the irrepressible plasticity of our brains,” which they regard as the locus of our freedom and as facilitating responses to danger and conflict that are not reductively mono-directional and programmed with inclinations toward violence. Philosophically, they situate these frequently unrecognized assumptions of neuroscience within the violentology perspective that is so widely taken for granted (and which I discussed in the second section of this chapter). Such assumptions mask recognition that inclinations toward nonviolent responses are also present or can be cultivated.
París Albert and Comins Mingol do not claim that human beings are nonviolent by nature. To make that claim would be reductive in ways like the opposite position that human beings are violent by nature—as has been postulated often in religion, philosophy, and science. They readily affirm that human beings are “conflictive beings.” However, in relation to the conflicts that we regularly face, they assert our responses “may be either violent or peaceful, i.e., this capacity for ‘fighting with’ can come about violently or peacefully.”50 They cite research that typically our “conflicts are linked to indecision,” noting “Conflicts are those moments when the fight is undecided; that is, those situations in which we do not really know what to do…and have different alternatives.”51 When such moments arise, nonviolent alternatives can be chosen. At this point, the response of París Albert and Comins Mingol moves from criticism of the neuroscience of ethics to support for nonviolent alternatives.
París Albert and Comins Mingol cite research that the alternatives open to individuals in conflicts include not only whatever may be in our genes but also and significantly the influences of our social environment. They say that these factors are ones that are stressed in much Peace and Conflict Research. They conclude, “People can be violent or peaceful, but our social make-up is probably what will influence directly on our being more violent or more peaceful.”52 Hence, efforts by pacifists and feminists and others concerned with nonviolence and social justice can advance their goals by stressing the development of individual and social behaviors that promote nonviolence. In this way, their argument supports the movement in Peace Studies away from conflict resolution and conflict management toward conflict transformation. In response to neuroscience, especially to aims in the neuroscience of ethics, they conclude, “if we can say there are universal neural bases that explain violence, we can also say there are universal neural bases that explain our ability to act in a peaceful way.”53 Thus, efforts to “study and disseminate the methodologies for peaceful conflict transformation” can contribute to making nonviolent responses even more widely available, appealing, and practical.54
4 Conclusion: Pacifism, Feminism, and Nonkilling Philosophy as Mutually Supportive
I have suggested that, in several ways, nonkilling philosophy is more radical in scope than either pacifism or feminism. Also, I have noted that nonkilling philosophy is not hampered by stereotypes that often thwart acceptance of pacifism and feminism. With its reliance on discourse ethics and care ethics, nonkilling philosophy can move peace studies beyond conflict resolution and conflict management to conflict transformation and can move gender studies beyond exposing patriarchalism and achieving gender equality to fostering restorative justice. In addition, I proposed that nonkilling philosophy provides a constructive approach for criticizing militarism and sexism and for unifying efforts to respect, protect, and advance the value and diversity of life and the environment. Finally, I addressed how nonkilling philosophy also responds to challenges for advocates of nonviolence that are posed by works in science that suggest humans are violent by nature or, particularly in the neuroscience of ethics, that seek to dismiss philosophical notions of human freedom.
We still need pacifism for the critique of war and other large-scale violence, and we still need feminism for the critique of gender inequality and other forms of social injustice. We also can profit from the interdisciplinary advances of the nonkilling perspective. We can benefit from this vocabulary, this interdisciplinary solidarity, and this bridge for connecting peace studies and gender studies in a manner that avoids the stereotyping and dismissal of pacifism and feminism and, instead, inspires hope and action that can help realize the acceptability of their shared vision and advance the achievement of their shared goals. In relation to pacifism and feminism, Nonkilling Philosophy is more radical in its advocacy of nonviolence and could even be more feasible in its implementation. Nonkilling Philosophy can provide an initiative for peace studies and gender studies that is mutually supportive for each.
Bibliography
Ackerman Peter and Jack Duvall. A Force More Powerful: A Century of Nonviolent Conflict. New York: St. Martin’s Press, 2000.
Addams Jane. The Jane Addams Reader. Edited by Jean Bethke Elshtain. New York: Basic Books, 2002.
Austin John Langshaw. How to do Things with Words. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1976.
Benhabib Seyla. Critique, Norm, and Utopia: A Study of the Foundations of Critical Theory. New York: Columbia University Press, 1986.
Brown Heloise. ‘The Truest Form of Patriotism’: Pacifist Feminism in Britain, 1870–1902. Manchester, UK and New York: Manchester University Press, 2003.
Burr Harold Saxton. Neural Basis of Human Behavior. Oxford: Blackwell Scientific Publications, 1960.
Cady Duane. From Warism to Pacifism: A Moral Continuum. 2nd ed. Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 2014.
Center for Global Nonkilling. www.nonkilling.org.
Churchland Patricia Smith. Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind/Brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1990.
Comins Mingol Irene. “Coeducation: Teaching Peace from a Gender Perspective.” Peace & Change 34, no. 2 (2009): 456–70.
Comins Mingol Irene and Sonia París Albert. “Nonkilling Philosophy.” In Toward a Nonkilling Paradigm, edited by Joám Evans Pim, 271–86. Honolulu: Center for Global Nonkilling, 2009.
Friere Paulo. Pedagogy of Indignation.New York: Routledge, 2004.
Friere Paulo. Pedagogy of the Oppressed. Translated by Myra Bergman Ramos. New York: Herder and Herder, 1972.
Gandhi Mohandas K. The Moral and Political Writing of Mahatma Gandhi. Vol. 1–3. Edited by Raghavan Iyer. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986.
Gay William C. “Apocalyptic Thinking versus Nonviolent Action: From Instilling Fear to Inspiring Hope.” In Spiritual and Political Dimensions of Nonviolence and Peace, edited by David Boersema and Katy Gray Brown, 43–53. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 2006.
Gay William C. “Diversity and Peace: Negative and Positive Forms.” In Community, Diversity, and Difference: Implications for Peace, edited by Alison Bailey and Paula J. Smithka, 175–85. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 2002.
Gay William C. “Exposing and Overcoming Linguistic Alienation and Linguistic Violence.” Philosophy and Social Criticism 24, no. 2/3 (1998): 137–56.
Gay William C. “Justification of Legal Authority: Phenomenology vs Critical Theory.” Journal of Social Philosophy 11, no. 2 (1980): 1–10.
Gay William C. “Negative Impacts of Militarism on the Environment.” In The Nature of Peace and the Peace of Nature: Essays on Ecology, Nature, Nonviolence, and Peace, edited by Andrew Fiala, 51–9. Leiden, Boston: The Netherlands: Brill Rodopi, 2015.
Gay William C. “Nonsexist Public Discourse and Negative Peace: The Injustice of Merely Formal Transformation.” The Acorn: Journal of the Gandhi-King Society 9, no. 1 (1997): 45–53.
Gay William C. “Reality of Linguistic Violence against Women.” In Gender Violence: Interdisciplinary Perspectives, edited by Laura O’Toole and Jessica Schiffman, 467–73. New York: New York University Press, 1997.
Gay William C. “Restorative Justice and Care Ethics: An Integrated Approach to Forgiveness and Reconciliation.” In Explorations of Forgiveness: Personal, Relational, and Religious, edited by Court Lewis, 39–66. Wilmington, DE: Vernon Press, 2016.
Gay William C. “The Language of War and Peace.” In Encyclopedia of Violence, Peace, and Conflict, 2nd edition, edited by Lester Kurtz, Volume 2, 1115–27. Oxford: Elsevier, 2008.
Gay William C. “The Practice of Linguistic Nonviolence.” Peace Review 10, no. 4 (1998): 545–7.
Gay William C. “The Prospect for a Nonviolent Model of National Security.” In On the Eve of the 21st Century: Perspectives of Russian and American Philosophers, edited by William Gay and T.A. Alekseeva, 119–34. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1994.
Gay William C. “The Role of Language in Justifying and Eliminating Cultural Violence.” In Cultural Violence, edited by Fuat Gursozlu, 175–97. Leiden: Brill, 2018.
Gilligan Carol. In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development. Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press, 1982.
Habermas Jürgen. “Justice and Solidarity: On the Discussion Concerning Stage 6.” In The Moral Domain: Essays in the Ongoing Discussion Between Philosophy and the Social Sciences, edited by Thomas Wren, 224–54. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989.
Habermas Jürgen. Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action. Cambridge: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press, 1993.
Habermas Jürgen. The Theory of Communicative Action. Cambridge: Polity, 1989.
Holmes Robert. “The Morality of Nonviolence.” In The Ethics of Nonviolence: Essays by Robert L. Holmes, edited by Predrag Cicovacki, 169–81. New York and London: Bloomsbury, 2013.
King Martin Luther Jr. Strength to Love. New York: Harper & Row, 1963.
Muñoz Francisco A. La Paz Imperfecta. Granada: Universidad de Granada, 2001.
Paige Glenn D. Nonkilling Global Political Science. Honolulu: Center for Global Nonkilling, 2009.
Paige Glenn D. “‘To Leap Beyond Yet Nearer Bring’: From War to Peace to Nonviolence to Nonkilling.” The International Journal of Peace Studies 2, no. 1 (1997).
París Albert Sonia. “Philosophy, Recognition, and Indignation.” Peace Review 25, no. 3 (2013): 336–42.
París Albert Sonia and Irene Comins Mingol. “Epistemological and Anthropological Thoughts on Neurophilosophy: An Initial Framework.” Recerca 13 (2013): 63–83. DOI: 10.6035/Recerca.2013.13.5.
Reardon Betty A. Education for a Culture of Peace in Gender Perspective. Paris: UNESCO, 2001.
Reardon Betty A. Sexism and the War System. New York: Teachers College, Columbia University, 1985.
Reardon Betty A. Women and Peace: Feminist Visions of Global Security. Albany: SUNY, 1993.
Reardon Betty A. and Dale T. Snauwaert. Betty A. Reardon: Key Texts in Gender and Peace. Cham, Switzerland; also, Heidelberg, New York, Dordrecht, and London: Springer, 2015.
Ruddick Sara. Maternal Thinking: Toward a Politics of Peace. Boston: Beacon Press, 1995.
Snauwaert Dale T. “Preface.” In Betty A. Reardon: Key Texts in Gender and Peace, edited by Betty A. Reardon and Dale T. Snauwaert, ix–xx. Cham, Switzerland; also, Heidelberg, New York, Dordrecht, and London: Springer, 2015.
Stanley D.A. and R. Adolphs. “Toward a neural basis for social behavior.” Neuron 80, no. 3 (2013): 816–26.
Warren Karen J., ed. An Unconventional History of Western Philosophy: Conversations between Men and Women Philosophers. Lantham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc., 2009.
Warren Karen J., ed. Ecological Feminism. London and New York: Routledge, 1994.
Warren Karen J., ed. Ecological Feminist Philosophies. Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1996.
Warren Karen J. and Duane L. Cady. “Feminism and Peace: Seeking Connections.” In Bringing Peace Home: Feminism, Violence, and Nature, edited by Karen J. Warren and Duane L. Cady, 1–15. Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1996.
Warren Karen J. and Duane L. Cady, eds. Bringing Peace Home: Feminism, Violence, and Nature. Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1996.
Wollstonecraft Mary. Vindication of the Rights of Woman. London: Penguin Books, 1992. First published 1792.
Zampaglione Gerardo. The Idea of Peace in Antiquity. Translated by Richard Dunn. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1973.
Heloise Brown, “The Truest Form of Patriotism”: Pacifist Feminism in Britain, 1870–1902 (Manchester, UK and New York: Manchester University Press, 2003); Jane Addams, The Jane Addams Reader, ed. Jean Bethke Elshtain (New York: Basic Books, 2002).
Gerardo Zampaglione, The Idea of Peace in Antiquity, trans. Richard Dunn (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1973); Mohandas K. Gandhi, The Moral and Political Writing of Mahatma Gandhi, vol. 1–3, ed. Raghavan Iyer (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986); Martin Luther King, Jr., Strength to Love (New York: Harper & Row, 1963).
Robert Holmes, “The Morality of Nonviolence,” in The Ethics of Nonviolence: Essays by Robert L. Holmes, ed. Predrag Cicovacki (New York and London: Bloomsbury, 2013), 170, n. 1.
Francisco A. Muñoz, La Paz Imperfecta (Granada: Universidad de Granada, 2001), par. 10.
Duane Cady, From Warism to Pacifism: A Moral Continuum, 2nd ed. (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 2014).
Karen J. Warren, ed., An Unconventional History of Western Philosophy: Conversations between Men and Women Philosophers (Lantham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc., 2009).
Mary Wollstonecraft, Vindication of the Rights of Woman (London: Penguin Books, 1992), first published in 1792.
Carol Gilligan, In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development (Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press, 1982).
Sara Ruddick, Maternal Thinking: Toward a Politics of Peace (Boston: Beacon Press, 1995).
Ibid., 138.
Cady, From Warism to Pacifism, esp. 64–8.
William C. Gay, “Restorative Justice and Care Ethics: An Integrated Approach to Forgiveness and Reconciliation,” in Explorations of Forgiveness: Personal, Relational, and Religious, ed. Court Lewis (Wilmington, DE: Vernon Press, 2016), esp. 49–59.
Betty A. Reardon, Sexism and the War System (New York: Teachers College, Columbia University, 1985); Women and Peace: Feminist Visions of Global Security (Albany: suny, 1993); Education for a Culture of Peace in Gender Perspective (Paris: unesco, 2001); and Dale T. Snauwaert, Betty A. Reardon: Key Texts in Gender and Peace (Cham, Switzerland; also, Heidelberg, New York, Dordrecht, and London: Springer, 2015).
Dale T. Snauwaert, “Preface,” Betty A. Reardon, ix.
Reardon, Education for a Culture of Peace in Gender Perspective, 85.
Karen J. Warren, ed., Ecological Feminism (London and New York: Routledge, 1994); Karen J. Warren, ed., Ecological Feminist Philosophies (Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1996).
William C. Gay, “Negative Impacts of Militarism on the Environment,” in The Nature of Peace and the Peace of Nature: Essays on Ecology, Nature, Nonviolence, and Peace, ed. Andrew Fiala (Leiden, Boston: The Netherlands: Brill Rodopi, 2015): 51–9.
Karen J. Warren and Duane L. Cady, eds., Bringing Peace Home: Feminism, Violence, and Nature (Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1996).
William C. Gay, “Nonsexist Public Discourse and Negative Peace: The Injustice of Merely Formal Transformation,” The Acorn: Journal of the Gandhi-King Society 9, no. 1 (1997): 45–53; “The Reality of Linguistic Violence against Women,” in Gender Violence: Interdisciplinary Perspectives, ed. Laura O’Toole and Jessica Schiffman (New York: New York University Press, 1997), 467–73; “Exposing and Overcoming Linguistic Alienation and Linguistic Violence,” Philosophy and Social Criticism 24, no. 2/3 (1998): 137–56; “The Practice of Linguistic Nonviolence,” Peace Review 10, no. 4 (1998): 545–47; “The Language of War and Peace,” in Encyclopedia of Violence, Peace, and Conflict, 2nd ed., ed. Lester Kurtz (Oxford: Elsevier, 2008), vol. 2: 1115–27.
Karen J. Warren and Duane L. Cady, “Feminism and Peace: Seeking Connections,” in Warren and Cady, Bringing Peace Home, 8.
William C. Gay, “The Prospect for a Nonviolent Model of National Security,” in On the Eve of the 21st Century: Perspectives of Russian and American Philosophers, ed. William Gay and T.A. Alekseeva (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1994), 119–34; “Diversity and Peace: Negative and Positive Forms,” in Community, Diversity, and Difference: Implications for Peace, ed. Alison Bailey and Paula J. Smithka (Amsterdam: Rodopi, 2002), esp. 180–83; “Apocalyptic Thinking versus Nonviolent Action: From Instilling Fear to Inspiring Hope,” in Spiritual and Political Dimensions of Nonviolence and Peace, ed. David Boersema and Katy Gray Brown (Amsterdam: Rodopi, 2006), 43–53.
Center for Global Nonkilling, www.nonkilling.org, accessed September 29, 2016.
Glenn D. Paige, Nonkilling Global Political Science (Honolulu: Center for Global Nonkilling, 2009).
Glenn D. Paige, “‘To Leap Beyond Yet Nearer Bring’: From War to Peace to Nonviolence to Nonkilling,” The International Journal of Peace Studies 2, no. 1 (1997).
Irene Comins Mingol and Sonia París Albert, “Nonkilling Philosophy,” in Toward a Nonkilling Paradigm, ed. Joám Evans Pim (Honolulu: Center for Global Nonkilling, 2009), 283–84.
William C. Gay, “The Role of Language in Justifying and Eliminating Cultural Violence,” in Cultural Violence, ed. Fuat Gursozlu (Leiden: Brill, 2018), 175–97.
Comins Mingol and París Albert, “Nonkilling Philosophy,” 278.
Jürgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action (Cambridge: Polity, 1989); Jürgen Habermas, Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action (Cambridge: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press, 1993).
William C. Gay, “Justification of Legal Authority: Phenomenology vs Critical Theory,” Journal of Social Philosophy 11, no. 2 (1980): 3.
John Langshaw Austin, How to do Things with Words (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1976).
Comins Mingol and París Albert, “Nonkilling Philosophy,” 278.
Seyla Benhabib, Critique, Norm, and Utopia: A Study of the Foundations of Critical Theory (New York: Columbia University Press, 1986).
Jürgen Habermas, “Justice and Solidarity: On the Discussion Concerning Stage 6,” in The Moral Domain: Essays in the Ongoing Discussion Between Philosophy and the Social Sciences, ed. Thomas Wren (Cambridge, MA: mit Press, 1989), 224–54.
Comins Mingol and París Albert, “Nonkilling Philosophy,” 279.
Betty Reardon, Education for a Culture of Peace in Gender Perspective, 85.
Irene Comins Mingol, “Coeducation: Teaching Peace from a Gender Perspective,” Peace & Change 34, no. 2 (2009): 456–70.
Comins Mingol and París Albert, “Nonkilling Philosophy,” 275.
Ibid., 276.
Ibid., 275.
Ibid., 283.
Ibid., 283.
Gay, “The Language of War and Peace.”
Sonia París Albert, “Philosophy, Recognition, and Indignation,” Peace Review 25, no. 3 (2013): 336–42.
Paulo Friere, Pedagogy of Indignation (New York: Routledge, 2004); Pedagogy of the Oppressed, trans. Myra Bergman Ramos (New York: Herder and Herder, 1972).
París Albert, “Philosophy, Recognition, and Indignation,” 340.
Harold Saxton Burr, Neural Basis of Human Behavior (Oxford: Blackwell Scientific Publications, 1960); D.A. Stanley and R. Adolphs, “Toward a neural basis for social behavior,” Neuron 80, no. 3 (2013): 816–26.
Patricia Smith Churchland, Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind/Brain (Cambridge, MA: mit Press, 1990).
Sonia París Albert and Irene Comins Mingol, “Epistemological and Anthropological Thoughts on Neurophilosophy: An Initial Framework,” Recerca 13 (2013): 63–83. DOI: 10.6035/Recerca.2013.13.5.
París Albert and Comins Mingol, “Epistemological and Anthropological Thoughts on Neurophilosophy,” 71.
Ibid., 76.
Ibid., 77.
Ibid., 80.
Ibid., 81.
Ibid., 81.