1 Introduction
Why are we unaware that we are asleep in most episodes of dreaming?1 Aristotle gives the oldest extant answer to this question. I will examine how Aristotle’s views on deception in dreaming and related cases are received and developed in pre-modern and modern philosophy. This wide-ranging paper may seem a bit unorthodox to some readers because of its inclusion of ancient, medieval, and premodern texts together with a rather thorough discussion of contemporary views. However, the idea is to follow Aristotle’s account of why dreamers tend to mistake their dreams for real, ongoing events in relation to later explanations up to the present. I will show how contemporary discussions entail more or less prominent Aristotelian elements that were rediscovered by later authors, even when the link to Aristotle has been lost. It will also be shown that contemporary discussions on delusional dreaming have not advanced considerably since Aristotle, and that a version of Aristotle’s explanation of why dreams are mistaken for real events is still a plausible alternative in contemporary debates. Thus, this work has the somewhat bold ambition to provide a contribution to the history of philosophy as well as defend an Aristotelian approach to the problem of why dreams are mistaken for real events, in a contemporary context.
I shall pay special attention to two pairs of related questions:
-
(1) What factors explain people’s reports that dreams are misapprehended as real events while dreaming? And do such reports actually reflect misapprehensions of dreams as real?
-
(2) Are dreamers on occasion completely deceived about the true nature of their dreams, and if so, do such deceptions involve belief?
I aim to show that there is a compelling form of deception that is present in dreams, which I shall call delusional dreaming. This form of deception involves an altered cognitive state, not necessarily pathological, characterised by the following closely related traits: (1) deception in the form of a misapprehension of dreams as real and (2a) the inability to be aware of absurd content as strange, as well as (2b) an inability to consider the dream as illusory even in cases where there is no absurd content. Thus, delusional dreaming involves a mode of forced deception that is based on deficient cognition and should not be conflated with deception that occurs under normal cognitive circumstances. Note that one can be deceived regarding the reality of an experience without having lost the ability to identify bizarre elements or to form critical judgements. For example, I may unknowingly be connected to a virtual reality device and tacitly assume that what I experience is real. Yet if I am awake, the readiness to react to bizarre elements and the ability to form critical attitudes is intact, even if there are no obvious elements that suggest that the experience is illusory. In the state of waking we can doubt the reality of our experiences at will, for any arbitrary reason: for example, as a playful theoretical exercise. By contrast, the state of delusional dreaming prevents any attempt to form critical attitudes toward one’s own experiences. The three aspects of delusional dreaming will be further discussed below.
Deception may generally be characterised as a commitment to misleading, imperfect, or incomplete evidence that is false. A typical case involves a false view which is formed on the basis of how things superficially seem. Deception entails that somebody is deceived but does not necessarily involve a deceiver such as a stage magician who fools his audience by means of smoke and mirrors or an unfaithful partner who conceals the betrayal. There are a lot of different factors that make us prone to deception. The state of delusional dreaming is one of them.
In this paper I shall mainly follow Pavel Gregoric’s interpretation of Aristotle’s explanation of why dreams are taken to be real. On this interpretation, Aristotle’s view provides the blueprint for a family of views that distinguish between proper beliefs (dóxa) that paradigmatically are the product of rational consideration in the state of wakefulness, and a simple form of unreflecting trust that occurs in sleep.2
I shall examine Aristotle’s idea regarding a rudimentary form of trust that is distinct from fully developed beliefs and follow it from antiquity, through the middle ages and the early and late modern era, all the way to contemporary discussions in philosophy of mind. I will show that the ghost of Aristotle lurks in the background in many modern and contemporary discussions of why dreams are taken to be real.
I shall also compare ancient and medieval ideas that resemble Aristotle’s views but which are not strictly Aristotelian, such as the distinction between rudimentary and fully developed beliefs that was endorsed by ancient sceptics in order to defend the sceptical stance in a coherent way. Moreover, I shall try to show that a cluster of modern theories called imagination theories that deny the possibility of deception in dreaming fail to account for the common experience of dreams as mistaken for real happenings while dreaming. Even so, some imagination theories come close to Aristotle’s view that the dreamer is deluded about the reality of dreams without assuming a proper belief in the reality of the dream. I shall side with Aristotle and argue that the misapprehension of dreams as real does not involve fully developed beliefs (a non-doxastic view). Yet there is a tacit unreflecting trust in the dream as real.
2 The Concept of Delusional Dreaming
Dreaming may be compared to other conditions that include delusions, for instance, states caused by intoxication or mental disorder. Such states involve a compelling element that ordinary non-delusional cases of deception lack. At this stage it is useful to think of delusions as emerging from an altered state of cognition. I shall develop this point below.
Roughly, there are two forms of delusions, namely, delusional awareness and delusional belief. For instance, if I dream or hallucinate (a non-veridical perception-like experience in waking that has the full force of a perception) a flying pig and respond to it as real, I am having a delusional awareness. By contrast, if I am awake and convinced that extra-terrestrials are conspiring to conquer our planet, without there being any particular sensory experience to suggest this, then I am having a delusional belief.3 Delusional awareness, however, does not rule out belief but rather highlights the presence of an illusory experience that is taken to be veridical.
Nevertheless, in some cases it seems warranted to acknowledge a form of delusional awareness that does not qualify as belief, strictly speaking. A deflationary type of delusional awareness includes a rigid state of trust where ‘delusional’ refers to a deficient kind of cognition and ‘trust’ is taken to be an element that approximates the sense of conviction that is the result of fully developed beliefs. In this paper I shall mainly focus on the form of delusional awareness that occurs in the state of sleep and does not qualify as proper belief.
Dreams are special cases of illusions, and illusions are roughly false appearances. We are sometimes fooled by illusions, and different kinds of illusions reflect different objects of deception. Two common types of illusion include:
-
(1) Things that appear other than they are. A common type of illusion involves any appearance about the world that does not correspond to how things are in reality. For example, a dolphin may look like a shark, a room may appear smaller than it actually is, and a stick in water may appear to be bent. Some illusions may continue to appear true even when we know that they are false.
-
(2) The misapprehension of internal sensory manifestations as happenings in the real world. The type of illusions that I shall focus on in this paper involves the misapprehension of sensory-like entities, often described as images, of the kind we entertain when we internally visualise objects or scenarios or reproduce an internal awareness of any sense modality. For example, we may picture a polar bear before our inner eye. When we imagine a polar bear, we do not see a polar bear strictly speaking, yet we are aware of something that has the visual characteristics of a polar bear. We can leave the ontology of such objects of awareness aside for the moment and focus on the phenomenology of internal images. We rarely mistake imagined things as real when we are awake, but it sometimes happens that such internal imaginations are mistaken for objects or happenings in the real world. The misapprehension of dreams as real is an example of the relevant kind of misapprehension. Other examples include hallucinations where external objects are experienced as present in cases where such objects are actually absent.4 This group of illusions also includes false memories, that is, memory-like experiences of things that did not occur, as if they actually occurred in the past.5
Dreams are habitually characterised as realistic experiences. What does it mean to appear real? In fact, “appearing real” has a range of different senses. Here are some:
-
(1) Faithful sensory replication. Illusory appearances sometimes deceive us because they resemble the real object or the state of affairs they mimic. For example, I may be deceived by a dream of the Eiffel Tower because it appears exactly like a previous perception of the Eiffel Tower. Even so, perfect sensory replication may deceive us in some situations but not in others.
-
(2) Likely and credible events. Events are sometimes said to be realistic if they fall within the range of what can be expected to be normal, likely, or credible. For example, if I dream that I am late for a lecture or that I eat a sandwich for lunch, such events are realistic because they reflect common or likely events in real life. By contrast, dreams about talking ducks, or that I am able to fly, include improbable or unrealistic elements, despite the sensory realism of such dreams.
-
(3) The sense of “this is really happening.” Alternatively, a dream may appear to be real in a more abstract feeling-like way rather than by faithful resemblance to perceptual states in waking, or with reference to credible scenarios. For example, I have dreamed about an environment consisting completely of different shades of blue, and dubious things like supposedly dead people who talk – such dreams may still appear as real as it gets.6 While we dream, we seldom pay attention to details that distinguish dreams from ordinary perceptual states in waking, yet we often marvel at a dream’s unrealistic features when we wake up.
-
(4) The sense of observing things in the world. Then again, even if dreams often diverge from sensory states in waking with reference to sensory phenomenology, dreams in general replicate the fundamental form of being-in-a-world, along with a sense of perceiving things in a way that roughly reflects the perceived environment in waking.7
Thus, ‘appearing real,’ in a broad sense, does not necessarily imply that the dream faithfully mimics the sensory phenomenology and the content of experiences we normally have in waking. Although some dreams are reported to faithfully imitate the perceptual phenomenology in waking,8 and some dreams are described as having an intensified vividness that goes beyond the perception in waking,9 the notion of ‘appearing real,’ as it is used here, does not require this kind of realism.
Finally, the state of delusional dreaming can be characterised as comprising three significant aspects:
(1) The dreamer mistakes the dream for a real-world thing or occurrence. A striking element in delusional dreaming is the common observation that dreams are habitually taken to be real events similar to those that we experience while awake. What does this mean? Here is a standard account by Michel Jouvet:
Our dream consciousness reacts like this, as if it were awake. We think that we are not dreaming. It is thus conscious awareness because we can ask ourselves if we are dreaming. Dream consciousness is thus similar to that of a hallucinating awake subject. Dream or hallucinatory images triggered by an endogenous system in the brainstem are considered to be real, even if fantastic. Thus the reasoning of conscious awareness during waking is absent.10
So, we are deceived about the true nature of our current mental state, that is, that we are not awake and perceiving things in the world. And we take experienced events to be real even if they are extremely incredible. Dreams may be viewed as a kind of recurrent nocturnal madness we experience. It is only when we wake up that we realise that we were dreaming, and perhaps notice the unreal and excessive features of the dream. Consider Allan Hobson’s colourful description of delusional dreaming:
What is the difference between my dreams and madness? What is the difference between my dream experience and the waking experience of someone who is psychotic, demented, or just plain crazy? In terms of the nature of the experience, there is none. In my New Orleans dream I hallucinated: I saw and heard things that weren’t in my bedroom. I was deluded: I believed that the dream actions were real despite gross internal inconsistencies. I was disoriented: I believed that I was in an old hotel in New Orleans when I was actually in a house in Ogunquit. I was illogical: I believed that drawing circles on a ceiling would help police localize individuals in a room above.11
(2a) The tolerance of bizarre elements. Another distinct aspect of delusional dreaming that this condition does not share with ordinary cases of deception is that the dreamer is insensitive and unable to react to the oddness or the incredibility of events. The dreamer cannot assess the dream as odd because strange experiential features do not stimulate critical assessment of the dream. Compare a normal case in which I may be deceived by, say, a virtual-reality device, that makes me believe that my current illusory experience is real. If really strange things happen I may doubt whether I am awake, or suspect that I am hallucinating. This cognitive sensitivity to react to events that lie beyond the range of what can be accepted as believable seems absent in delusional dreaming. In fact, the peculiarities in dreams often pass unnoticed as nothing out of the ordinary: for example, I may find myself talking to my partner M although she happens to look like a complete stranger; nevertheless I respond to her as my familiar long-time partner. It seems that that we often are aware of dreams without noticing (or caring) how poorly the dream-object imitates real things. Finally, consider a related deficiency:
(2b) The inability to consider the dream as illusory. However, the inability to detect oddness is a symptom of a more serious deficiency. The state of delusion prevents the dreamer from doubting or disbelieving the dream, even as a voluntary theoretical exercise (as we might doubt the existence of the external world without really taking the doubt seriously). In order to see the difference between (2a) and (2b) more clearly, observe that, even if the dream comprises no fantastic elements, in the delusional state the dreamer is unable to view the experience in a critical way, nor even in a speculative, non-committing way. It seems that in the delusional state the dream cannot be challenged even as an act of make-believe. In fact, in delusional dreaming there seems to be no conscious awareness of a possible contrasting illusory state that provides a theoretical ground for uncertainty. On the other hand, if a dream is apprehended as illusory, in any manner for any reason, the dreamer is likely not to be fully deluded. Hence, delusional dreaming is a far more deprivational state than deception caused by ordinary ignorance, heedlessness, or absent-mindedness in wakefulness.12
The inability to consider the dream as unbelievable, deceiving, illusory, or false is an effect of a cognitive condition that conceals its deficient performance. In other words, we are cognitively incapacitated without being aware of it. For example, when we are awake, we may notice that we have certain gaps in our memory – I may realise that I remember nothing about how I got into my present situation. By contrast, delusional dreaming is more like an amnesia that we are unable to be aware of as a memory loss. For example, imagine that you wake up one morning with no memory at all about what happened the previous night, but you do not even notice your loss of memory. The delusional state is devious because it conveys an illusory sense of cognitive status quo in the sense that prevents any awareness of impaired cognitive performance.
Jouvet’s and Hobson’s description of deception in dreaming has been challenged by some philosophers. According to Jonathan Ichikawa, Jouvet and Hobson represent what he calls “the orthodox view.”13 Two tenets sum up the orthodox view, which reflects how people intuitively describe their experiences of dreaming: (1) dreams appear in a perception-like guise, and (2) dreams are misapprehended as real events. In this theoretical landscape, Aristotle may be said to be an advocate of the orthodox view since he considers dreams to be perception-like images that we usually mistake for real events. Those who oppose the orthodox view typically argue that dreams are imaginations (of the kind we entertain when we picture objects or scenarios before our inner eye) rather than percepts, and that being caught up in dreaming is not to believe in the reality of what is imagined regardless of what the dream is about (hereafter “imagination theories”).
I shall return to the question of how modern proponents of imagination theories use the term ‘image’ in relation to Aristotle’s general conception of phántasma and specific concept of dream-phántasma. I shall also use some modern imagination theories as a contrast to Aristotle’s account of delusional dreaming, which basically reflects the orthodox view. Even if some imagination theories deny that dreams are mistaken for real events, nonetheless, other imagination theories provide an interesting account about how imagination may entail a rudimentary form of belief, that more or less reflects Aristotle’s conception of delusional dreaming on the interpretation here considered.
I shall suggest a view that stays close to Aristotle’s view in one plausible interpretation and argue that delusional dreaming involves (1) a rudimentary form of unreflecting trust, though not necessarily a full-fledged belief that dreams are real, and that (2a) not being aware of the dream as a dream, (2b) being unaware of being asleep, or (2c) taking the dream to be really happening in the world rather than being an illusion produced by our mind, is sufficient in order to be deceived by a dream’s apparent reality. Thus, deception regarding the reality of dreams does not require a fully developed belief, nor a conscious thought that a dream is real, nor some other articulated idea that an experience is real rather than illusory.
3 Aristotle’s Conception of Delusional Dreaming
3.1 Why Dreams Are Taken to Be Real
The problem of how we may prove that we are not dreaming right now is mentioned briefly by Aristotle in the Metaphysics14 and is described as an artificial problem that misleadingly suggests the need of a demonstration in order to be resolved. Aristotle argues that to ask for proof in order to distinguish between one’s dreaming and waking is to have things backwards, since the fundamental distinction between veracity and error is founded on circumstances that do not need proof. The problem of dream-scepticism is discussed in the context of Protagorean relativism and echoes Plato’s formulation of the problem in Theaetetus 157e–58e. Aristotle holds that there are normal circumstances of waking life that serve as paradigmatic cases of authoritative awareness in relation to more or less distorted apprehensions of reality due to a variety of causes. Aristotle seems to endorse the view that under normal circumstances we can recognise that we are awake and that the state of waking is more authoritative than sleep or dreaming. However, this does not rule out that we occasionally may be deceived by dreams during sleep.
To reduce overlaps with Gregoric’s contribution in this volume I shall highlight a set of themes that are not extensively treated in his paper, including the nature of delusional dreaming as a forced mode of deception and varieties of deflationary notions of trust. It will be shown that the concept of delusional dreaming, in one interpretation, illuminates Aristotle’s account of why dreams are cognised as real. Here is what Aristotle has to say about why people tend to mistake dream-images (phantásmata) for real events:
Each of these [phantasms], as has been said, is a remnant of the actual sense-impression, and is still present within, even when the real one [viz. sense-impression] has departed. Thus, it is true to say that it is like Coriscus, even though it is not Coriscus. While one was perceiving, one’s ruling and judging part was saying not that the sense-impression is Coriscus, but because of that impression, that the actual person out there is Coriscus. The part that says this while it is actually perceiving (unless it is completely held in check (katéchetai) by the blood) is moved by the movements in the sense-organs, as if it were perceiving.15
In short, dream-appearances derive from sense-impressions and linger on and become apparent in sleep because ordinary perception is shut down. One central idea is that, like veridical perceptual states, dream-appearances present information about how things appear to be in the world, even if false. For example, when we perceive Coriscus the senses display (the real) Coriscus as-if-present. Likewise, the dream (of Coriscus) involves an appearance of the real Coriscus even if the real Coriscus no longer causes the presence of the sense-impression that persists in sleep.
Aristotle attributes a primitive form of judgement (dokeîn) to the senses, roughly the senses have the capacity to assess how things are in the world, which should not be conflated with proper belief (dóxa).16 Sight is said to be more authoritative than touch because if touch stood alone, one single object would be taken as two when the object is sensed by crossed fingers.17 Furthermore, appearances in perception sometimes contradict what is believed or known about the world. For example, the sun appears to be one foot across. In such cases there are conflicting cognitive assessments.18 Thus, appearances may be challenged by many different kinds of cognitive assessments where some assessments are more trustworthy than others. For example, vision normally outranks touch, and accumulated knowledge about the world is superior to how things superficially look. It seems plausible to assume that what Aristotle refers to as superior cognition in terms of the “the ruler” (tò kýrion) may vary with the circumstances. For example, vision loses its status as the authoritative sense in a pitch-black environment. Exactly how Aristotle’s discussion of hierarchical cognitive assessments relate to the conditions of deception in dreaming is not fully transparent. I shall discuss this problem briefly below, especially in connection with Radulphus Brito’s (d. 1320/21) account.
Aristotle seems to mean that the highest instance of judgement, in relation to normal observational circumstances, is sufficient for reliable judgements. If the cognitive machinery works the way it is supposed to (that is, the subject is not diseased, sleeping, intoxicated, and so forth), the subject would know when he is awake, and accordingly he would know that he is not asleep and dreaming. The point is not that there are no ambiguous cases between sleep and waking, but rather that, given the radical difference between the cognitive conditions of sleep and wakefulness in their paradigmatic manifestations, it makes good sense to suppose that we can be aware of being awake when we in fact are awake, that is, in a state where the mind can exercise the full range of its cognitive powers.
Conversely, Aristotle’s example of deception regarding the reality of the dream seems to rely on a similar assumption that all other cognitive functions are shut down except the awareness of the dream-appearance. In the case of humans, the intellect as well as lower capacities are inactive. Now, it seems reasonable to assume that animals can be deceived about the reality of dreams even if they lack rational capacities. This point is important because it shows that the conditions for deception in dreaming do not include having an intellect, even if the operation of the intellect may be of help in judgements that experiences are illusory. For instance, (1) a dog may be deceived about the reality of the dream, that is, not be aware of that the dream involves an illusory world, (2) when the dog wakes up it becomes aware of the real world, but this does not necessarily imply (3) that the dog has the capacity to be aware of a dream (or any other experience) as an illusory entity. In other words, deception regarding the reality of the dream does not presuppose the cognitive powers to know or suspect that we are sometimes deceived.
Aristotle’s examples of dream deception in which there is no opposing cognition in relation to the appearing phántasma probably reflects a typical condition in which deception occurs. We do not receive any information about what is minimally sufficient for snapping out of the deceptional state in which dreams are taken to be real. Nevertheless, Aristotle is quite clear that the capacity for belief-formation is restrained in the state of sleep. On one interpretation, this means that the dream is neither believed to be real nor believed to be unreal (this is the non-doxastic interpretation of deception in dreaming):19
And does judgement sometimes declare it an illusion, as it does for waking people, while at other times it is held in check (katéchetai) and follows along with the appearances (phantásmata)?20
And in a related passage:
For in general the starting-point affirms the report from each sense, provided that some other, more authoritative one does not contradict it. In every case, then, something appears, yet what appears is not in every case judged to be real; it is, though, if the critical part is held in check (katéchetai) or fails to move with its own proper movement.21
In this second passage Aristotle does not explicitly refer to belief-formation as restrained but only to the “critical part.” So, does he refer to the capacity to form critical beliefs or to any assessment that may oppose a present phántasma? It seems plausible to interpret Aristotle as referring to any opposing cognitive assessments as absent in the typical case of dream-deception. The reference to dóxa as a product of the operating intellect in the first passage, however, is likely to highlight the point of there being a deceptive non-doxastic form of naïve trust in dreams.
As for the question of belief, I follow Gregoric’s view that deception does not require a proper belief. It is a form of unreflecting trust, which involves a tacit uncritical affirmation of whatever appears to be the case. Aristotle maintains that there is an element of low-level judgement (dokeîn) that is conveyed by the senses. The dokeîn-element in sense-perception basically means that the senses, in one very restricted sense, can be said to judge how things are in the external world. This form of low-level judgement should not be conflated with fully developed belief (dóxa) yet it seems sufficient to explain the apprehension of a dream as something real. Now, if the sensory remnants in sleep convey some sort of judgements about how things are, which are manifest as appearances, the dreamer will respond to such appearances as true given the absence of opposing cognitive assessments. This is the non-doxastic interpretation of why the dreamer is deceived regarding the reality of the dream.
However, there is another option. It might be argued that the state of sleep only inhibits the formation of critical beliefs, not the formation of affirmatory beliefs. So when the dreamer responds to the apparently real dream as actually real there is a proper belief in the dream as real. Yet it is difficult to see why the state of sleep would restrain critical belief formation but leave the capacity for affirmatory belief intact. If there can be only confirmatory beliefs there is not much left of the normal belief-generating procedure that is the result of rational evaluation, and consequently it becomes odd to characterise such non-rational assents as proper beliefs.22
3.2 Realism, Deception, and Dream Bizarreness
As we have seen, Aristotle’s explanation of delusional dreaming involves examples that faithfully mimic sensory qualities and also mundane events, for instance, when it seems as if a well-known person (Coriscus) is present. Aristotle does not explicitly discuss incredible dream-content or cases in which dreamers respond to fantastic dream-content as real, nor does he discuss the cognitive capacity needed in order to be able to assess what is considered as normal, credible, or hard to believe. In other words, Aristotle does not explicitly address the question of why absurd dream-content is accepted without further notice. Nonetheless, it seems reasonable to assume that the dreamer responds to the phántasma as nothing strange because it provides the only present cognitive assessment about how things are. In such simple-minded cognitive states, nothing can be analysed or examined.23
However, Aristotle discusses aspects of dream-bizarreness from another angle in De insomniis. Strange dream-contents are understood as distortions that are caused by physiological disturbances and may involve deformed, fragmentary, or rearranged sense-impressions to the extent that they no longer resemble the perceived objects they derive from.24
When Aristotle refers to distortions, or grotesque or incoherent dreams, he seems to be focused on strange dream-images in the form of objects, not on fantastic dream-narratives. Two related points can be made in connection with this observation. First, Aristotle’s conception of distorted dreams, just like his conception of undistorted dreams, is object-centred, rather than event-centred (unlike our contemporary notion of dreaming which involves a succession of events, sometimes in the form of stories).25 There is no remark on bizarre sequences of events in dreams in Aristotle’s account.
Further, Aristotle does not make any distinction between (1) what qualitatively appears as real, and (2) what can be reasonably taken to be a realistic experience of an object or an event. For example, a dream of a chimera may appear as real (in a qualitative sensory sense) but may seem unrealistic given what I know about the world. For Aristotle, a dream about a chimera is a distortion, most likely a unity composed of several sense-impressions with different origins.26 A further implication is that the dreamer tends to apprehend a dream-image of a chimera as real, regardless of whether such a creature exists or not. Yet the parts of a chimera-dream correspond to various fragments that derive from mundane sense-impressions. In sum, Aristotle might explain the dream-subject’s tolerance of dream-bizarreness by way of the restrained powers of the intellect or some other inhibited cognitive function that is deactivated by the state of sleep. Even if Aristotle does not explicitly discuss what capacity would be sufficient to identify a dream as odd, incredible, or bizarre, the suggestion that the dream-appearance, as such, involves the only present cognitive assessment, indirectly explains why bizarre elements are ignored or taken as equally real as mundane events.
3.3 The Proper Sense of ‘Unreflective Trust’
Non-doxastic accounts tend as a rule to sound slightly more intellectualistic (that is, doxastic) than they are intended to be. The problem is mainly terminological and concerns the element of assent that may appear to be some kind of top-down attitude taking sense-impressions as its object. The dokeîn-element of a sense impression mentioned above is not something that is added to the sense-impression, but ought to be regarded as an integrated part of it. Hence when the dreamer blindly or non-committedly follows his dream-appearances, the element of trust, conviction, or assent is already there in the very awareness of the appearance itself, provided that there are no other assessments.
Therefore, expressions that aim to capture the non-doxastic interpretation of delusional dreaming conceptualised as an “unreflective acceptance,” “unreflective assent,” “tacit acceptance,” “taking the appearance of realism for granted,” “passive trust,” etc., should not be understood as something added to what is included in the bare awareness of the appearance. Hereafter I shall refer to this non-doxastic type of assent as “unreflective trust.”
We need to make some further qualifications of the relevant Aristotelian sense of ‘unreflective trust’ that is characteristic of delusional dreaming. First, the relevant kind of ‘unreflective trust’ only partly corresponds to similar phenomena we are familiar with from waking life. For example, we usually presuppose (take for granted, or accept) without any critical reflection that the ground under our feet is solid as we walk, if it appears that way. It is arguable that the dreamer tacitly believes, (thinks, presupposes, or takes for granted) that what is experienced during dreaming is real, in the same sense a wakeful person ‘believes’ that the ground under his feet is solid if there are no particular reasons to be uncertain about it. In such cases it becomes reasonable to speak of an absence of doubt rather than the presence of an affirmative belief as something actively produced in response to an appearance. However, it is important to realise that the condition of delusional dreaming does not include any readiness to form critical attitudes as we may do when we tacitly trust that the ground is solid under our feet.
Even naïve or spontaneous beliefs in the existence of the external world are misleading analogues in this context. Why? There is a compelling element in delusional dreaming that distinguishes it from other kinds of unreflecting trust in waking. For instance, when the person is fully awake, he can withdraw, modify, or suspend his trust in bare experience, as he sees fit. For example, if I fall into a camouflaged hole in the ground, I might be very suspicious the next time I stroll around in similar surroundings. Or, even if I do not for a second commit to the belief that there is no external world, I can doubt its existence as part of a sceptical exercise, perhaps to the point where I feel the world to be unreal (without really being deceived by the feeling of unreality). The delusional dreamer, by contrast, cannot withdraw his trust in experience at will for any reason, not even by means of a suspension of judgement or a speculative hypothesis that the present experience is illusory. In sum, the relevant kind of unreflective trust that is characteristic of delusional dreaming, in Aristotle’s account, manifests itself as a rigid, narrow awareness that takes experiences at face value and cannot be modified or altered at will as long as the cognitive inhibitions that are characteristic of the delusional state prevails. Give and take some details, this characterisation seems a plausible option in contemporary theorising.
4 Two Kinds of Assent in Ancient Scepticism
In order to get some perspective on Aristotle’s conception of unreflecting trust we may take a look at some later conceptions of proto-belief, which contrasts with fully developed belief. A distinction between fully developed beliefs and something in line with ‘unreflecting trust’ was developed in the ancient sceptical tradition in order to escape the charge that that scepticism is a self-refuting position. For example, if you believe that nothing can be known, it seems quite pointless to defend this view by a knowledge-claim. This problem resulted in attempts to articulate a distinction, as Michael Frede puts it, between “having a view” and “making a claim.” The sceptics distinguished between two kinds of assent: sometimes ‘assent’ was used to describe a mental act, for example, the acceptance of a sense-impression, that is based on reasons for judging it to be true; on other occasions people assent to sense impressions simply because they appear in certain ways.27 Michael Frede writes:
On the basis of this one might try to make a distinction between just having a view and making a claim, taking a position. To just have a view is to find oneself being left with an impression, to find oneself having an impression after having considered the matter, maybe even for a long time, carefully, diligently, the way one considers matters depending on the importance one attaches to them. But however carefully one has considered a matter it does not follow that the impression one is left with is true, nor that one thinks that it is true, let alone that one thinks that it meets the standards which the dogmatic philosophers claim it has to meet if one is to think of it as true. To make a claim, on the other hand, is to subject oneself to certain canons. It does, e.g., require that one should think that one’s impression is true and that one has the appropriate kind of reason for thinking it to be true. To be left with the impression or thought that p, on the other hand, does not involve the further thought that it is true that p, let alone the yet further thought that one has reason to think that p, that it is reasonable that p.28
One important point is that appearances are forced upon us. Perhaps some beliefs are also forced upon us after reflection. Yet beliefs can be endorsed for a variety of reasons. The distinction between the impression that p, on the one hand, and the reason-based belief that p or not-p, on the other, seems fairly clear and approximates Aristotle’s distinction between an unreflecting trust in appearances and fully developed beliefs. However, as previously argued, Aristotle’s notion of delusional dreaming should not be equated with the voluntarily suspension of judgement, as one attitude among others. The dreamer cannot voluntarily choose to accept the impression, nor disbelieve the impression, nor withhold acceptance or rejection.
Next I shall make a leap to the middle ages and examine Radulphus Brito’s commentary of Aristotle’s De insomniis.29
5 Radulphus Brito: Delusional Dreaming and Incredible Dreams
I shall now turn to a medieval discussion of the deceptive nature of dreams: namely, Radulphus Brito’s comments on Aristotle’s account on dreaming in De insomniis. I shall follow a particular strand in Brito’s commentary that deals with fantastic dreams, that is, dreams with incredible content.30 Brito is interesting in this context because he attempts to explain why the dreamer accepts very strange dreams as true. The fact that the dreamer is inclined to be fooled by dreams that include quite ordinary events like eating breakfast at home is more understandable, since such dreams do not give any reasons to suspect that something is wrong. Brito’s discussion may be seen as a development of a theme that was implicit in De insomniis. Brito investigates the general idea that the sense-impressions that linger on in sleep are taken to be actual sense-impressions. Dreams about horses as well as dreams about centaurs appear real because dreams in general appear to be caused by real objects. Brito writes:
This, then, is first clear from a consideration of the movement of images to the fantasy, for, according to the Philosopher, during sleep, towards the end of the sleep when the evaporation has become refined, there is a continuous movement of images from the fantasy to the common sense, for they are moving continuously in such a way that one is there in actuality and another in potency, and when one is destroyed another is generated, and then the common sense is modified by those phantasms as if it were modified by external sense-objects, and therefore, when several phantasms that do not have any mutual ranking modify the common sense, then it judges as if it were modified by external sense-objects, and then something composed of a man and a horse or the like appears to one, and one dreams of monsters.31
Brito repeats Aristotle’s explanation of how phantásmata may change shape into various forms that more or less resemble proper real-world objects. Thus, a phantasm may be composed of a man and a goat, and this is how monsters may appear in sleep. The claim that any dream, even a dream of monstrous creatures, appears to be real, is a plausible interpretation of what is implicit in De insomniis.32
Brito goes on to discuss the effect of the disabled intellect during sleep. It is the power of sleep that makes the dreamer believe that a likeness of a thing, that is, a phántasma, is the very thing it resembles:
The major is evident from the Philosopher, for the Philosopher claims that if someone were to put his finger under his eye, but is unaware of having his finger under his eye, then he sees one thing as two, and he is unaware of this deception and believes that one thing is two. But if he is not unaware of having his finger under his eye, then he still sees one thing as being two, but he is not unaware of the deception; on the contrary, he knows that in reality there is just one thing and not two, and he judges in accordance with the superior capacity. This is also the way it is during sleep: if someone believes that a phantasm of Coriscus is Coriscus, he is deceived; but if a superior capacity, such as the intellect, is not fettered, and he does not believe that the phantasm of Coriscus is Coriscus, he is not deceived. But the intellect, which is a superior capacity, is sometimes actual, and then one is not unaware of the deception †33 are because of the horrible nature of the dream† when the intellect is actual, because sometimes a dream is so terrible that the intellect judges that this cannot possibly happen. Thus when someone dreams that something disgraceful happens to him, he believes that he is dreaming. Also, sometimes memory becomes actual, and when someone judges about something past that it is present and remembers that it is past, then he judges that this is a dream, and thus he is not unaware of the deception. When, however, the superior capacity is fettered, then he is unaware of the deception.34
In addition to Aristotle’s standard examples of dreams about men or horses, Brito considers the case of monstrous or incoherent dreams (that is, bizarre dreams) which relates to Aristotle’s discussion of deformed and fragmentary dreams in De insomniis 3, 461a8–25. Brito’s idea is that if the intellect is operating properly, the dreamer may notice that something is terrible and supposedly unrealistic (in the sense of being highly unlikely). In a similar vein, if something disgraceful happens to the dreamer (for example fornication), then he is inclined to believe that he is dreaming. In addition, Brito makes an interesting claim about memory. He suggests that if a superior capacity happens to be operational in the state of sleep, for example, if the subject remembers that the dream concerns a friend who passed away some time ago, this superior assessment is sufficient for the subject to reject the apparent reality of the dream. Brito’s account is a reasonable interpretation even if Aristotle’s explicit account of ‘monstrous dreams’ is more focused on how such dreams emerge, not how the dreamer responds to such dreams or what is required in order to be able to identify them as strange or incredible.
Finally, we may note that Brito does not make any distinction between fully developed beliefs and non-doxastic forms of unreflecting trust. He simply says that, in sleep, the likeness of Coriscus (the phántasma) is believed to be the real Coriscus, if the function of superior cognitive capacities such as memory or intellect is restrained. Even so, Brito explains the phenomenon of delusional dreaming by a reference to absent superior cognitive assessments, following Aristotle in the assumption that our highest actual cognitive assessments will be taken as authoritative when superior cognitive assessments for some reason are inaccessible. For instance, the intellect may reveal that a dream is illusory, but also memory can contradict and expose the false nature of dreams. Thus, the novel element in Brito’s contribution is that he provides an account of how the sleeper may be deceived by dreams that are odd or incredible.
6 Modern Philosophy on Delusional Dreaming
6.1 Descartes: Deception in Sleep and Waking and the Question of Dream-Belief
In the early modern period Descartes reintroduced the ancient theme of dream-scepticism – widely known as the argument from dreaming.35 Descartes stresses the illusory nature of dreams and raises the problem of how we can know that what appears to be an ordinary experience in waking is not really a dream. The argument from dreaming, in various formulations, is discussed by Descartes mainly as an epistemological problem involving the quest for criteria that guarantee certain knowledge. Nonetheless, one strand in Descartes’ discussion concerns the deceptive nature of dreams. In a well-known passage in the First Meditation Descartes suggests that dreams are unreliable because they occasionally mimic plain experiences in waking. However, it might be useful to highlight some divergences between Descartes’ dream-scepticism and Aristotle’s analysis of delusional dreaming. First, Descartes does not pay any special attention to the fact that dreaming and waking exemplify two radically different states of cognition – at least not explicitly. For instance, Descartes does not seem to endorse the view that we are likely to be deceived about the true nature of our experiences in sleep but not in waking, which is one of Aristotle’s basic assumptions. Second, a tacit supposition in Descartes’ discussion of dream-scepticism is that the capacity for belief-formation is intact in the dream-state. This assumption, as we have seen, is explicitly rejected by Aristotle. Descartes’ and Aristotle’s opposing views on dream-belief will be an important backdrop to more recent discussions on whether genuine belief-formation is possible in the state of sleep – discussions which otherwise may appear more or less obscure.
Let us now turn to an early modern account that more directly resembles Aristotle’s idea that sensory experience is taken as real in the absence of information to the contrary.
6.2 Spinoza: Revisiting Aristotle
In a passage in the Ethics, Spinoza highlights a kind of unreflecting trust that is characteristic for the dream-state – a notion that strongly reflects Aristotle’s conception of a non-doxastic form of trust as described in De insomniis:
So this may be clearly understood, let us conceive a boy imagining a winged horse, and perceiving nothing else. Since this imagination involves the existence of the horse (by Prop. 17, Coroll., Part 2) and the body perceives nothing that takes away the existence of the horse, he will necessarily regard the horse as present, nor will he be able to doubt of its existence, even though he is not certain of it. We experience this daily in dreams, and I do not believe that there is anyone who thinks that, whilst he is dreaming, he has a free power of suspending his judgement about that of which he dreams, and of bringing it about that he does not dream what he dreams he sees. Nevertheless, it happens that even in dreams we suspend judgement, namely when we dream that we are dreaming. Further, I grant that nobody is deceived in so far as he perceives; that is, I grant that the imaginations of the mind, considered in themselves, involve no error (see Prop. 17, Schol., Part 2). But I deny that a man affirms nothing in so far as he perceives. For what is it to perceive a winged horse, other than to affirm wings of a horse? For if the mind were to perceive nothing other than a winged horse, it would regard the horse as present to it, and would have no cause of doubt about its existence and no faculty of dissent, unless its imagination of the winged horse were joined to an idea which takes away the existence of that horse, or because it perceives that the idea of the winged horse that it has is inadequate. Then it will either necessarily negate the existence of the horse, or it will necessarily doubt it.36
Thus, if the mind perceives nothing but a winged horse, then there is nothing that may provide a ground for doubt or disbelief, and so the presence or existence of the horse will be taken for granted. Supposing that the mind perceives nothing but a winged horse, a kind of affirmation of the perceived object’s existence will follow from the mere awareness of it.
Spinoza’s view involves some ideas that resemble Aristotle’s account of delusional dreaming: for instance, (1) there is a compelling type of awareness that includes (a) an apprehension of the imagined horse as real, (b) the inability to doubt its existence or suspend judgement,37 (c) even if there is no certainty of what is apprehended (“certainty” here refers to something that is the result of intellectual assessment). Thus, perceiving (understood to include imagination) considered in isolation from other cognitive features conveys an element of trust in what is perceived. (2) Doubt and disbelief require grounds, and since the awareness of the winged horse is the sole cognitive assessment, without any competing evaluation, the presence of a winged horse is taken as real. A point concerning the example including a winged horse that easily goes unnoticed is that even when such incredible things as winged horses are apprehended, they are apprehended as real. We may also note that Spinoza’s example reflects Radulphus Brito’s discussion of the cognitive conditions that make the dreamer inclined to experience dreams as real even when dreams are completely incoherent or absurd (cf. section three).
6.3 Late Modern Adaptations of the Principle of Unreflecting Trust
A version of Spinoza’s account appears in William James’ Principles of Psychology. James elaborates on the idea of unreflecting trust as a result of absent contradictory information, and his immediate source appears to be Spinoza’s Ethics. He discusses the idea in very general terms – not specifically in the context of delusional dreaming – and makes no explicit reference to Aristotle. James gives a rather general characterisation of belief in terms of a mental state that involves some degree of assuredness, certainty, or conviction.38 Belief, or a sense of reality is a feeling close to an emotion of conviction.39 James maintains that the true psychological opposites of belief are doubt and inquiry, not disbelief,40 and he rhetorically asks what it would mean if a simple apprehension of something were to be considered as not real:
Suppose a new-born mind, entirely blank and waiting for experience to begin. Suppose that it begins in the form of a visual impression (whether faint or vivid is immaterial) of a lighted candle against a dark background, and nothing else, so that whilst this image lasts it constitutes the entire universe known to the mind in question. Suppose moreover (to simplify the hypothesis), that the candle is only imagery, and that no “original” of it is recognized by us psychologists outside. Will this hallucinatory candle be believed in, will it have a real existence for the mind?
What possible sense (for that mind) would a suspicion have that the candle was not real? What would doubt or disbelief of it imply?41
James concludes:
The sense that anything we think of is unreal can only come, then, when that thing is contradicted by some other thing of which we think. Any object which remains uncontradicted is ipso facto believed and posited as absolute reality.42
The most basic forms of belief occur when there is no contradictory information that opposes the existence of the object of awareness. Such primitive beliefs in the reality or existence of something do not involve some reference to some special property or quality that makes it real. Rather, any object of awareness, in the absence of contradictory information, will be apprehended as real. The idea here is that primitive unreflecting trust does not imply fully developed belief, while doubt and disbelief imply a fully operational ability to form beliefs.
James considers a case in which we apprehend something in an epistemically detached way and on the basis of rational evaluation make an affirmative or critical judgement:
The having and the crediting of an idea do not always coalesce; for often we first suppose and then believe; first play with the notion, frame the hypothesis, and then affirm the existence, of an object of thought. And we are quite conscious of the succession of the two mental acts. But these cases are none of them primitive cases. They only occur in minds long schooled to doubt by the contradictions of experience. The primitive impulse is to affirm immediately the reality of all that is conceived.43
Now, cases of detached sober rational assessment are cognitively sophisticated whereas the primitive mode of apprehension of something as real is not. James maintains that there is a general inclination to believe, and that we have to learn to distrust on the basis of contradictions in our experiences. It is only when contradictions and discrepancies are recognised that there is a need to resolve the felt cognitive tension.44
A few decades later, Bertrand Russell examines James’ theory of unreflecting assent in The Analysis of Mind:
If this is correct, it follows (though James does not draw the inference) that there is no need of any specific feeling called ‘belief,’ and that the mere existence of images yields all that is required. The state of mind in which we merely consider a proposition, without believing or disbelieving it will then appear as a sophisticated product, the result of some rival force adding to the image-proposition a positive feeling which may be called suspense or non-belief – a feeling which may be compared to that of a man about to run a race waiting for the signal. Such a man, though not moving, is in a very different condition from that of a man quietly at rest. And so the man who is considering a proposition without believing it will be in a state of tension, restraining the natural tendency to act upon the proposition which he would display if nothing interfered. In this view belief primarily consists merely in the existence of the appropriate images without any counteracting forces.
There is a great deal to be said in favour of this view, and I have some hesitation in regarding it as inadequate. It fits admirably with the phenomena of dreams and hallucinatory images, and it is recommended by the way in which it accords with mental development. Doubt, suspense of judgement and disbelief all seem later and more complex than a wholly unreflecting assent. Belief as a positive phenomenon, if it exists, may be regarded, in this view, as a product of doubt, a decision after debate, an acceptance, not merely of this, but of this-rather-than-that.45
Russell seems to agree with James that some simple forms of awareness entail a belief-like trust, and he mentions dreams and hallucinations as examples of such unreflecting assent. In cases where there is neither uncertainty nor doubt there is a naïve trust, whereas uncertainty and doubt are the products of rational considerations. Even if Russell is sympathetic to the idea that some states like dreaming involve an unreflecting trust, such states should not be conflated with fully developed beliefs.46 It seems as if Russell comes very close to a plausible interpretation of Aristotle’s position. Rudimentary belief-like phenomena may occur in the absence of contradictory information, for example, in dreams, but full-fledged beliefs are the outcome of a rational choice of this over that, and such judgements require something more advanced than a form of unreflecting trust that is the outcome of a simple awareness of something.
7 Contemporary Views
In this section I shall broaden the scope to some extent and include contemporary views on delusional dreaming, not only explained in terms of an unreflecting trust. I shall highlight two themes that have an Aristotelian origin even if the Aristotelian connection is quite obscure in the contemporary context. The first theme is dreaming understood as a case of imagination as opposed to perception. Another idea is the view that the dream-state comprises no genuine belief. As we will see, this latter issue is entangled with the question in what sense, if any, a dream can fully deceive the dreamer to the extent that the dream is mistaken for a real ongoing event. In the final part of the paper I argue in favour of an Aristotelian explanation of delusional dreaming opposed to rival explanations in the recent literature.
7.1 Imagination Theories of Dreaming
There are a variety of views that reject the idea that dreaming involves a false apprehension of reality. As we have seen, appearing real and also trusting the dream to be real are prominent elements in many accounts of delusional dreaming (Aristotle, Spinoza, James, and so forth).
A number of theories that we may call imagination theories challenge the traditional idea of deception in dreaming. The label “imagination theory” of dreaming minimally entails that dreams are conceived as imaginations in the sense of being internal manifestations of a sensory character that are distinct from perception proper and are under voluntary control. It is often maintained that imaginations occur in the form of unfolding sequences of events or stories. Further, most imagination theorists stress that imaginations should not be conflated with other cognitive functions like belief. A central idea in many contemporary conceptions of imagination is that we can imagine arbitrary events, for example, that we travel to the planet Mars. However, it is sometimes supposed that acts of imagination also may seemingly emulate primitive forms of trust, for example, trust that we really encounter the things that we imagine. Exactly what this means will be discussed in detail below.
A quick comparison between the notion of “imagination” as used by modern imagination theories and Aristotle’s conceptions of phantasía (the faculty of imagination) and phántasma (sensory replication in any sense-modality) reveals a superficial resemblance, but Aristotle’s conception of imagination merely partially overlaps with contemporary conceptions of the term. According to Aristotle, dreams are perceptual remnants that emerge through phantasía. Sensory after-effects and re-activations (so-called phantásmata) occur under different cognitive circumstances, for example, in cases of misperception, in relation to thinking and memory, and in sleep in the form of dreams. Aristotle contrasts imagination (phantasía) with belief (dóxa), arguing that belief is involuntary whereas imagination, at least in waking, conforms to our will.47 Elsewhere in De insomniis Aristotle says that dreaming is the work of the perceptual part, but belongs to this part in its imagining capacity.48 So even if imagination is distinct from perception, they are closely related, which explains why imagination appears in a perception-like guise. One point of divergence between Aristotle’s and modern conceptions of imagination is that Aristotle’s notion of phántasma is object-oriented whereas modern theories of imagination often emphasise the narrative-like products of imagination.
However, there are at least two noteworthy correspondences between Aristotle’s conception and modern conceptions of imagination. First, both notions of imagination are regarded as strictly distinct from other cognitive attitudes such as belief. Still, imagination may under some circumstances superficially mimic something akin to a state of unreflecting trust or belief. Even so, it is quite difficult to determine to what extent modern imagination-theories are influenced by Aristotelian ideas of, for instance, non-doxastic belief-like phenomena or whether they are responses to Cartesian assumptions about intact belief-formation in the state of sleep.
However, to what extent modern imagination-theories oppose the tenets of the orthodox view varies – tenets such as (1a) that dreams appear in a way similar to the way perceptions appear during waking, or (1b) that dreams are percepts, and that (2a) dreams involve a misapprehension of reality or (2b) that dreams involve beliefs in the reality of the dream. I shall argue that some imagination theories fail to provide an account that accords with the widespread assumption that dreams in most cases are apprehended as real. Imagination theories that explain the dreamer’s absorption in a dream as the sort of immersion we undergo when, for instance, we read a story, seem better equipped to explain ambiguous states that are on the brink of delusional dreaming than they are to explain fully-developed delusional states.
As we saw, the orthodox view characterises dreams as perception-like experiences. Aristotle explains the perception-like nature of dreams by assuming that they are remnants of proper sense-impressions that no longer indicate the presence of real-world objects. In the modern discussions there is some disagreement on how to articulate the distinction between image and percept. However, the proponents of the so-called orthodox view quite often characterise dreams as perception-like experiences, but not necessarily perceptions, a description that refers to how dreams appear to the subject in the dream-state. The issue of how images relate to percepts remains controversial.49 Part of the problem is the lack of standardised definitions of ‘imagination’ and ‘percept.’ In any event, a plausible theory should be able to account for the perception-like appearance of dreams, even if dreams are not considered to be ‘percepts’ according to very restricted applications of the term.
7.2 Fascination and Fictional Immersion
Sartre presents an intriguing theory that aims to show that the dreamer does not believe his dreams to be real events – the dreamer is rather compelled to attend to the dream by means of a narrow-minded consciousness. Dreaming is characterised by a spellbinding attention to unreal imaginations.50 Sartre makes it clear that when we are caught up in imagination this is not a misapprehension of reality. According to him, the dreamer cannot apprehend the dream-image as real since he has lost the very conception of reality. This view is difficult to accept for a variety of reasons. For instance, if the notion of reality is lost, there seems to be no awareness of the experience as unreal either, which seems to make the experience neither real nor illusory. Yet Sartre clings to the idea that the dreamer is in some sense aware of the dream as an illusory image.
Sartre describes dream-consciousness as similar to the spell-bound state of our consciousness when we are absorbed in reading a fictional story: we buy into the story we are reading, but we are not mistaking it for real events. Colin McGinn presents a view that recalls of Sartre’s theory. McGinn calls this theory the “immersion theory of dreaming.” He writes:
Just as your mind cannot wander from your daydreams and expect them to proceed by themselves, so it cannot wander from your dream images – and the reason in both cases is the attention-dependence of the imagination. This explains the enthralling character of dreams, the single-mindedness of the dream state. It is not that dreams are somehow intrinsically fascinating so gripping that you cannot take your mind off them; on the contrary, they can be quite boring in the retelling. It is that they de facto have a monopoly on the attention. Since they are constituted by the attention, they are not the kind of thing from which the attention might wander. Their fascination for the dreaming consciousness is therefore an artifact of their constitutive nature, not a reflection of the narrative powers of their author.51
This idea reflects Sartre’s assumption that the reality perspective is absent in the dream-state. Thus, the dreamer is unable to be aware of the narrow-mindedness of the dream-state as opposed to the broader state of awareness that characterises waking consciousness. Yet Sartre maintains that the dreamer is not fooled by the illusory nature of the dream.
7.3 Do Dreamers Believe Their Dreams?
Sartre argues that no matter how caught up the dreamer is in his dreams, he has some rudimentary awareness that the dreams are mere images. In other words, he does not believe the dream. Sartre writes:
Here it is necessary to characterize the degree of belief of consciousness in the imaginary worlds, or if you prefer the “weight” of these worlds. Let us return to Mlle B …’s dream. The sole fact that the dream is given as a story should permit us to understand the kind of belief that we can attribute to it. But the dreamer instructs us still better, she tells us that she believed she was reading this story. What does she mean, if not that the story is presented to her with the same type of interest and credibility as that of a read story? Reading is a kind of fascination, and when I read a detective story I believe in what I read. But this does not signify in the least that I cease to hold the detective’s adventures to be imaginary. Simply, an entire world appears to me as imaged through the lines of the book (I have already shown that the words serve as an analogon) and this world encloses my consciousness, I cannot disengage, I am fascinated by it. This is the kind of fascination without positing existence that I call belief.52
Sartre seems to argue that the enchanting fascination that characterises the dream-state should not be understood as an affirmative belief that what is dreamt is real. The dreamer rather accepts the dream as he might accept a story in a novel. We play along with the story in a sort of make-believe, yet we know that the dream-story is unreal.
Sartre may be right, given a particular interpretation: perhaps the dream exhibits no explicit or conscious claims of reality, that is, the dreamer does not explicitly think “This is real.” The dreamer may misapprehend the reality of the dream nevertheless. It is difficult to see how the state of fascination, in its most developed and compelling form, does not imply a misapprehension of reality. Sartre explains that what might appear as certain mental attitudes in dreams (for example beliefs) are really imagined fake imitations of real beliefs. But then, does not an ersatz-belief that the dream is real amount to the very same thing as real belief that the dream is real, namely, deception about the true nature of the dream?
Just like Sartre, McGinn maintains that the dreamer is not misapprehending his experiences as real events. He writes:
The attraction of this theory is obvious: it reconciles the image theory of dreams with the phenomenon of dream belief. While I am immersed in a novel, I am not under the strange delusion that the marks on paper are real events that I am observing; I know that I am only reading a book, not witnessing the events described in it. Nor do I mistake the images that form in my mind for belief-inviting percepts. Yet I am able to enter into the story to such a degree that my emotions may be stirred, rather as if I were witnessing these events. Perhaps even closer to the dream, when am I watching a film I do not confuse the images on the screen with real events; nor do I mistake my prompted imaginings for reality. Yet I may find myself so absorbed that my state of mind mimics real belief and feeling; I “enter into” the story. Similarly, in a dream I am not under the illusion that the images are percepts – I am implicitly aware (in some sense) that they are not – yet I am able to enter into the dream fiction in such a way as to become emotionally affected. I am not confused about the status of dream experiences; it is just that the dream images can draw me into a fictional world in such a way as to engage my cognitive and affective faculties. So engrossed am I by the dream story that I give my assent to it – or go into a state that is very similar to ordinary assent. Fictional immersion stimulates belief.53
McGinn claims that we are not confused about the illusory nature of dream-experiences. Even if there is no genuine misapprehension of reality in dreaming, why does the dreamer not react appropriately in response to bizarre and incredible features of dreaming? McGinn explains:
I know very well that the actor on the stage is not about to stab the other actor, but I ‘believe’ that he is. I become absorbed in a novel in which a certain world leader has been assassinated, but I know very well that he has not. I am hypnotized into believing that I am a barking dog, but part of me knows that this is rubbish. The dreamer’s tolerance of inconsistency is therefore not some kind of preternatural irrationality or disregard for logic; it is simply the correlative of fictional immersion.54
The tolerance for incredible elements is explained as an effect of playing along with the story; it is not a kind of acceptance that the dream is believable or real.
Nevertheless, McGinn seems to accept that dream-immersion may stimulate belief. But these are not really beliefs, they are more like quasi-beliefs.55 McGinn writes:
We should not make the mistake of supposing that everything we call ‘belief’ fits some chosen paradigm of belief – say, assenting to a sentence when confronted by a sensory stimulus. Beliefs come in a great many forms everything from beliefs about perceived matters, to ethical beliefs, to theoretical beliefs, to religious beliefs (‘faith’), to dream beliefs.56
And a few pages earlier:
I noted earlier that dream fear is not quite the same as real fear; it doesn’t have quite the clout of real fear. And dream belief is not quite as committed as ordinary belief; there is some kind of holding back or reservation about it. It is very hard to characterize exactly what this involves, but the point I want to make now is that the same kind of holding back applies to the emotions felt in ordinary fictional immersion. The belief and emotion of fictional immersion are quasi-belief and quasi-emotion (whatever this may ultimately come to).57
McGinn seems to follow Sartre here when he claims that quasi-believing is something like going along with the story without strictly believing that it is true. The main weakness of this view is that it does not correspond to how people normally experience their dreams. For example, there seems to be no holding back when we are in the grip of horrifying nightmares. On the contrary, we psychologically respond to dreams as if the events dreamed of are really happening. Perhaps the reluctance to accept the idea of deception in dreaming relies on the assumption that the state of sleep disables belief-formation and that deception requires belief. However, to assume a kind of holding back seems to be a high price to pay given the almost universal experience that the dream-state in most cases deceives us (see note 1 above).
Jonathan Ichikawa, on the other hand, seems to argue that the dreamer is completely deceived regarding the reality of the dream, at least implicitly, but that this is not a belief, strictly speaking.58 Ichikawa’s stance on deception depends on how the phrase “as if you are really there” is interpreted. He writes:
Lose yourself enough in your daydream, and you will feel, in some sense, as if you are really there. That’s not to say you falsely believe the contents of the daydream to be true. Our dreams in sleep are, on the imagination model, like that.59
Ernest Sosa, along the same line of thought, introduces the notion of make-believe,60 as a substitute for proper belief and just like Itchikawa he also seems to accept that deception does not imply belief.61
When something happens in my dream, reality tends not to follow suit. When in my dream I am chased by a lion, this poses no threat to my skin. No physical proposition about the layout of the world around me is true in actuality just because it is true in my dream. What about mental propositions about how it is in my own mind? Must any such proposition be true in actuality whenever it is true in my dream? No, even if in my dream I believe that a lion is after me, and even if in my dream I intend to keep running, in actuality I have no such belief or intention. What is in question is the inference from <in my dream I believe (or intend) such and such> to <In actuality I so believe (or intend)>.62
In sum, the contemporary proponents of imagination-theories all circle around the same idea of being caught up in a dream and introduce a set of notions that are meant to substitute for proper instances of belief. The relevant notions include “fascination,” “immersion,” “quasi-belief,” and “make-belief.”
How then is imagination supposed to mimic belief? The idea seems to be that imaginations may simulate the occurrence of a variety of cognitive attitudes. So, when quasi – or pseudo – beliefs occur in dreams they are empty, ghostly replicas of the real thing. The difference between proper belief and imagined belief is as great as that between imagining the Eiffel Tower and perceiving the real Eiffel Tower. So when in the dream I take the horse I experience to be real, I do not really believe it to be real, I just imagine myself to believe it to be real.63 Conversely, when I perceive the real Eiffel Tower I can form proper beliefs about the Eiffel Tower, for example, that it is real and not just some optical illusion. So, according to one interpretation of Ichikawa’s and Sosa’s accounts, “imagining x to be real” as this occurs in dreaming has the same practical consequence of deception as-if this was really believed, even if it is not. Let us now take a closer look at some theorists’ reluctance to accept that the dreamer is deceived with regard to the reality of the dream.
As we have seen, the assumption that dream subjects are never completely deceived about the reality of the dream conflicts with ordinary experiences of dreaming. Even so, the imagination theory seems well suited to explain borderline cases between delusional awareness and lucidity, that is, ambiguous awareness of a dream’s reality, such as the awareness that there is something strange about the dream that is difficult to articulate while we remain in the dream-state. For example, I have often dreamed of interacting with people who have passed away. In such dreams, at some points, I have felt that something is wrong, as if a part of me knows that the current dream contradicts known facts. On a charitable reading, this ‘feeling that something is wrong’ might correspond to McGinn’s description that something is holding us back in dreaming. As mentioned, Sartre and McGinn deny complete deception and assume some degree of lucidity in every case of dreaming. However, the occurrence of borderline cases between delusional dreaming and lucidity does not rule out dream-states in which the subject is completely deceived about the illusory nature of the dream.64 So, are people mistaken when they say that they are deceived by the realistic appearance of dreams? If Sartre and McGinn are right, people merely say that they mistake dreams for real events, but they do not really.
Let us sum up some of the points made by proponents of imagination theories of dreaming and their stance on the question of delusional dreaming. (1) Are we deceived (or deluded) about the reality of the dream? Sartre: No, not really, but we are immersed in the dream by the narrow-minded consciousness that constitutes dreaming. Something in us is aware of the dream as an unreal imagination. McGinn: No, there is a holding back of the kind we experience when we are immersed in fictions. Yet, immersion can stimulate belief-like attitudes. Ichikawa: Yes, we can be deceived, it is as if we really are at the place we dream about, but we do not strictly speaking believe it. Sosa: Yes, we respond to the dream as real without believing it, because in dreaming we are unable to believe that the dream is real by means of proper belief.
One detail that divides modern imagination theories is the issue of whether deception occurs at all. Now, all the discussed varieties of imagination theories presuppose that beliefs are ruled out regardless of whether the dreamer is deceived. Sartre and McGinn reject the possibility of deception whereas Ichikawa and Sosa seem to accept a form of deception that is not based on belief. The latter position, apparently involves a kind of immersion in dreams that approximates the non-doxastic view that has been attributed to Aristotle in this paper.
7.4 Owen Flanagan: Delusional Dreaming through Absent Metacognition
Owen Flanagan, a philosopher in the contemporary analytical tradition, presents an account of delusional dreaming that comes close to Aristotle’s view that the kind of unreflecting trust that is characteristic for dreaming is a consequence of the temporary shut-down of a set of higher cognitive functions. He writes:
Another way in which dreams differ from wakefulness is this. Many philosophers, thinking they follow Descartes – take for example, Russell’s claim that the awake and dreamed thoughts of the ruined church are ‘intrinsically indistinguishable’ from each other – think that the fact that often we cannot tell we are dreaming when we are dreaming is because dreams seem as real as real can seem. One reason dreams seem so real is related to the point just made: our metacognitive powers are typically turned way down in dreams and thus so are our judgemental capacities to perceive incongruities, uncertainties, and discontinuities as odd while they are occurring. Perceiving that such things are odd is hard, since perceiving them as odd requires layering thoughts, for example, having the thought that one is flying while also having the thought that people can’t fly. We understand from a neurophysiological perspective why we are better able to think metacognitively when we are awake than asleep. But in any case, the fact that dreams seem so real while we are dreaming that we cannot tell that we are not awake does not imply that dream mentation is just like awake mentation in terms, say, of vivacity or along other phenomenological dimensions.65
Flanagan highlights an important detail: we can be deceived about the reality of dreams even if they are very unlike ordinary perceptions we have in the state of waking. For example, it may be the case that dreams are less vivid than perceptual experiences and that they typically deviate from perceptions in a number of distinctive ways. Moreover, dreams often display unrealistic content that does not correspond to waking experiences (cf. section two on different senses of ‘appearing real’ above): it is as if we are unable to detect vital differences between dreams and waking consciousness while we remain in the deficient mode of cognition that is characteristic of the dream-state. Differently put, we are not necessarily deceived by the dream because it mimics waking experiences to some degree; rather, the dreamer mistakes the dream for reality because of the altered cognitive state he is in, not because the dream in itself is indistinguishable from waking experience.
Flanagan observes that in order to be aware of (1) incongruities (e.g., having a conversation with a duck on the campus lawn), (2) uncertainties (a person may look like a known person but is at the same time felt to have some different or indeterminate identity), and (3) discontinuities (my dream-self undergoes rapid shifts in location – in one moment I am in Europe another moment I am in the Americas), as odd, we have to have layered thought. In other words, we have to have thoughts about thoughts (cf. Brito’s view of the role of the intellect in delusional dreaming). In the dream-state we seem to be unable to assess content in a rational way through the firmly held beliefs we have established in the state of wakefulness. Thus, it is the absence of metacognitive assessments that explains why the subject mistakes the dream for reality.
Flanagan’s explanation of delusional dreaming comes close to Aristotle’s account because the delusional appearance of reality is a mere effect caused by the inactivity of certain supervising cognitive capacities. However, unlike Aristotle, Flanagan explicitly discusses the inability to detect irrational and atypical events and unfolding of events. Another important difference between the two accounts is that Aristotle stresses the similarity between dreams and perception, whereas Flanagan emphases their differences.
7.5 Jennifer Windt: Unreflecting Trust, Deception, and Adoxastic Dream-States
Jennifer Windt offers a very rich account and I shall only consider her take on dream-deception in relation to the notion of unreflecting trust. Just like Flanagan, Windt makes a distinction between deception based on phenomenal resemblance and deception due to cognitive impairment. She introduces the notion of doxastic situatedness, and beliefs are said to be paradigmatic cases of doxastic situatedness. She then explains:
Doxastic situatedness refers to exactly those attitude types that carry with them particular epistemic commitments. If I believe or affirm that p, I am convinced or firmly assume that p, and so on, then I am thereby committed to the truth of p. This commitment influences how I subsequently reason or act on p. If I am strongly convinced of a particular theoretical claim, I will defend it against objections; and if I clearly remember having left my keys in my purse, I will search for them there when needed, which deplorably is not always the most direct path to success.66
Windt’s main point seems to be that some dreams exhibit no doxastic situatedness at all, not even in the form of a rudimentary unreflecting trust. Such dream-states are considered to be doxastically undetermined and are adoxastic in nature. In fact, Windt argues that a majority of dreams are of this adoxastic character. She writes:
A new way of saying that dreams are deceptive, then, is to say that dreaming is a state of doxastic disorientation: dreams mislocalize us in our doxastic framework by preventing access to long-standing beliefs or memories, but also by temporarily enticing us to endorse new ones. Dreams are, literally, misleading experiences. In the Cartesian scenario of dream-deception, the dreamer believes or affirms propositions such as ‘I am awake,’ ‘I am really holding this piece of paper in my hands and not just dreaming that I am,’ and so on. The dream self is now doxasticially situated toward the content of these propositions in the manner of believing of affirming their truth. Again, not all dream cogitations involve doxastic situatedness, and only a subgroup that do will affect how one is situated toward the fact that one is now dreaming. If dream beliefs can occur in isolation, as argued in section 9.6, then believing, in a dream, that my mother has grown a beard does not entail that I thereby take myself to be awake. Other dream-beliefs will undermine one’s prior doxastic position without substituting a new one. One can be doxastically situated toward the proposition I am awake’ by simply doubting its truth. In this case one will no longer believe that one is awake, but one will also not believe that one is dreaming. What is essential for dream deception, then, is being doxastically situated toward a certain type of content, expressed in propositions about one’s current state of consciousness and the reality of ongoing experience, in a manner that is at odds with the actual truth or falsity of the respective propositions.67
Windt suggests that dreams are deceptive in a special sense because they do not stimulate adequate doxastic attitudes in the way that waking experiences do. Nevertheless, she also suggests that a large class of dreams lack any doxastic element – they do not include even rudimentary forms of unreflecting trust – and therefore these cases do not involve deception, strictly speaking, because deception requires at least some minimal degree of doxastic situatedness. So, a mistake about the reality of a dream requires that this reality is affirmed, no matter how simple such affirmations are.
Windt challenges a central element in the Aristotelian account of the mistaken reality of dreams, namely, that unreflecting trust automatically results from the simple awareness of a sense-impression. Instead, she argues that an awareness of p as such does not imply blind trust in p because of the absence of opposing considerations. She writes:
What about intermediate states between doxastic indeterminacy and doxastic situatedness? A possible objection to my account is that dreams involve unquestioning assent rather than full-fledged belief and that this is enough for deception. For instance, Reed while granting that ‘ordinary dreams involve no considered opinion or strongly appraisive belief’ (Reed, 1979, p. 45), argues that the concept of taking for granted should be applied to dreaming. Here “the dimension of appraisal is minimal … and the possibility of deception is assured” (pp. 43–44) since one can take something for granted that is false. According to Reed, this is enough to vindicate the traditional view: “Ordinary dreaming involve belief, in the perhaps extended or uncommon sense of ‘taking for granted’ ” (p. 44).
To this, I would respond that taking for granted, or unreflected assent, may well be a precursor to more sophisticated forms of belief. The distinction between doxastic indeterminacy and doxastic situatedness is intended to be not sharp but gradual. Taking something for granted in a dream – for instance, that this is not a dream, but is really happening – is a simple and unarticulated form of doxastically situating oneself toward the fact that one is now dreaming. In doing so, one fulfils the condition for the simplest form of deception. What I would question, however, is that we should ascribe even this simple form of belief to dreams in the absence of any positive evidence. Rather, it might be useful to distinguish such cases of taking for granted from doxastically indeterminate dreams. The concept of doxastic indeterminacy makes room for the possibility that experience does not automatically invite beliefs and does not per se involve even a primitive form of belief such as taking for granted.68
Windt’s reference to adoxastic states may superficially appear to involve a quite non-committing position. However, it is not clear what the claim that most dreams are adoxastic amounts to. For instance, we may ask (1) are there adoxastic dream-states, and (2) if there are, how many dreams have this adoxastic character, and (3) do such states involve any kind of deception? I shall argue that the average awareness of dreams involves a form of unreflecting trust in the reality of the dream. The proposed view challenges Windt’s position which claims that most instances of dreaming lack any doxastic element no matter how rudimentary it is assumed to be. In my view, if the dream seems to take place in the real world and this appearance is not questioned in any way, then there is deception about the reality of the dream. On the other hand, rudimentary forms of unreflecting trust do not imply articulated beliefs like “This is real” or “I am not sleeping.” Dreams may be taken to be real, not necessarily through a conscious judgement that what is experienced is real, but indirectly by viewing events as if appearing in the world and not noticing that one is asleep. This implicit apprehension of the dream as real is sufficient for deception regarding the reality of the dream.
Let us examine Windt’s assumption of alleged adoxastic states in dreaming. What does it mean to be aware of a dream yet remain neutral to how the dream appears? Is it a disengaged attitude of “going through the motions”? Is it a completely neutral apprehension of a dream with regard to its realistic qualities? Is it like watching a movie but not responding to what is seen with actions or emotions? Or does it simply mean that the realistic features of a given dream are not reported upon awakening? For example, would my dream of my friend D reading on the campus lawn qualify as such an adoxastic state? I do not apprehend the dream as real in any conscious significant way at all. While dreaming, I am just completely caught up in the situation here and now. I did not explicitly think: “This is real,” and I did not disbelieve that it was an occurrence in the world. It seems right that there is no deception of reality in delusional dreaming that matches sophisticated cases where we sincerely wonder: “Are my sensory appearances deceiving me?” In my dream there was not even any consciously articulated conception of reality, only a tacit, intuitive sense of reality. In fact, deceptions of reality do not seem to require any articulated concept of reality. Imagine a cat being deceived about chasing an unreal mouse while dreaming. If a cat can be deceived by a dream it seems unreasonable to suppose that deception requires the cognitive resources to articulate conceptually sophisticated attitudes about reality as “reality.”
The dreamer is not only deceived about the true nature of the things dreamt of, the dreamer is also deceived about the cognitive states that monitors the events in the dream. This move turns things back to the endorsed interpretation of Aristotle and suggests in just how deflated a sense ‘unreflecting trust’ ought to be understood. It is a tacit unreflecting trust that things are really happening in the world, not in the form of articulated doxastic attitudes like “This has to be real,” “This really appears real,” or “I am truly convinced that this is real,” but rather in an unquestioned intuitive yet prominent sense of reality that is not the result of any top-down processing.
It seems like Windt’s discussion disregards the detail that dreams can appear to be real and that appearances play a vital role in accounts of why dreams are apprehended as real. Now, to uncritically take dreams at face value is not a matter of intellectual processing. But why then do dreams present themselves as real rather than neutral or unreal? Here is one answer. Perception paradigmatically gives us immediate and intuitive access to the world. Sensory imaginings of the kind we entertain in the state of waking do not really indicate the presence of real-world objects, yet their existence is parasitic on proper perceptual states. Dreams along with imaginations mimic the characteristic format of perception that things take place in a world and thereby emulate the realistic appearance of perception. The illusion of reality that is inherent in imagination is less prominent when we perceive the world around us and conversely the illusion of reality in imagination and dreaming is increased the more perception, and other higher cognitive functions are deprived.
8 Conclusion
A non-doxastic interpretation of Aristotle was proposed along the lines of Gregoric’s account in this volume, in which deception in dreaming manifest itself as a compelling state of unreflecting trust in appearances (phantásmata) that is distinguished from believing the dream to be real (dóxa). This forced mode of deception warrants a characterisation of the condition as delusional due to a deficient state of cognition. The dream is cognised as real and its reality cannot be doubted or disbelieved, for any reason, as long as the higher cognitive functions that enable critical examination are restrained.
Similar notions of rudimentary forms of unreflective trust have been used for different purposes among the ancient sceptics. Further, Aristotle’s theory was discussed and slightly developed by commentators in the medieval West such as Radulphus Brito. Later in early modern times, something very close to the view of Aristotle’s conception of unreflecting trust presented reappears in Spinoza and is discussed by William James and Bertrand Russell.
Moreover, a wide range of modern imagination theories claim that fully developed beliefs cannot be formed in dreaming. Some imagination theories deny that dreaming involves deception, presumably because deception seems to require belief, whereas other imagination theories accept deception but without belief. The latter type of imagination theories echo Aristotle’s view in the proposed interpretation.
Finally, I have argued against the adoxastic view, namely, the idea that many dreams are doxastically neutral and therefore cannot involve deception strictly speaking. On the contrary, I maintain that the dreamer frequently is deceived about the reality of the dream even if this form of deception does not include articulated beliefs or thoughts of the kind “This is really real,” “This has to be real,” or “I am certain that I am not asleep.” Minimally, it is sufficient to be deceived about the reality of dreams indirectly by not being aware of that one is currently asleep or by a misidentification of the dream-world as the perceived world. However, unlike Aristotle I endorse a wider conception of ‘appearing real’ that does not necessarily include a faithful replication of ordinary perceptual states in waking.
Acknowledgements
I especially want to thank David Bennett, Peter Adamson, Mika Perälä, Miira Tuominen, Stephen Menn, and the members of the Representation and Reality programme for their comments on an early version of this chapter. I also wish to thank Sten Ebbesen and Pavel Gregoric for helpful comments and suggestions on a later version.
Modern dream-research has established that 90–99 percent of all dreams are completely non-lucid (that is, dreams where the dreamer is unaware of the dream as an illusory experience). See for instance, Antti Revonsuo, Inner Presence: Consciousness as a Biological Phenomenon (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2006), 83.
Cf. Pavel Gregoric’s chapter in this volume, pp. 28–60.
Standard textbooks in psychopathology typically defines delusional belief as: “A false unshakable idea or belief which is out of keeping with the patient’s educational, cultural and social background; it is held with extraordinary conviction and subjective certainty.” (Andrew Sims, Descriptive Psychopathology: Symptoms in the Mind: An Introduction to Psychopathology, 2nd ed. (London: W. B. Saunders Company Ltd., 1995), 101.) It has turned out to be difficult to specify exactly how delusional beliefs differ from other ordinary irrational beliefs, yet idiosyncratic content and some degree of suffering seem to be two important distinguishing features. For a comprehensive discussion of this problem see Lisa Bortolotti, Delusions and Other Irrational Ideas (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), 259–65. As mentioned, the distinction between delusional awareness and delusional belief is not sharp. A large class of delusional beliefs seems to emerge in relation to supporting experiences even if some of those experiences are not sensory hallucinations, strictly understood. See Filip Radovic, “The Sense of Death and Non-Existence in Nihilistic Delusions,” Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 16:4 (2017): 679–99, for examples of delusional beliefs that are likely to involve an uncritical assent to an underlying experience.
Cf. the distinction between illusion and hallucination such as that attributed to Aretaeus of Cappadocia (c.150 CE) and later developed by Jean-Etienne Dominique Esquirol (1722–1840), according to which illusions are understood roughly as distorted perceptions of external objects, whereas hallucinations are taken to be perception-like experiences in the absence of any corresponding external object. For attempts in the scientific literature to define illusion and hallucination, see Jan Dirk Blom, A Dictionary of Hallucinations (Dordrecht: Springer, 2010) for a great variety of suggestions.
A special case includes perceptual circumstances that blur the line between imagination and perception in waking. For instance, the medieval thinker Ibn Khaldūn argues that mirror-scrying (an alleged kind of supernatural perception) involves an unconscious projection of internal images onto a perceived surface. See Ibn Khaldūn, The Muqaddimah: An Introduction to History, trans. F. Rosenthal (New York: Pantheon Books, 1958), 1:216–17. See also the case in which extremely vivid imagery in waking takes the form of real occurring events: Alexander Romanovich Luria, The Mind of a Mnemonist (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1968), 149–60. Non-sensory, more abstract cases involve an illusory sense of the presence of a person or feelings of persecution; see Graham Reed, The Psychology of Anomalous Experience: A Cognitive Approach (London: Hutchinson & Co. Ltd., 1972), 44–45, 126–33.
Cf. Jennifer Windt, Dreaming: A Conceptual Framework for Philosophy of Mind and Empirical Research (Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press, 2015), 476–83. See especially the distinction between (1) deception from presumed indistinguishability and (2) deception from cognitive corruption.
Revonsuo, Inner Presence, 82–84.
Jennifer Windt and Thomas Metzinger, “The Philosophy of Dreaming and Self-Consciousness: What Happens to the Experiential Subject During the Dream-State?” in The New Science of Dreaming, vol. 3: Cultural and Theoretical Perspectives, ed. D. Barrett and P. McNamara (London: Praeger, 2007), 221.
Windt and Metzinger, “The Philosophy of Dreaming,” 208–11.
Michel Jouvet, The Paradox of Sleep: The Story of Dreaming, trans. L. Garey (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1999), 75.
Allan Hobson, Dreaming as Delirium: How the Brain Goes out of Its Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1999), 5.
Cf. Windt who suggests a similar distinction: “Deception in an interesting sense requires not just that one’s beliefs are false but also a modicum of systematicity. The falsity of one’s beliefs should be more than a matter of superficial oversight, carelessness, or clumsiness.” (Windt, Dreaming, 470.)
Jonathan Ichikawa, “Dreaming and Imagination,” Mind and Language 24 (2009): 103–4.
Metaph. 4.5, 1010b3–11; 4.6, 1011a3–13.
Insomn. 3, 461b21–29; Aristotle on Sleep and Dreams: A Text and Translation with Introduction, Notes and Glossary, trans. D. Gallop (Warminster: Aris and Phillips Ltd., 1996), 101.
Cf. Gregoric’s chapter in this volume for an extensive discussion of the dokeîn-element in perception and phantasía, pp. 34–35, 44, and 51.
Insomn. 2, 460b20–23.
Insomn. 2, 460b19.
See also a related passage in de An. where Aristotle briefly mentions that some animals blindly act upon their appearances because they lack reason. Humans too can enter into this cognitive predicament in states in which the operation of reason is deprived, such as illness or sleep. Aristotle writes: “Because instances of imagination persist and are similar to perceptions, animals do many things in accordance with them, some because they lack reason, e.g. beasts, and others because their reason is sometimes shrouded by passion, or sickness, or sleep, e.g. humans.” (De An. 3.3, 429a5–8; Aristotle, De anima, trans. C. Shields (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016.)
Insomn. 1, 459a6–8; Aristotle, On Sleep and Dreams, 87.
Insomn. 3, 461b3–7; Aristotle, On Sleep and Dreams, 99.
See Gregoric’s chapter in this volume for a fine-grained non-doxastic interpretation of Aristotle’s account of why dreams are mistaken for perceived real-world objects. See also Gallop, Aristotle on Sleep and Dreams, for an influential account that presents a view along the lines of a non-doxastic interpretation. Gallop writes: “If we perceive something indistinctly, we will say that it ‘appears to be a man,’ to register uncertainty as to whether it really is one or not (DA 428a12). Here we make no firm judgement on the matter. Accordingly, Aristotle distinguishes ‘imagination’ (phantasía) from ‘judgement’ (dóxa), which may either endorse or oppose imagination’s deliverances, or which may do neither. In dreaming it simply fails to oppose them, so that the appearances presented to the subject gain acceptance by default (461b29–462a8, cf. 459a6–8, 461b3–7).” (Gallop, Aristotle on Sleep and Dreams, 24–25.) Cf. also Philip van der Eijk, Aristoteles: De insomniis, De divinatione per somnum: Übersetzt und Erläutert (Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 1994), 150–52, 225–26.
The dream of Coriscus is mistaken for the real Coriscus because the dream resembles the real Coriscus. However, misidentifications based on resemblance exclusively concern unreal things that are mistaken for real things, not the other way around, because perception is the primary state and dreaming is the anomaly. Thus, a likeness resembles a real thing but the real thing is not a likeness, technically speaking, even if it resembles the copy.
Insomn. 3, 461a8–25. Modern research on dreams suggests that dreams are not completely chaotic even if they sometimes include striking differences in relation to experiences in waking. A scale used in contemporary research to measure bizarreness considers different kinds of dream content: plot, characters, objects, actions, thoughts, feelings, and emotions. Moreover, three kinds of bizarreness are considered (1) discontinuity, (2) incongruity, and (3) uncertainty. See for instance, Allan Hobson et al., “Dream Bizarreness and the Activation-Synthesis Hypothesis,” Human Neurobiology 6 (1987): 157–64. See also Allan Hobson, The Dreaming Brain: How the Brain Creates Both the Sense and the Nonsense of Dreams (New York: Basic Books, 1988), 257–69; Adam N. Mamelak and Allan Hobson, “Dream Bizarreness as the Cognitive Correlate of Altered Neuronal Behavior in REM Sleep,” Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 1 (1989): 201–22. See also Antti Revonsuo and Christina Salmivalli, “A Content Analysis of Bizarre Elements in Dreams,” Dreams 5:3 (1995): 169–87.
Cf. Eric R. Dodds, The Greeks and the Irrational (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1951), 104–6, and Gregoric in this volume (p. 30). Note also that Aristotle’s conceptions of memory and recollection exhibit a similar orientation towards states and objects rather than events or plot-like narratives.
Cf. Aristotle’s remark on dream-interpretation in Div.Somn. 2, 464b5–16.
Michael Frede, “The Sceptic’s Two Kinds of Assent and the Question of the Possibility of Knowledge,” in Philosophy in History, ed. R. Rorty, J. B. Schneewind, and Q. Skinner (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), 255–78.
Frede, “The Sceptic’s Two Kinds of Assent,” 261.
A medieval source that superficially seems to be linked to Aristotle’s discussion in De insomniis is al-Ghazālī (c.1058–1111, known as Algazel in the Latin tradition). Al-Ghazālī discusses the idea of hierarchical cognitive assessments and his remarks about conviction based on the absence of opposing evidence are reminiscent of the problem of deception as discussed in De insomniis (al-Ghazālī, The Deliverance from Error and the Beginning of Guidance, trans. W. M. Watt (Kuala Lumpur: Islamic Book Trust), 8–10). However, al-Ghazālī pushes the issue further than Aristotle and notes that if people are inclined to respond to unchallenged information as trustworthy, why should any judgement be taken as trustworthy? A general mistrust of human rationality would make little sense for Aristotle. However, al-Ghazālī’s discussion was probably not influenced by Aristotle or Arabic Aristotelianism. The relevant passage in the Deliverance that considers a cognitive hierarchy of (1) sense, (2) intellect, and (3) super-understanding is similar to the Neoplatonic one found, for example, in Boethius’ The Consolation of Philosophy: (a) sense (common to all animals) – (b) imagination (some animals only) – (c) reason (humans only) – (d) divine super-understanding (intelligentia). See Boethius, The Consolation of Philosophy, trans. P. G. Walsh (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 108–9. Moreover, the relevant passages in the Deliverance echo a fragment of Democritus where an imaginary dialogue between the senses and the mind (phrḗn) takes place; see frag. 552 in The Presocratic Philosophers, ed. G. S. Kirk, J. E. Raven, and M. Schofield, 2nd ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983), 412 (= fragment 125 in Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, ed. H. Diels, rev. W. Kranz, 6th ed. (Zurich: Weidmann, 1951)). The fragment is preserved by Galen. See Stephen Menn, “The Discourse on the Method and the Tradition of Intellectual Autobiography,” Hellenistic and Early Modern Philosophy, ed. J. Miller and B. Inwood (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003): 141–91, on the genre of intellectual autobiography on which al-Ghazālī models his own text. At any rate, al-Ghazālī mentions Galen in the Deliverance, and is likely to have read him.
See Sten Ebbesen, “Radulphus Brito on Memory and Dreams: An Edition,” Cahiers de l’Institut du Moyen-Âge Grec et Latin 85 (2016): 11–86.
Radulphus Brito, Quaestiones super libros De somno et vigilia in Ebbesen, “Radulphus Brito,” qu. 2.4, 65. I am grateful to Sten Ebbesen for preparing this English translation exclusively for this inquiry.
For the role of the common sense, in cases when dreams are mistaken for real events, see Gregoric in this volume (pp. 32–34).
The translator notes that “the text between the crosses makes no sense in the context, and the text after it is not a direct continuation of the text before it. Probably a scribe has mistakenly jumped over some text (translator’s note).”
Radulphus Brito, Quaestiones Somn.Vig., ed. Ebbesen, qu. 2.4, 66; trans. Ebbesen.
René Descartes, Meditationes de prima philosophia VI, trans. J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch, in The Philosophical Writings of Descartes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), 2:89–90. Dream-scepticism has since ancient times been used to establish a range of different conclusions. For example, the presumed indistinguishability between dreaming and waking can be used to undermine the assumed authority of the waking state (cf. Metaph. 4.5, 1010b3–11; 4.6, 1011a3–13).
Baruch Spinoza, Ethics, 2, schol. 49, trans. G. H. R. Parkinson (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), 160.
The claim that “[…] even in dreams we suspend judgement, namely when we dream that we are dreaming” is difficult to understand.
William James, The Principles of Psychology (New York: Dover Publications, 1890), 2:288.
James, The Principles, 2:283.
James, The Principles, 2:284.
James, The Principles, 2:287.
James, The Principles, 2:289.
James, The Principles, 2:319.
James, The Principles, 2:299–300.
Bertrand Russell, The Analysis of Mind (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1921), 248–49.
Russell, The Analysis of Mind, 249–50.
De An. 3.3, 428b3–5.
Insomn. 1, 459a21–22.
For contemporary discussions of how images relate to percepts, see Colin McGinn, Mindsight: Image, Dream, Meaning (Cambridge. Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2004), 7–41, and Jonathan Ichikawa, “Dreaming,” 106–11.
Jean-Paul Sartre, The Imaginary: A Phenomenological Psychology of the Imagination, trans. J. Webber (London: Routledge, 1940), 165. Sartre’s theory of dreaming was most likely inspired by theories in the German school of phenomenology. For a helpful overview of theories of dreams in the phenomenological tradition, see Nicola Zippel, “Dream Consciousness: A Contribution from Phenomenology,” Rivista Internazionale di Filosofia e Psicologia 7 (2016): 180–201.
McGinn, Mindsight, 79.
Sartre, The Imaginary, 168.
McGinn, Mindsight, 104.
McGinn, Mindsight, 109.
I think that it is easy to misrepresent McGinn’s view. For instance, he says that immersion stimulates belief. But he also makes clear that dream-belief is something that should not be conflated with fully developed beliefs that are formed in waking consciousness. Moreover, dream-beliefs are described as less committing – there is a holding back. Thus, dream-belief, as characterised by McGinn seems to be merely nominally belief.
McGinn, Mindsight, 112.
McGinn, Mindsight, 110.
Ichikawa presents a version of the fascination theory in line with Sartre and McGinn, but explicitly holds that the absorption in a dream involves no kind of belief, not even quasi-beliefs. In fact, he criticises McGinn for endorsing quasi-beliefs in dreaming. However, Ichikawa’s own rejection of beliefs in dreaming relies on a very narrow conception of belief. On this account, beliefs are basically modelled on the cognitive functions they serve in waking life, that is, they are intimately linked to perception and action, and therefore the kind of quasi-belief that is endorsed by Sartre and McGinn poorly exhibits the distinctive traits of genuine belief. See Ichikawa, “Dreaming,” 115.
Ichikawa, “Dreaming,” 119.
Ernest Sosa, A Virtue Epistemology: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2007), 1:8.
Sosa developed his view on dream-belief unaware of Sartre’s and McGinn’s view. Nevertheless, Sosa’s view on dream-belief echoes Sartre’s and McGinn’s accounts.
Sosa, A Virtue Epistemology, 3–4.
See also Malcolm who formulates a version of this idea in Dreaming, 112.
The majority of theories within the phenomenological tradition deny that dreams can be misapprehended as real. However, there are exceptions, see for instance Eugen Fink’s view as described in Zippel, “Dream Consciousness,” 195–96. Cf. Sartre above.
Owen Flanagan, Dreaming Souls: Sleep, Dreams, and the Evolution of the Conscious Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), 173.
Windt, Dreaming, 469.
Windt, Dreaming, 470.
Windt, Dreaming, 474–75. The references are to T. M. Reed, “Dreams, Skepticism, and Waking Life,” in Body, Mind, and Method: Essays in Honor of Virgil C. Aldrich, ed. D. F. Gustafson and B. L. Tapscott (Boston: D. Reidel, 1979), 37–67.