1 Introduction
Studying the influence of Aristotle’s political philosophy on Medieval Arab philosophers presents three major challenges.1 Firstly, it is dependent on the interpretation of Aristotle’s texts, and of how his doctrine may have evolved in relation to that of Plato. Even today, there is considerable disagreement amongst specialists of Aristotle’s works. For example, phronēsis—one of the most crucial notions of Aristotelian thought—is considered by some to be an elevated form of knowledge based on right reason that serves as a guide for practical intellect, while others believe that the standard of practical wisdom is less epistemological than it is anthropological in nature, with the phronimos himself acting in a contingent, indeterminate universe that is the immanent incarnation of this virtue.2 These interpretations may also differ according to context. In the Middle Ages, following the 13th-century translation of Aristotle’s Politics by William of Moerbeke, the main discussions revolved around the mixed constitution. But in the 20th century, in the wake of the human disasters that seemed to be an effect of arrogant and senseless technological modernity, the return to Aristotelian phronēsis allowed us to think of practical reason as wisdom and to push for harmony between correct desire, the sort of goods a human being can pursue, and the identification between happiness (eudaimonia) and the excellent activity of the rational soul.3
The second obstacle in studying the influence of Aristotle’s political ideas on Arab philosophers concerns their understanding of the actual identity of Aristotle. Certain apocryphal texts, such as the Theology, were attributed to
Finally, at a strictly political level, we know that Aristotle’s Politics had a decisive impact on the Latin context from its translation in the 13th century and its arrival, together with the texts of the Arab philosophers, in the intellectual centers of Medieval Europe. It was thus that it developed as the origin of the major works of Giles of Rome, Bartholomew of Lucca and Marsilius of Padua, whereas the text had never been translated into Arabic in the Middle Ages, and played no role in the philosophical careers of al-Kindī (801–873), al-Fārābī (870–950), Miskawayh (932–1030), Avicenna (980–1037), Avempace (d. 1138) or Averroes. As such, can we continue to speak of how these Arab philosophers were influenced by Aristotle’s political philosophy?
These various factors (firstly, the interpretation of Aristotle’s political philosophy in comparison, notably, with that of Plato; secondly, the acknowledgement of the Arabs’ interest in these two philosophers’ texts in a philosophical
In response to these readings, other approaches have sought to adhere to ‘positivist’ principles, trusting only what the history of the texts’ transmission has taught us about their availability and circulation within philosophical circles. However, from this point of view, the political texts read by the Arabs, whether written by Plato or Aristotle, probably came from summaries or paraphrasing by Galen (in the case of the Republic) or Porphyry (in the case of the Nicomachean Ethics). The true Greek masters were not accessible due to these historical contingencies, and their ideas ended up being explored only through a range of distorted sources, whether Hellenistic, Neoplatonic or otherwise. In these approaches, when a significant gap is discovered between the texts of al-Fārābī or Averroes and those of the Greek masters, it is justified by the presence of an incomplete corpus, and as long as original points are found, it is assumed that they were taken from an anonymous source or a Greek commentator, with original text surviving only in Arabic.10 Arabic authors thus reflect either a failure of interpretation (due to the unavailability of the genuine texts) or the wonderful discovery of a known or anonymous Greek thinker, whose genius can be contemplated in the surviving Arabic translation of his work. In both cases, the center of the approach and starting point for analysis is not the Arab political philosophy but the philosophy of the Greek predecessors.
Through an interpretative approach that remains conscious of these various difficulties, this paper aims to identify the major dimensions of this influence, while also taking into account the fact that such influence may come from
2 Aristotle’s Political Corpus in Arabic
If we set aside the apocryphal texts addressed at the end of this article, only Aristotle’s Politics11 is absent from the ensemble of the Aristotelian corpus that fuelled the political reflections of Arab philosophers. However, this ‘ensemble’ can be narrowed down to one text, namely the Nicomachean Ethics. Aristotle’s Politics which had a significant influence on the Latin world from the late thirteenth century, was not translated into Arabic with the rest of Aristotle’s works, and was not available to Arab thinkers at that time. Certain writers cite the text and intimate that it did indeed exist, while others explicitly state that it was not at their disposal and therefore not available in Arabic. Of this second category, Averroes is the most unequivocal. In the opening pages of his Commentary on Plato’s Republic, he states that since he cannot procure Aristotle’s book which contains the second part of the science (the first being the Nicomachean Ethics), he chose instead to explore the content of Plato’s Republic.12
The aim of Aristotle’s second book on ethics and politics entitled Politika, meaning “civil”, dedicated to one of his friends, is similar to the aims of his first book [i.e the Nicomachean Ethics]. In these pages, he addresses civil politics in more detail, yet certain chapters are identical to those of the first book.13
Other authors mention the Book of Politics or the Book on the Government of Cities by Aristotle, yet they are referring to either Secretum secretorum, also known as Of Politics, or to one of Aristotle’s treatises to Alexander the Great On the Government of Cities. This is the case for the Andalusian science historian Ṣāʿid al-Andalusī (1029–1070). In a list of Aristotle’s works, he cites treatises on cities, the administration of the household and ethics.14 Similarly, in his Book of Caution and Revision, al-Masʿūdī (d. 956) notes that Aristotle’s political philosophy is featured in his book The Political Regime (al-Siyāsa al-madaniyya). This could be construed to be Aristotle’s Politics, yet the description of the text’s contents and main ideas show that al-Masʿūdī briefly summarizes ideas set out in al-Fārābī’s work of the
Turning now to political philosophers with an in-depth knowledge of the Aristotelian corpus, al-Fārābī’s Book of Letters refers to a “book by Aristotle on political science”, which immediately brings Politics to mind.16 However, this interpretation adopted by Shlomo Pines to support the general idea of the existence of at least the first book—and perhaps the first two books of Politics—was incorrect. In actual fact, the book al-Fārābī is referring to in this passage is none other than the Nicomachean Ethics. The cited text addresses the theory of relatives and their relation to categories, a subject that Aristotle does not cover at the beginning of Politics.17 The passage in Politics (I, 3, 1253b 21–23) that Shlomo Pines compares to al-Fārābī’s text, discusses the nature of slavery: is it just because is determined by nature, or is it unjust because it is founded on force? Similarly, the text by Miskawayh that Shlomo Pines used to prove the existence of two books of Aristotle’s Politics in Arabic is more likely to refer to one of the Letters’ principal pieces Aristotle sent to Alexander. According to the manuscripts, this text is called, Of Politics (al-Siyāsa), The Politics of Cities (Siyāsat al-mudun) or General politics (al-Siyāsa al-ʿāmmiyya). The word siyāsa is interchangeable with tadbīr (rule, government, management, direction), making it highly possible that the work Miskawayh cited (Tadbīr al-mudun, On the Government of Cities) refers to this book.18 The fact that he states that the text contains two books (maqālatān) confirms this hypothesis, since the treatise attributed to Aristotle does indeed have two parts in certain manuscripts: “The qualities of the king” (“Fī ṣifāt al-malik”) and “The Reform of the cities” (“Fī iṣlāḥ al-mudun”).
Generally speaking, when analyzing the Aristotelian corpus mentioned by Islamic philosophers and its passages cited in their works, it can be useful to distinguish three levels. The first one pertains to the citation of works and their content that may be sourced from bibliographical catalogues and secondary
The second level relates to citation of certain textual fragments, whether it be developments of varying significance attributed to the texts of commentators including Alexander of Aphrodisias, Porphyry, Simplicius, John Philoponus and Nicolaus of Damascus, or maxims compiled in anthologies that attracted a wide audience in the East from the 9th to 12th centuries.20 Admittedly, most of these maxims and aphorisms had no connection to the authentic texts of Aristotle. The image some of these writings evoke of the Stagirite can be surprising: of a neo-platonic philosopher yearning to purify his soul, a mystic eager to rid himself of his body’s influence, or an ascetic that holds this lowly world in contempt and thinks of nothing but the afterlife. However, other passages do indeed reflect biographical aspects of Aristotle’s authentic ideas. In this respect, the text by pseudo-al-ʿĀmirī is even more exemplary as it is the only work to have recorded a few lines which are equivalent, in terms of ideas, to Book I of Aristotle’s Politics.21 But these passages do not reflect Aristotle’s text verbatim, meaning that it is a secondary citation by Greek commentators of Aristotle, or Alexandrian authors. The Aristotelian work from which pseudo-al-ʿĀmirī sourced the moral and political aphorisms therefore remains the Nicomachean Ethics. The numerous citations taken from this work prove
The third level concerns Aristotle’s authentic texts, the contents of which are strictly political. Here we are forced to restrict ourselves to one sole text, Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. This text had by far the most influence on Arab philosophers’ studies of not only politics, but philosophy in general.22 It played a pivotal role in this crucial moment for scientific and philosophical thought in the 10th and 11th centuries, as manifested by its central position in the works of young al-Fārābī, which combine the search for happiness and perfection with the mastery of the art of logic.23 The short treatise of al-Fārābī, al-Tanbibīh ʿalā taḥṣīl al-Saʿāda, illustrates this influence of Aristotelian thinking in the first two books of Nicomachean Ethics on happiness and perfection. This is the starting point of the young al-Fārābī, known above all as a logician, in his overall philosophical endeavour.24 Miskawayh follows the same path in Tartīb al-Saʿādāt (The Order of Happiness) and devotes the first pages to a study inspired by the first two books of the Nicomachean Ethics, leading to a lengthy development of Aristotle’s philosophy supported by a text by Paul the Persian. Here, it should be noted that he follows al-Fārābī’s plan by linking research on happiness (eudaimonia) to scientific knowledge, particularly the work of Aristotle, and the way in which he perfected the tools of the logical arts.25 These two examples illustrate that Aristotle’s work was the basis for both authors’ philosophical works, since they will devote most of their work to ethical and political and questions, relating them to their psychologies, cosmologies and metaphysics. The same influence can be identified in the work of Avempace.26 In the Governance of the Solitary, he conveys an original approach based on the idea that a philosopher must attain the perfection described by Aristotle, but in absence of an ideal political environment and a city willing to carry out this aim, must take this charge upon himself. Avempace then carried out
3 Practical Philosophy
The different levels of Aristotelian corpus found in the writing of Arab philosophers in the Medieval era come to light in how they present the branch of practical philosophy. Accordingly, there is generally a tripartition between ethics or self-government, economics or the administration of the household, and politics or the government of the city based on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, Economics and Politics. This tripartition inspired by Aristotle was preserved in the most vivacious philosophical tradition Islam immediately encountered in different cities in which it became established, namely the currents of Alexandrian Neoplatonism.28 Aristotle’s work Economics, like Politics, was not available in Arabic. This explains its replacement with a text by Bryson, a 1st century Neopythagorean who wrote a small treatise on the administration of the household (oikonomia/tadbīr al-manzil), practically the only reference on the subject.29
This tripartition, which can be traced back to Aristotle, would be systematized in philosophical encyclopaedias and scientific catalogues, especially in the post-Avicennian era. The first significant treatises combining all three parts of practical philosophy only came to light at the end of the classical era. Paradoxically, the inclusion of ethics, economics and politics in one volume increased the division between the three fields on an epistemological level. It is important to note that in philosophical writings in the post-Avicennian era, these three fields took on a scholastic nuance insisting on the specific nature of each branch as an individual science. Al-Ṭūsī’s Nasirean Ethics, a work written in Persian and then translated into Arabic in the 14th century by al-Ǧurǧānī, illustrates this position. In the introduction of al-Ṭūsī’s work, one of Avicenna’s most famous commentators, he explains that he had been commissioned by
Practical Philosophy, says al-Ṭūsī, is the acknowledgement of benefits in voluntary movements and disciplined acts on the part of the human species, in a way that conduces to the ordering of the states of man’s life here and hereafter, necessitating arrival at that perfection towards which he is directed. It likewise is divided into two: that which refers to each soul individually, and that which concerns a community in association. The second division is itself subdivided: that which refers to a community associated within a dwelling or home, on the one hand; on the other, that which concerns a community associated within a city, a province, or even a region or a realm. Thus, Practical Philosophy too has three divisions: the first is called Ethics, the second Economics, and the third Politics.30
This approach to practical philosophy shows that each discipline is autonomous, to a certain extent, and that the distinction between them is made through adding or subtracting the number of individuals involved in the exercise of governance in each sphere. According to this concept, ethics has no part to play in the political domain, nor any purpose that corresponds to the entire community as a whole. Although this was not originally the authors’ intention, we note that the prevailing scholarly approach at the end of the classical age of Islam supported the idea that practical philosophy was based on the autonomy of each branch as part of the whole. They were inclined to create divisions and subdivisions and identify different categories that made up the scientific disciplines.31 Avicenna appears to be the source of this approach to practical philosophy. In the Eastern Philosophy, he notes that ethics “teaches how the human individual should behave for himself and for the states that concern him, so that he will
This perspective is not shared by all Arab philosophers. Some insist on the indivisibility of practical philosophy, while still precisely listing its individual parts. This point can be made clear by analyzing the role of the household governance as part of the whole, on the one hand, and examining the link between ethics and politics, on the other.
Both the city and the household have an analogy with the body of the human being. The body is composed of different parts of a definite number, some better and some baser, adjacent to one another in rank, each doing a certain action, so that from all of their actions they come together in mutual assistance to perfect the purpose of the human being’s body. In the same way, both the city and the household are composed of different parts of a definite number, some baser and some better, adjacent to one another in a rank of different ranks, each performing on its own a certain action, so that from their actions they come together in mutual assistance to perfect the purpose of the city or the household. Even though the household is a part of a city and households are in the city, their purposes are nonetheless different. Yet there comes together from those different purposes, when they are perfected and brought together, a mutual assistance for perfecting the purpose of the city.34
In the same way [as the physician] ought the governor of the city to govern every one of the parts of the city, whether it is a small part such as a single human being or a large one like a single household. He treats it and provides it with good in relation to the whole of the city and to each of the rest of the parts of the city by endeavoring to make the good that part provides a good that does not harm the whole of the city or anything among the rest of its parts, but rather a good useful to the city in its entirety and to each of its parts in accordance with its rank of usefulness to the city.35
In addition to the epistemological phase that made it possible to identify the role of the different parts of practical philosophy by drawing on analogies found in biology, we note that the reflections on the government of the household as a ‘science’ disappears altogether in the principal works of al-Fārābī. This can be seen in The Political Regime, where he clearly stipulates that perfection and happiness can only be achieved by moving from the lower forms of association such as the family or the village to the superior form which is the city.
Human beings are [one] of the species that cannot complete their necessary affairs nor gain their most excellent state except by coming together as many associations in a single dwelling-place. Some human associations are large, some medium, and some small. The large association is an association of many nations coming together and helping one another. The medium is the nation. And the small are those the city embraces. These three are the perfect associations.
Thus, the city is the first in the rankings of perfections. Associations in villages, quarters, streets, and houses are defective associations. Of these, one is very defective, namely, the household association. It is part of the association in the street, and the association in the street is part of the association in the quarter. And the latter association is part of the civil association. The associations in quarters and the associations in villages are both for the sake of the city. However, the difference between them is that quarters are parts of the city, while villages serve the city. The civil association is part of the nation, and the nation is divided into cities. The absolute perfect human association is divided into nations.37
To conclude this section on the role of the administration of the household and the relationship it maintains with ethics and politics, it is important to note that two Andalusian philosophers, Avempace and Averroes would address this question and develop a highly critical stance on the discourse of household governance.
Avempace raises this in The Governance of the Solitary, in which he discusses how an individual must do everything to attain the supreme goal of man in an imperfect political environment, regardless of whether or not the excellent city is yet a reality. Following a philological and philosophical explanation of the concept of tadbīr (government, management, conduct, care), the cornerstone of Arab political philosophy, he attempts to restrict the domain of the individual and the city by rejecting the idea of a tadbīr for the household alone.
[…] The perfection of the household is not something desired for its own sake, but only for the sake of rendering perfect either the city or the natural end of man, and the treatment of the latter clearly forms part of man’s governance of himself [that is, ethics]. In any case, the household is either a part of the city and its treatment forms part of the treatment of the city, or a preparation for another end and its treatment forms part of the treatment of that end. This explains why the treatment of the household in the popular manner is pointless and does not constitute a science.38
Avempace’s critique of the science of the organization of the household implies that the techniques of civil government cannot be reduced to those at work in the organization of the household, and that a city cannot be considered as such. In other words, the art of managing a city cannot be likened to managing a household. Despite Plato’s influence on these various developments, the fact remains that Avempace begins with the problem of government that seeks to identify the original relationship, enshrined in Aristotle’s political philosophy, between the individual and the city. Self-governance and city government, ethics and politics are locked in a relationship of identity that negates any
This same logic serves as the foundation for Averroes’ criticism—not of the science of the household government itself, but rather of the transformation of certain societies into spaces governed by clan or family-based systems. Rather surprisingly for modern thinkers, it is democracy that is likened to the government of the household. To understand this particular view of the democratic regime, it should be noted that in the Commentary on Aristotle’s Rhetoric, democracy is referred to as the ‘city of groups’ (al-siyāsa al-ǧamāʿiyya) and that it is likened to arbitrary government, and to individuals’ desire i) to be free, and ii) to be able to eliminate the ideally merit-based hierarchical relationships enjoyed by the rulers in relation to the governed.40 Another idea is put forward in the Commentary on Plato’s Republic, and is line with Avempace’s remarks. Averroes notes that most Muslim cities of the time were ‘democratic’, as for him, the essence of democracy was the division of society into family and clan groups that broke the bond of political unity, and reorganized all spheres of society and the economy according to the interests of the parties rather than the interests of the whole. The contradiction of this regime lies in that democracy really does form a whole, however one that is entirely disjointed and disconnected, a contradiction that is perfectly reflected in the term ‘ǧamāʿiyya’, which encapsulates both ‘the whole’ and the ‘separate groups’.
The association in these States is of necessity only one of chance, since they do not aim at one end in their association. Consequently, authority in them is only accidental. The associations among many of the Muslim kings today are communities exclusively based upon homes. Of the norm only that which observes the first laws is left among them. It is clear that in this State all property appertains to the home.41
4 Aristotle’s Influence: Moral Philosophy or Political Philosophy?
In light of the absence of Politics in the Arab context, in which Aristotle undertook the singular task of studying one hundred and fifty-eight constitutions, with the particular judicial or political functions that characterizes them, and their effects on morals, social habits and laws, can we still support the existence of truly political thinking among Arab philosophers, or should we simply refer to their writings as ‘moral’? Ibn Khaldūn himself, at a crucial moment in the final decades of the classical age of Islam, when he began examining the political knowledge of his predecessors, described the works of philosophers such as al-Fārābī as politically useless, and valid only for self-governance.42 As such, would these treatises not be – at most – valid only for ethical reform and self-improvement, given that they in no way address the matter of political power, nor explain the genesis of the State, its evolution, or disintegration? Based on this observation by Ibn Khaldūn and other philological considerations, Dimitri Gutas sought to defend the notion of the absence of political philosophy in the person generally considered to be the very founder of political philosophy in Islam: al-Fārābī.
According to Dimitri Gutas, true political philosophy only arrived in Islam with Ibn Khaldūn, whereas the technical terms and vocabulary used by
Discussions [on human communities and their governance], says D. Gutas, are always derivative, not central, and they depend for their philosophical validity on al-Fārābī’s metaphysical scheme and his theory of the intellect (noetics) rather than on any properly political analysis or argumentation.43
The term ‘madanī’, an adjective derived from ‘madīna’ (city), which refers to everything civil, is present in the very name of political science (ʿilm al-siyāsa) used by the philosophers, who also call it al-ʿilm al-madanī (civil science), ʿilm tadbīr al-mudun (the science of city government), al-ʿilm al-insānī (human science) or al-ʿilm al-irādī (voluntary science).44 Focusing on the term ‘madanī’, frequently used by al-Fārābī, D. Gutas, observes that translators in Baghdad between the 9th and 10th centuries used it without any real political connotation. It simply means “a person or thing that belongs or pertains to a city”.45 At the same time, the watchword of Greek political philosophy, politeia, which, in the historical and cultural context of ancient Greece, refers to the constitution of the city-state, was not correctly understood by the translators, leading them to overlook the legal and political meaning of the term and to retain only the moral meaning of ‘way of life’, bios or moral conduct. Expressions such as al-sīra al-madaniyya, referring to the type of constitution adopted by a given city has therefore taken on a moral and psychological hue. A correct translation of the Greek term politeia, had it been understood correctly, bearing in mind the general interest of a State and the advantages provided by the arrangement of offices (magistracies or powers), established there, would have resulted in the Arabic terms qawānīn (regulations, laws, nomoï) or aḥkām (legal rules, legislative ordinances) rather than the vague and only slightly political term sīra.46
For Dimitri Gutas, if the Fārābian understanding of Aristotelian political philosophy is correct, it should be limited to what is said about politeia in
Al-Fārābī’s so-called ‘politics’ is thus actually based on ethics for two reasons: first because he derives it primarily from the Nicomachean Ethics, which leads him to develop an ethical framework for understanding what we call ‘political life, and second because the mistranslation of politeia as ‘way of life’, sīra, led him to concentrate on an ethical concept as the key feature of ‘political life’.47
Although Dimitri Gutas’ analyses are based on a high level of philological competence, the central interpretation involving removing the political content of al-Fārābī’s philosophy and reducing it solely to morality merits some comment. Firstly, it would seem that in Dimitri Gutas’ use of the words ‘political’ or ‘politics’, the term should be unambiguous and apply exclusively to the legal organization of power. Now, we see that there are several ways of approaching politics, which may be judicial (tradition of public or constitutional law), historical-literary (mirrors of princes and the arts of governing), theological (writings on the imamate) or philosophical (as we approach it here).48 Moreover, given that politics is the art of leading the people or affairs of the city, it is therefore hard to support an understanding limiting it to the legal and institutional aspects of the organization of power, as stated by D. Gutas in this work. The polysemy of the terms siyāsa and tadbīr, for example, two pivotal concepts in Arab political philosophy, as well as the plurivocity of the objects and domains to which they apply, encourages us not to fall prey to the modern representation of this work, which reduces it to technical-practical or purely legal-institutional dimensions. The fact that Ibn Khaldūn is considered the first political philosopher in the Arab tradition is even more surprising, given that he i) fiercely opposes the philosophers, and that ii) his thinking is not founded on the legal aspects that D. Gutas presents, based on his reading of Aristotle, as fundamental criteria to legitimize the use of the term ‘political’. The desire to remove all political meaning from the vocabulary of Arab
Regarding the philological analysis of the term madanī, it would be fair to say that it is a relational adjective formed from the words madīna (city) and designating “of the city, politikè”, but would be strange to say that when the adjective is turned into a noun and applied to the man in charge of governing the city (the king, the statesman, politikos), the term must always be taken in a non-political sense.50 In the Selected Aphorisms, al-Fārābī clearly notes that the politician (madanī) is responsible for caring for souls just as the doctor is the one who cares for bodies. In this definition, he is presented as the statesman (al-insān al-madanī) or the king (al-malik).51 Likewise, the adjective ‘madanī’, when used in conjunction with philosophy (falsafa madaniyya), art (ṣināʿa madaniyya) or science (ʿilm madanī), refers to political philosophy, its principles and purposes, as detailed in the Enumeration of Sciences.52 Here, the spatial, geographical or territorial meaning (belonging to a city’s territory) gives way to other more elaborate meanings. The philological analysis conducted by D. Gutas is very competent, however she merely finds the Arabic equivalents to the Greek terms, in assessing their adequacy or divergence with respect to the understanding of Aristotle’s original text. However, to measure the effect of the translation of an idea or the introduction of a concept in a new linguistic culture, we would need to further question the semantic innovations and lexical creations it may have given rise to. This is what we observe in the new reflections led by Arab philosophers, who show that the word madanī did not solely have a geographical meaning referring to the territorial space of the city (city-dweller). In a text by Miskawayh, a contemporary of al-Fārābī and whose political philosophy owes much to Nicomachean Ethics, we see that the Arabic root (MDN) resulted in the formation of the notion of ‘madaniyya’, which can be translated as ‘citizenship’ or ‘political sociability’.53 The creation of this
The state of prosperity”, he says, “is achieved by the large number of auxiliaries, and the promotion of justice among them, thanks to the might of the political power that ensures their conditions, safeguards their ranks and eliminates insecurity from their lives. By the great number of auxiliaries, I mean the mutual assistance of physical strength and wills through great works, some of which are necessary for survival, others useful for living well, and a third category, useful for enjoyment. It is the combination of these three things that constitutes prosperity. But if the city is lacking any of these three elements, then it falls into ruin, and if it is lacking two of them – the good life and the enjoyment of life – then it is in an extreme state of ruin.54
Miskawayh adds that the way of life satisfied with the mere necessities, such as in ascetics, is a negation of madaniyya, since it calls into question the material conditions for the attainment of happiness and prosperity. This depends on the cultivation of the land, the disciplines associated with this activity, the defense of the State by military means, and the intensification of transport and commercial activities. Without these three elements (1. agriculture and industry, 2. military arts and 3. transportation and trade), Miskawayh says, one cannot attain the ‘excellent life’ (ǧawdat al-ʿayš). Madaniyya manifests as an element through the participation of individuals in the common affairs of the city, in order to ensure its prosperity and create the conditions for an excellent life. Truly civil life is therefore not limited to the mere belonging to the space the city inhabits, where individuals are content with their basic needs being met, as in ascetics, nor a mere space for the exercise of virtuous ethics. The excellence of political sociability rests on the distinction between living and living well, which is at the basis of Aristotle’s political thought, as can be seen in an opening passage of Politics (I, 2, 1252b 29–30) where he states that the
Another equally as important passage in the same book describes political power as an art (ṣināʿa) at the foundation of madaniyya, leaving no doubt as to the political meaning of the term, and dispels the ambiguities created by D. Gutas’ reading.
Political power (mulk) is an art at the foundation of citizenship (madaniyya), as it is capable of leading men to pursue the interests that derive from their laws and leadership, whether by choice or coercion. It is also an art that safeguards people’s positions and livelihoods, so that they are guided in the best way possible.56
Certainly, al-Fārābī’s approach, which is at the heart of this discussion, is unique in that it cannot be traced to that of other authors such as Miskawayh, Avempace or Averroes, philosophers whose political ideas can be appreciated using other criteria and assume different meanings. However, this kind of analysis by one of al-Fārābī’s contemporaries shows that the term ‘madanī’ had an eminently political meaning. In addition, the term ‘madanī’ and its derivatives were used a century before, as we saw above with al-Kindī, to refer to political science. The presence of this kind of analysis in the work of a contemporary of al-Fārābī thus reflects the permanence of this political meaning assigned to the term. One could concede to Dimitri Gutas, of course, that al-Fārābī’s political approach is unique because it is overdetermined by ethics. The constitutions referred to in his works exceed the number found in Aristotle or Plato, to the point of increasing the number of cities based on the aims pursued by their leaders, and the ways of life that prevail there. The proliferation in the number of bad cities (double the number of Aristotle’s) shows that their nature varies, ultimately, according to the aim pursued by the leader, and above all, according to the conduct and morals they establish by acceding to government. In the same way, the focus on the leader means the governed only gains access
We know that Aristotle conceives politeia not only as an arrangement of offices, but also as a widespread temperament amongst people, leading them to choose one type of government over another.57 In his important article retracing the meaning of the word politeia and its different philological, literary, philosophical and political uses, J.J. Mulhern argues “that Aristotle had in mind mainly four distinct senses in using politeia in the Politics – citizenship, citizen-body, constitution or arrangement of offices, and regime”.58 At the end of his article, he argues that “an exact understanding leads away from treating Aristotle’s argument as focused on constitutions or forms of government in every case”.59 Thus, the understanding of both translators and Arab philosophers of the term politeia and its translation by sīra was quite accurate and appropriate. To define the best city, Aristotle calls for an examination of the most worthy way of life (Politics, VII, 1, 1323-a). The problem of the good life therefore joins that of the best city; the two subjects are inseparable from each other, as confirmed by the division of political science into two parts: ethics, studying the characters and virtues of justice, prudence, friendship, etc., and politics, which deals with types of cities and regimes. As Ch. Genequand notes in his critical discussion of the work of D. Gutas, Gutas’ argument disregards a number of philological points relating to the meaning Aristotle gives to the term politeia in Nicomachean Ethics, which goes beyond the simple legal-institutional framework in which D. Gutas seeks to confine it.60
For al-Fārābī, Charles Genequand says, moral action is therefore not conceivable outside a political framework, which is expressed rather accurately by the adjective madanī. However, it can still be considered from two angles: moral in the sense of action determined by an internal motivation ḫuluqī), or political as conditioned by external rules (siyāsī).61
[…] Ethical treatises identify sovereign good as happiness. However, Politics also begins with observations on ‘supreme good’, stating that it can only be the good of the most accomplished community.63
Al-Fārābī follows this path of the inseparability of ethics and politics in all his works on the perfect city. That path is clearly explained by Averroes at the beginning of Commentary on Plato’s Republic: he points out that ethics and politics are the same science, the parts of which differ only in that the first generally describes the principles of good deeds, while the second relates to the means of fostering virtuous habits in individuals.
[…] This art (of Politics) is divided into two parts: in the first part acquired habits, volitional actions and behaviour in general are mentioned in a comprehensive exposition. Their mutual relationship is also explained, and which of these habits are due to which others. In the second part will be explained how these habits become entrenched in the soul, and which of them are co-ordinated so that the action resulting from the intended habit should be perfect to the highest degree; and which habits hinder one another. Generally, in this part are placed things which are capable of realization, if they are conditioned by general principles.64
It has been said that he who has attained perfect self-governance and correction of his morals, tamed the enemy of his soul lodged between his flanks, is in good condition to administer a house, and that he who is in a fit state to govern a household is also in a fit state to govern a city; and that he who is in a fit state to govern a city is also in a fit state to govern a kingdom.65
The link between ethics and politics, which is at the heart of both Aristotle’s and Plato’s philosophies, is therefore accepted by Arab philosophers. What changes, however, is the geographical scale of the pursuit of the supreme good, which extends far beyond the city-state of the Greek philosophers. This is one of the most important aspects marking the distance taken by the Arab philosophers from the Greek masters. To explore this aspect, a study of human excellence will be the key to understanding the foundations of Arab political philosophy.
5 On Human Excellence and the Politeia
The human things through which nations and citizens of cities attain earthly happiness in this life and supreme happiness in the life beyond are of four kinds: theoretical virtues, deliberative virtues, moral virtues, and practical arts.68
The concepts of kamāl and faḍīla, which is the translation of “aretē”, have no moral or religious meaning for Arab philosophers (nor for Aristotle, incidentally). They are instead synonyms for excellence in function, the perfect realization of the full potential of something, and flawlessly performing a task. The concept of kamāl is fundamental because it first cultivates reflections on the kind of life most worthy of being lived (which is the purpose of ethics). It then calls for a search for the excellent city, one which fosters happiness and ensures that everyone can attain excellence as part of the city, according to their individual skills and aptitudes (a point which brings us to the realm of politics). Finally, the search for excellence that is truly human necessarily prompts us to reflect on the distinction between humans and other beings (reason), which leads us to psychology and metaphysics.
In a lengthy passage in the Commentary on Plato’s Republic,69 Averroes restates the typology of four types of excellence set out by al-Fārābī, and largely preserves their essence. Theoretical excellence relates to sciences such as astronomy and metaphysics, for example, which are not related to practical activities. Ethical excellence is what shapes a morally exemplary individual. Deliberative or cogitative excellence (fikriyya) relates to the field of practical
The theory of excellence put forward by al-Fārābī, later taken up by Averroes and other philosophers such as Avempace and Maimonides,70 is key to understanding the role of politics in their overall philosophical vision. The reorganization of Aristotle’s ideas described above provokes reflection on the ensemble of human activities, organized in such a way as to point to one distinct, ultimate goal. This creates the necessary conditions for humankind to undertake that which sets it apart from other beings, namely that which allows individuals to fully express their humanity (insāniyya). However, this is confused with intellect, as noted by Aristotle in Nicomachean Ethics (X 7, 1178a 5–10), as intellect designates humankind’s true function (ergon), and meets the definition of happiness as an activity in keeping with virtue, namely an individual’s potential (Nicomachean Ethics, I, 6). Averroes analyzes this typology in the context of an Aristotelian discussion: what is more noble, a contemplative life or an active life? And what is the highest excellence? Activities for the city’s common good and its political wellbeing, or intellectual activities relating to matters that the will (irāda) does not seek or cannot bring about? The answer to this question relates to the role of each excellence and gives rise to the establishment of an ontological ordering for each one, in order to ensure that the ultimate goal (theoretical knowledge, life according to what is intelligible) may be recognized as such, and the other types of excellences may act as propaedeutical to this goal. The criteria defining supreme excellence and the ultimate goal of humankind are threefold: plurality and unity, materiality and immateriality, and self-sufficiency or dependence of the excellence. According to these criteria, the supreme excellence must be unique, immaterial and sought for its own sake, not to serve the purpose of another excellence. Only theoretical science
The hierarchy of excellences and their arrangement towards a distinct goal is what maintains their plurality on the one hand (as it is not a question of cultivating one excellence at the expense of another) and demonstrates, on the other, that the ontological order unifying them under the banner of a supreme excellence cannot be upturned without giving rise to disastrous consequences for the possibility of attaining what embodies man’s humanity. It is critical to our discussion that setting the order of each excellence, in addition to complying with noetic and ontological considerations, must be seen to bear a highly political meaning. In reality, it embodies the political order that the perfect city must produce and safeguard. According to al-Fārābī and Averroes, an excellent city is one in which the statesmen, administrators, strategists, secretaries, etc., recognize the superiority of theoretical sciences and purely scientific knowledge, and give primacy to nurturing this knowledge, despite it being remote from practice. Similarly, a city that deems moral excellence to be the ultimate goal in life is mistaken, and thus misleads the citizens who comprise it, since the excellent character is not solely a human attribute. Indeed, certain animals set the example through their courage (the lion) and generosity (the rooster). The same can be said for the excellence in craftsmanship observed in bees or ants. Since Aristotle’s best constitution is based on the definition of a certain order (taxis), but applied to the distribution of powers among citizens, the two great political philosophers of Islam, al-Fārābī and Averroes, would determine this order from the hierarchy of human excellence, and the best constitution (the aristē politeia) would therefore be the one that manages to maintain it according to the hierarchy that facilitates the study of man’s nature or his own function. The excellence of producers and artisans supplies the city with material goods; since statesmen, judges, strategists, etc., must be virtuous, ethical excellence is propaedeutical to deliberative excellence, and the moral education of the people is one of their political tasks. Finally, the excellent leadership of the city makes it possible to attain extreme happiness by adhering to sound thought on metaphysical matters (God, the manner with which He must be described and represented) and psychology (the fate of the soul in the afterlife, and divine fortune and misfortune).
Political science that is a part of philosophy is limited—in what it investigates of the voluntary actions, ways of life, and dispositions, and in the rest of what it investigates—to universals and to giving their patterns. It also brings about cognizance of the patterns for determining particulars: how, by what, and by what extent they ought to be determined. It leaves them undetermined in actuality, because determining in actuality belongs to a faculty other than philosophy and perhaps because the circumstances and occurrences with respect to which determination takes place is infinite and without limitation.72
For al-Fārābī and Averroes, as discussed below, philosophy does not, in addressing politics, determine concrete measures relating to the organization of the judiciary or the distribution of power within the State. In place of this work, which is at the heart of the Aristotelian undertaking in Politics, we see the emergence of a reflection on politeia as a perfect entanglement of human excellence, and the realization of the nature of man, i.e. of his ontological
Thanks to the reading and commentary of Aristotle, the theory of human perfections, as we see it in al-Fārābī and Averroes, goes beyond what seems to be a contradiction in Aristotle’s texts, highlighting the fact that it is simply a shift in perspective. This apparent contradiction can be seen in a comparison between Book VI of Nicomachean Ethics, which posits that prudence constitutes happiness, and that it is activity within the city that provides it, and Book X, which establishes, in Chapter 8, that prudence, the supreme virtue of the practical intellect, is linked to the passions and thus to the irrational nature of the soul. This opposition between the virtue of the rationally calculating part of the soul (phronēsis) and the excellence of its scientific part (sophia), is abandoned in De Anima, in which the terminology pits practical intellect against theoretical intellect. It is indeed the same intellect, however when it undertakes reasoning with a goal in mind, it is practical, whereas when the reasoning relates to objects unrelated to practice, it is theoretical (De Anima, III 10, 433a). The difficulty resides in the fact that the Nicomachean Ethics widens the gap between prudence and the other virtues in order to emphasize what distinguishes the excellence of the politician, whereas the other texts that adopt a noetic perspective draw them closer by subsuming these various cognitive aspects under the rational part of the soul.
In view of these diverse perspectives on the approach to the virtues man is capable of, Arab philosophers undertook to resolve the tensions underlying the different parts of the Aristotelian corpus. For them, the happiest life is not political life, but rather life according to intellect. This is what brings us closer to the shores of the divine and promises us a kind of separation. Fulfilment therefore corresponds to supreme bliss, and it is continuous thought that achieves the purpose for which man exists. The Arab Aristotelian philosophers therefore settle this debate by taking noetics, i.e. the study of man’s cognitive
6 Downgrading Phronēsis, Highlighting Practical Intellect: Still Aristotle?
These developments demonstrate how the tensions that enliven Aristotle’s political philosophy have been resolved by Arabic Peripatetics thanks to the articulation of noetic, metaphysical and ethical-political levels. Although this work takes its inspiration from commentaries on Aristotle’s texts, its results lead to territories where Aristotle’s doctrine is no longer fully recognizable. However, these results nevertheless maintain a common thread that connects them to the other texts that are subject to commentary. To measure meaning and impact in the field of political philosophy, three points resulting from the reformulation of the theory of human perfections by Arab philosophers must be addressed.
When the theoretical sciences are isolated and their possessor does not have the faculty of exploiting them for the benefit of others, they are defective philosophy. To be a truly perfect philosopher one has to possess both the theoretical sciences and the faculty for exploiting them for the benefit of all others according to their capacity. Were one to consider the case of the true philosopher, he would find no difference between him and the supreme ruler. For he who possesses the faculty for exploiting what is comprised by the theoretical matters for the benefit of all others possesses the faculty for making such matters intelligible as well as for bringing into actual existence those of them that depend on the will. The greater his power to do the latter, the more perfect is his philosophy.74
By establishing that teaching theoretical sciences is essential to attaining ultimate happiness, and that deliberative excellence should be considered as a propaedeutic that prepares one for more elevated excellence, the Fārābian
The secondary effect of restructuring Aristotelian elements around a purely noetic axis relates to the question of happiness, which is no longer solely political, but, above all, intellectual and metaphysical. It can even be described in its theological aspects because it is turned towards the idea of God, the source of absolute perfection, and because it is then linked to all of the dogmas and theoretical knowledge taught in the perfect society with regard to divine attributes, the hierarchy of intellects, prophecy, the status of well-guided leaders and all that constitutes opinions and right actions leading to the salvation of souls. However, as has been highlighted above, the same distinction between deliberative excellence and theoretical excellence is paradoxically dedicated to strong subordination of the political to the metaphysical, and prohibits the autonomy of the latter with regard to the former. According to this analysis, it is therefore impossible to succeed in making political art fully independent from the objectives of salvation in the afterlife. However, this analysis is not based on religious considerations, but is the result of al-Fārābī’s noetic, which has been extended variously by Miskawayh, Avicenna and Averroes by turning the salvation of the soul into a real philosophical problem.
Although it is possible to express this noetic-eschatological plan in line with al-Fārābī’s political philosophy, it can be seen that the difference between ignorant cities and the perfect city lies, definitively, in the fact that the latter promises its citizens the celestial purpose described above. Other cities,
Despite these aspects that draw us considerably further from Aristotle’s political thinking, it is not necessary to interpret subordinating politics to metaphysics from a religious perspective. We must not lose sight of the fact that this representation of the purpose of civil association by al-Fārābī has simultaneously led to the ultimate purpose of man becoming more secular as the fact of converting it into active intellect and cultivating the understanding of intelligibles is an action that starts here on earth. However, it is the expectation for this end that is described as the equivalent of future life and the sheer happiness of the soul after death. In addition, in the movement that relegates honor and utility to pseudo-happiness, as they do not achieve the ultimate purpose of man, al-Fārābī provides a strong theory that would find its way into Latin Averroism and be condemned in the context of Christianity by Etienne Tempier in 1277 because it rightly establishes a strong secular nature to the ultimate purpose of man. This theory states: “There is no position more excellent than attending to philosophy”.78
The third, and no less important effect of the theory of human excellence lies in the distinction between phronēsis and practical intellect. Phronēsis, which is rendered in Arabic as ‘taʿaqqul’, is described as a capacity for inference and deliberative excellence, which can relate to the direction of cities or achieving human welfare, just as it can concern legislation within cities, as quickly indicated in the Book of Letters, by incorporating phronimos with the work
It is this limitation in the scope of prudence that led al-Fārābī to compare this capacity with extreme cunning (al-dahāʾ) and other forms of inference. This shows that this capacity to properly deliberate focuses less on the means than on the purpose as such and that the variation of the latter makes it possible to specify the type of deliberation being addressed. In addition, the cunning person, like the prudent (mutaʿaqqil, phronimos) has an excellent disposition, allowing him to deliberate and to choose well. However, the difference lies in the purposes that, for the prudent, are arranged in line with
Far from being at the core of political philosophy for Arab followers of Aristotle and playing the role that Aristotle gave them in his work, analysis on phronēsis have been mobilized to assess the action of two men who were the origin of a historic period in the story of the beginning of Islam, namely the conflict between ʿAlī, the fourth Caliph, and Muʿāwiya, the winner of the civil war that pitted him against his adversary, and the founder of the Umayyad Caliphate in 661. This historical example is mentioned by al-Fārābī in the Epistle on Intellect and Avempace in the Governance of the Solitary. It can lead back to the question of moral purpose in practical intellect and the option of whether to admire a man whose capacity to infer and deliberate is not directed at the common good, but rather his calculated personal interest. For Aristotle, the distinction between phronēsis and cleverness is in the moral purpose of the action, but, at the same time, shows that phronēsis is not without the mastery of a certain intelligence that is noble when its goal is good and villainy when it is bad (VI. 12, 1144a). This reading axis was adopted by al-Fārābī and Avempace in order to correct the common opinion regarding the appreciation of this historical episode of the Fitna. For al-Fārābī and Avempace, the common representation of practical intellect tended to confuse the phronimos, as described by Aristotle, meaning the politician whose practical intellectual capabilities are focused on the good of the city, and the cunning man or the crafty politician who places his personal interest above that of the group. The two philosophers show that it is necessary to go beyond this common opinion which confuses many things about the true nature of phronēsis. It is commonly held, with the exception of Shiites, that Muʿāwiya is the model for crafty intellect and diplomatic finesse in Arabic political thinking, especially among historians and mirrors for princes’ authors, and this is reason for which he is described as ‘mutaʿaqqil/phronimos’. Thus, the two philosophers show that there is a need to look beyond this commonly held belief, which conflates many aspects of the true nature of prudence. Furthermore, the mass has a proven fascination with this extreme intelligence, which can be separated from any moral assessment of the purposes of political action, and it is for this reason that prudence is also aligned by some authors of political treatises with
7 From the City-State to the City-World: Signs of Universalization in Aristotle’s Political Thinking
One of the most prominent aspects of the theory of human perfections, as we have seen above, consisted of illustrating the need for command in philosophy and legitimizing its objective of organizing all of human knowledge. Theologians, jurists, holders of religious knowledge (hadith, Koranic exegesis, etc.), secretaries, politicians, strategists are all placed under the umbrella of the only intellect that knows the ultimate happiness of man, as well as the means of making people happy. This assumption is the foundation of many discussions on al-Fārābī, which all strike a controversial note, for the recognition of philosophy, rather than religion or other human knowledge, as the queen of sciences and the ultimate origin of knowledge, from both chronological and ontological perspectives.
On the basis that philosophy reached maturity thanks to Aristotle, who perfected reasoning methods in Organon, and established the path to achieving human excellence, al-Fārābī then arrived to assess the knowledge available in Islamic era, in particular religious knowledge, such as theology (kalām) and law (fiqh), as disciplines inferior to philosophy.
It is clear, al-Fārābī says, that the arts of dialectical theology and jurisprudence are subsequent to religious law, which in turn is subsequent to philosophy, that the dialectical and sophist faculty predated philosophy and that dialectical philosophy and sophist philosophy preceded demonstrative philosophy. Overall, philosophy came before religious law, in the same way that over time, those who use tools come before the tools.86
In the Book of Religion, the same assimilation and subordination of religious knowledge and philosophy is reviewed and extended to other aspects, such as examining the respective role of the prophet who founded a virtuous religious community, and that of the philosopher king who founded the perfect city. These observations demonstrate that philosophy is the only carrier of wisdom permitted to be the origin of norms. Whence discussions on the need to afford philosophers exclusive status at the top of the elite, even if several other groups, such as bearers of religious knowledge and politicians, also vie for the status of the elite within the elite.88 Many issues related to teaching religion, its relationship with philosophy, the difference, within logical arts, between demonstrative and non-demonstrative arguments and, lastly, the use of images and symbols to teach some metaphysical truths to the wider population, originated from the establishment of philosophy and assigning philosophy a political role in guiding the community.89 Nevertheless, it is intellect that
It should be noted that in these developments as brought about by Arab philosophers from Organon, the rhetoric to which Aristotle already assigned an important function within the city90 was further politicized due to the fact that it was integral to teaching the general population (al-ǧumhūr) and for taking responsibility for conveying theological opinions and moral values taken from religion as truths, expressing the same message as in philosophy using demonstrative methods that were adapted from the teaching of philosophical elites.91 The major consequence for our assertion is that the validity of teachings expressed by a religion, both in terms of dogma and moral practice, is measured in al-Fārābī and Averroes by the universality of the religion and its ability to play the same role for the masses as philosophy plays for the academic elite. That is why al-Fārābī believes that virtuous government may involve several religious communities, and Averroes only defends the superiority of Islam compared to other monotheistic religions because it conveys a more universalist message.92 This way of tackling the relationship between religion and philosophy shows how the former can only be virtuous or lead Man to happiness when it is based on the universal teachings of the second.
As the fundamental issue is the transmission of excellence such as defined by a philosophy which lies at the origin of human knowledge and which
This opening to the universal where political science guided by philosophy and assisted by religion no longer recognizes the territorial boundaries of the Greek city is the last point that must be developed in this work. As the thinking of Arab philosophers centers around an issue of government focused on happiness and the attainment of excellences, it is very far removed from speculation on the State, the study of anthropological mechanisms relating to its genesis, or power relationships that make it possible to think of power in concreto. This is important to note because it shows the sense in which they understood Man as a political being. And as this is an issue focused on government and not on power, we must ask ourselves why they were led to think of this tie-in between political philosophy and the idea of universal government, rather than between political philosophy and the City-state, as is the case with Aristotle. Would a pseudo-Aristotle, he of the Letters to Alexander, have played a determining role in this scaling up from the territorial dimensions of the city to that of nations, or even of the federation of several nations?
From the beginning of Islam – to be specific, under the government of the Umayyads – and long before the beginning of the great movement of systematic translation of the texts of Aristotle in the ninth century, a collection of letters entitled the Letters from Aristotle to Alexander was translated to meet the political needs of the new Arab Empire and assimilate certain major teachings of the art of governing as practiced by the Ancients. This text paints a picture of an Aristotle by his pupil’s side, acting as an adviser or minister, dictating to him the best policy for the administration of the lands conquered in Persia and India, bestowing upon him his precious advice and supporting him from
Aristotle presents himself in the Letters as a fervent partisan of a virtuous pambasileia, the defender of a universal and ecumenical State, uniting humankind under the authority of a just and benevolent king, which conflicts with his true political ideas centered on the city, and in general opposed to the idea of the royalty of a single person because it denies the concept of a politeia formed by citizens who are equal and who take turns to be governors and governed.96 Here we find ourselves far from the negative views of barbarians in general, and Persians and Asians in particular (for example in Politics, I, 2, 1252b 8–10 and I, 6, 1255a 29–40 where Aristotle claims that barbarians
In response, it is possible to maintain that dynastic government bringing together several nations (umam, pl of umma) was already at the heart of the political model established by Islam from the Umayyads and especially with the Abbasids. Considering the perfect government on a broader scale to that of the territorial limits of the city may therefore be interpreted as an effect of the culture of Islam and of the institutional model of the universal caliphate. The Letters from Aristotle to Alexander would in that case constitute only a further intellectual caution to support institutional practices already rooted in the societies of the Muslim world.
This is the sovereign over whom no other human being has any sovereignty whatsoever; he is the guide; he is the first sovereign of the excellent city, he is the sovereign of the excellent nation, and the sovereign of the universal state (the oikumenē).99
How strange is the fate of this man, exclaims Averroes concerning Aristotle, and how different is his nature from other human beings! You could say that divine providence has distinguished him in order to show us, we humans, the existence of ultimate perfection in mankind, embodied in such a sensitive and recognizable person. This is why the Ancients called him ‘the divine’.100
8 Conclusion
Our work has shown that the political influence of Aristotle exerted on Arab philosophers is equally due to his strictly political ideas (contained in the Nicomachean Ethics and in the Rhetoric) as to the frequentation of his system, the defense of his method founded on the apodeixis, or the radicalization of certain theses that were powerful yet had not yet been much evidenced in his corpus (the doctrine of the separation of the intellect, the choice of his noetic as the guiding light of any investigation into Man, including politics, the assimilation of the First Mover to the creator God, to the Artisan, to the First Cause or to the Necessary Being). But, ultimately, was this political thinking by the Arab philosophers Aristotelian or not? The response to this question requires taking account of the particular nature of the corpus of each philosopher, something we have tried to emphasize throughout the various different developments. It also involves a critique of the labels that are both massive and reductive, of ‘Neoplatonist’, ‘Platonist’ and ‘Aristotelian’. One could say that al-Fārābī was a political thinker influenced by Neoplatonism because the theory of emanation is present in his cosmology and it affects his political thought. But how can we explain, in that case, the absence of the theory of the scale of sciences, fundamental in these movements, and which implies a gradation in the mastery of virtues and a to-ing and fro-ing between the practical sciences and the theoretical sciences, a mastery of mathematics before descending towards ethics and ascending towards the world of the intelligibles once the soul is purified and brought nearer to the divine?105
Turning to the Aristotelian corpus as such, one may postulate that its influence was limited by the absence of reflection on the regimes and the politeia as Aristotle theorized it, But one may also go beyond the observation of a particular fact (the absence of the Politics) to realize that other biological texts (on the central role of the heart in the animal body) or disciplines a priori without any link to practical philosophy (logic) have had determining consequences on the representation of the perfect city, the characteristics of its leader, or how to educate its citizens. Even further, one may maintain that mastering the major lines of the Aristotelian project as a whole has led Averroes, al-Fārābī and Avempace to resolve, each in their own way, the tensions in the practical philosophy of Aristotle between the happiness of Man and the happiness of the citizen. For us, this point is the cornerstone of the political thinking of the Arab philosophers who believe, each according to their own viewpoint, that
Bibliography
Primary Sources
al-Dawwānī, Akhlaq-i Jalali, trans. W.T. Thompson, Practical Philosophy of Muhammedan People (London, 1839).
al-Fārābī, Al-Taʿālīq al-manṭiqiyya, ed. M.I. Alouzad (Tunis, 1997).
al-Fārābī, Iḥṣāʾ al-ʿulūm, ed. O. Amine (Cairo, 1931).
al-Fārābī, On the Perfect State (Mabādiʾ ārāʾ ahl al-madīna al-fāḍila), ed. R. Walzer (Oxford, 1985).
al-Fārābī, al-Radd ʿalā Ǧālīnūs (The Refutation of Galen), in Al-Fārābī, Risāla fī Aʿḍāʾ al-insān, ed. ʿAbd al-Raḥmān Badawī Rasāʾil Falsafiyya li-al-Kindī wa-al-Fārābī wa-Ibn Bājja wa-Ibn ʿAdī (Beirut, 1980).
Al-Fārābī, Selected Aphorisms, in Alfarabi: Political Writing, trans. C.E. Butterworth (Ithaca, 2001).
Al-Fārābī, The Attainment of Happiness, in Alfarabi’s Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle, trans. M. Mahdi (New York, 1962).
Alfarabi, The Political Writings, vol. II (Ithaca, 2015).
Al-Kindī, al-Rasāʾil al-falsafiyya (Philosophical Epistles) (Cairo, 1950).
Al-Masʿūdī, al-Tanbīh wa l-išrāf, trans. C. de Vaux, Livre de l’avertissement et de la révision (Paris, 1896).
Aristotle, On Rhetoric, trans. G.A. Kennedy (Oxford, 2007).
Aristotle, Politics, trans. E. Barker (Oxford, 1995).
Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics, trans. D. Ross (Oxford, 2009).
Avempace, Risālat al-wadāʿ (Letter of Farewell), in Rasāʾil Ibn Bāǧǧa al-ilāhiyya (Opera metaphysica), ed. M. Fakhry (Beirut, 1991).
Avempace, “Épître de l’adieu”, in Ibn Bāǧǧa, La conduite de l’isolé et deux autres épîtres, ed. C. Genequand (Paris, 2011), pp. 89–120.
Avempace, “The Governance of the Solitary”, in Medieval Political Philosophy: A Sourcebook, trans. L. Berman, ed. R. Lerner and M. Mahdi (New York, 1967).
Averroes, Averroes on Plato’s “Republic”, ed. and trans. R. Lerner (Ithaca, NY, 1974).
Averroes Commentary on Plato’s Republic, ed. E.-J. Rosenthal (Cambridge, 1956).
Averroès (Ibn Rushd), Commentaire moyen à la Rhétorique d’Aristote, vol. II, ed. M. Aouad (Paris, 2002).
Averroes (Ibn Rušd), Kitāb al-Kašf ʿan manāhiğ al-adilla wa ʿaqāʾid al-milla, ed. M.-A. Al Jabri (Beirut, 1998).
Averroes (Ibn Rušd), Talḫīṣ al-qiyās, ed. A. Badawī (Kuwait, 1988).
Bryson and Ibn Sînâ, Penser l’Économique, eds. Y. Seddik and Y. Essid (Tunis, 1995).
Faḫr al-dīn al-Rāzī, Šarḥ ʿuyūn al-ḥikma, vol. 2 (Cairo, 1986).
Ibn Fātik, Muḫtār al-ḥikam wa maḥāsin al-kalim (The Dicts and Sayings of the Philosophers), ed. A. Badawi (Beirut, 1980).
Ibn Khaldūn, The Muqaddimah. An Introduction to History, trans. F. Rosenthal (Princeton, 1958).
Ibn Sīnā, Manṭiq al-mašriqiyyīn (Cairo, 1910).
Ibn Sīnā, Risāla fī aqsām al-ʿulūm al-ʿaqliyya, in Tisʿ rasāʾil (Constantinople, 1880).
Maimonides, The Guide for the Perplexed, vol. 2, trans. S. Pines (Chicago, 1974).
Miskawayh, al-Fawz al-aṣġar, French trans. R. Arnaldez (Tunis, 1987).
Miskawayh, Al-Ḥikma l-ḫālida (Eternal Wisdom), ed. Badawi (Cairo, 1952).
Miskawayh and al-Tawḥīdī, al-Hawāmil wa l-šawāmil (Cairo, 1951); al-Tawḥīdī, Abū Ḥayyān – Miskawayh, Abū ʿAlī, Kitāb al-hawāmil wa-al-šawāmil, ed. Aḥmad Amīn – Aḥmad Ṣaqr (Cairo, 1951).
Miskawayh, Tartīb al-Saʿādāt (The Order of Happiness), ed. al-Suyūṭi (Cairo, 1928).
Nasīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī, The Nasirean Ethics, trans. G.M. Wickens (London, 1964).
Ṣāʿid al-Andalusī, Ṭabaqāt al-umam (Beirut, 1912).
Ṭāš Kubrā Zādeh, Ahmed b. Mustafa, Miftāḥ al-saʿāda, vol. 1 (Beirut, 1985).
Secondary Sources
Abbès, Makram, “Al-Farabi”, in Le bonheur. Dictionnaire historique et critique, ed. M. Gally (Paris, 2019).
Abbès, Makram, “Gouvernement de soi et des autres chez Avempace”, in Studia Islamica 100/101 (2005), pp. 113–160.
Abbès, Makram, “Le concept de politique dans la pensée islamique. Qu’est-ce que la ‘siyâsa’ ?” (“The Concept of Politics in Islamic Thought. What is siyâsa?”), in Archives de Philosophie 82.4 (2019), pp. 683–699.
Abbès, Makram, “Leo Strauss and Arab Philosophy: Medieval versus Modern Enlightenment”, in Diogenes 57.2 (2010), pp. 117–141.
Abbès, Makram, “Le statut de la raison pratique chez Avempace”, in Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 21 (2011), pp. 85–109.
Akasoy, Anna and Alexander Fidora (eds.), The Arabic Version of The Nicomachean Ethics (Leiden, 2005).
Alwishah, Ahmed and Josh Hayes, Aristotle and the Arabic Tradition (Cambridge, 2015).
Aouad, Maroun, “Le texte arabe du chapitre sur la rhétorique d’Ibn Ridwan et ses correspondant dans la Didascalia Rhetoricam Aristotelis ex glosa Alpharabii”, in La Rhétorique d’Aristote. Traditions et commentaires de l’Antiquité au XVIIe siècle, ed. G. Dahan and I. Rosier-Catach (Paris, 1998), pp. 169–225.
Aubenque, Pierre, La prudence chez Aristote (Paris, 1962).
Berti, Enrico, “Phronèsis et science politique”, in Aristote politique, eds. P. Aubenque and A. Tordesillas (Paris, 1993), pp. 435–459.
Bielawski, Józef and Marian Plezia, Lettre d’Aristote à Alexandre sur la politique envers les cités (Krakow, 1970).
Black, Deborah L., “Practical Wisdom in Arabic Philosophy”, in Les philosophies morales et politiques au Moyen-Âge, ed. Carlos Bàzan (New York/Ottawa/Toronto/Legas, 1995), pp. 451–464.
Bodéüs, Richard, Politique et philosophie chez Aristote (Namur, 1991).
Brague, Rémi, “Note sur la traduction arabe de la Politique. Derechef, qu’elle n’existe pas”, in Aristote politique, eds. P. Aubenque and A. Tordesillas (Paris, 1993), pp. 423–433.
Butterworth, Charles E., “Averroes’ Platonization of Aristotle’s Art of Rhetoric”, in La Rhétorique d’Aristote : traditions et commentaires de l’Antiquité au XVIIe siècle, eds. G. Dahan and I. Rosier-Catach (Paris, 1998), pp. 227–240.
Butterworth, Charles E., “Rhetoric and Islamic Political Philosophy”, in International Journal of Middle East Studies 3.2 (1972), pp. 187–98.
Butterworth, Charles E. “The Rhetorician and His Relationship to Community: Three Accounts of Aristotle’s Rhetoric”, in Islamic Theology and Philosophy: Studies in Honor of George F. Hourani, ed. Michael E. Marmura (Albany, NY, 1984), pp. 111–36.
Butterworth, Charles E. (ed.), The Political Aspects of Islamic Philosophy. Essays in Honor of Muhsin S. Mahdi (Harvard, 1992).
Carlier, Pierre, “Étude sur la prétendue lettre d’Aristote à Alexandre transmise par plusieurs manuscrits arabes”, in Ktema 5 (“Autour de la Politique d’Aristote”) (1980), pp. 277–288.
Cohen de Lara, Emma, “Aristotle’s Politics: Ethical Politics or Political Realism”, in Aristotle’s Practical Philosophy. On the Relationship between his Ethics and Politics (Dordrecht, 2017), pp. 13–33.
Crubellier, Michel and Pierre Pellegrin, Aristote. Le philosophe et les savoirs (Paris, 2002).
D’Ancona, Cristina, “The Textual Tradition of the Graeco-Arabic Plotinus. The Theology of Aristotle, Its “ruʾūs al-masāʾil”, and the Greek Model of the Arabic Version”, in The Letter before the Spirit: The Importance of Text Editions for the Study of the Reception of Aristotle, eds. A.M.I. van Oppenraay and R. Fontaine (Leiden, 2012), pp. 37–71.
De Libera, Alain, Penser au Moyen Âge (Paris, 1991).
Doufikar-Aerts, Faustina, Alexander Magnus Arabicus (Paris, 2010).
Druart, Thérèse-Anne, “Al-Fārābī, Ethics and First Intelligibles”, in Documenti e Studi sulla Tradizione filosofica medievale 8 (1997), pp. 403–423.
Emon, Anver M., Islamic Natural Law Theories (Oxford, 2010).
Endress, Gerhard, “L’Aristote arabe : réception, autorité et transformation du Premier Maître”, in Medioevo 23 (1997), pp. 1–42.
Essid, Yassine, A Critique of the Origins of Islamic Economic Thought (Leiden, 1995).
Gannagé, Emma, “Y a-t-il une pensée politique dans Kitāb al-ḥurūf d’al-Fārābī ?”, in Mélanges de l’Université saint-Joseph 57 (2004), pp. 229–257.
Genequand, Ch., “Loi morale, loi politique : al-Fārābī et Ibn Bāǧǧa”, in Mélanges de l’Université Saint-Joseph 61 (2008), pp. 491–514.
Grignaschi, Mario, “La « Siyâsatu-l-ʿâmiyya » et l’influence iranienne sur la pensée politique islamique”, in Acta Iranica. Hommages et opera minora, Volume III, Monumentum H.S. Nyberg (Leiden, 1975), pp. 233–287.
Grignaschi, Mario, “Le roman épistolaire classique conservé dans la version arabe de Sâlim Abû-l-ʿAlâ”, in Muséon 80 (1967), pp. 211–264.
Grignaschi, Mario, “Les « Rasā;ʾil ʾArisṭā;ṭā;līsa ʾilā;-l-Iskandar » de Sā;lim Abū-l-ʿAlā;ʾ et l’activité culturelle à l’époque omayyade”, in Bulletin d’Études Orientales 19 (1965), pp. 7–83.
Guerrero, Rafael Ramón, “Recepción de la Ética Nicomaquea en el mundo árabe: la teoría de la virtud en la filosofía islámica”, in Studia graeco-arabica 4 (2014), pp. 315–334.
Gutas, Dimitri, Avicenna and the Aristotelian Tradition (Leiden, 2014).
Gutas, Dimitri, “The Meaning of madanī in al-Fārābī’s ‘Political’ Philosophy”, in Mélanges de l’Université Saint-Joseph 57 (2004), pp. 259–282.
Hourani, George F., Reason and Tradition in Islamic Ethics (Cambridge, 1985).
Janssens, Jules, “Ibn Bājja and Aristotle’s Political Thought”, in Well begun is Only Half Done: Tracing Aristotle’s Political Ideas in Medieval Arabic, Syriac, Byzantine, and Jewish Sources, ed. V. Syros (Tempe, 2011), pp. 73–95.
Kraut, Richard, Aristotle on the Human Good (Princeton, 1989).
Kraut, Richard, Aristotle. Political Philosophy (Oxford, 2002).
Lameer, Joep, The Arabic Version of Ṭūsī’s Nasirean Ethics (Leiden, 2015).
Lameer, Joep, “The Organon of Aristotle in the Medieval Oriental and Occidental Traditions”, in Journal of the American Oriental Society 116/1 (1996), pp. 90–98.
Mahdi, Muhsin, “Philosophy and Political Thought. Reflections and Comparisons”, in Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 1 (1991), pp. 9–29.
Marcotte, Roxanne D., “Ibn Miskawayh’s Tartīb al-Saʿādāt (The Order of Happiness)”, in Monotheism and Ethics: Historical and Contemporary Intersections among Judaism, Christianity and Islam, ed. Y. Tzvi Langermann (Leiden, 2011), pp. 141–161.
Maróth, Miklós, The Correspondence Between Aristotle and Alexander the Great (Budapest, 2006).
Morel, Pierre-Marie, Aristote. Une philosophie de l’activité (Paris, 2003).
Mulhern, John J., “Politeia in Greek literature, inscriptions, and in Aristotle’s Politics: Reflections on translation and interpretation”, in Aristotle’s Politics: A Critical Guide, eds. T. Lockwood and T. Samaras (Cambridge, 2015), pp. 84–102.
O’Meara, Dominic J., Platonopolis, Platonic Political Philosophy in Late Antiquity (Oxford, 2003).
Parens, Joshua, Metaphysics as Rhetoric: Alfarabi’s Summary of Plato’s “Laws” (Albany, NY, 1995).
Pellegrin, Pierre, L’excellence menacée. Sur la philosophie politique d’Aristote (Paris, 2017).
Pines, Shlomo, “Aristotle’s Politics in Arabic Philosophy”, in Studies in the History of Arabic Philosophy, S. Pines and ed. S. Strousma (Jerusalem, 1996), pp. 251–261.
Schofield, Malcolm, “Aristotle’s Political Ethics”, in The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. R. Kraut (Malden, 2006), pp. 305–322.
Stern, Samuel M., Aristotle on the World-State (Oxford, 1968).
Strauss, Leo, “Farabi’s Plato”, in Louis Ginzberg, Jubilee Volume (New York, 1945), pp. 357–393.
Strauss, Leo, “How Farabi Reads Plato’s Laws”, in Mélanges Louis Massignon, vol. 3 (Damascus, 1957), pp. 319–344.
Syros, Vasileios, “A Note of the Transmission of Aristotle’s Political Ideas in Medieval Persia and Early-Modern India. Was There any Arabic or Persian Translation of the “Politics”?”, in Bulletin de philosophie médiévale 50 (2008), pp. 303–309.
Syros, Vasileios, “Forgotten Commentators Society: Aristotle’s Political Ideas in Arabic, Syriac, Byzantine, and Jewish Garb”, in Well begun is Only Half Done: Tracing Aristotle’s Political Ideas in Medieval Arabic, Syriac, Byzantine, and Jewish Sources, ed. V. Syros (Tempe, 2011), pp. 1–15.
Syros, Vasileios, “Political Treatise”, in Handbook of Medieval Studies, vol. 3, ed. A. Classen (Berlin, 2010), pp. 2001–2008.
Thillet, Pierre, “Aristote conseiller politique d’Alexandre vainqueur des Perses ?”, in Revue des Études Grecques 85/406–408 (1972), pp. 527–542.
Vagelpohl, Uwe, Aristotle’s Rhetoric in the East (Leiden, 2008).
Watt, John W., “Aristotle’s Rhetoric and Political Thought in the Christina Orient and in al-Fārābī, Avicenna and Averroes”, in Well begun is Only Half Done: Tracing Aristotle’s Political Ideas in Medieval Arabic, Syriac, Byzantine, and Jewish Sources, ed. V. Syros (Tempe, 2011), pp. 17–48.
Wirmer, David, “Arabic Philosophy and the Art of Reading. I. Political Philosophy”, in La philosophie arabe à l’étude. Sens, limites et défis d’une discipline moderne, eds. J.-B. Brenet et O.L. Lizzini (Paris, 2019), pp. 179–244.
Woerther, Frédérique, “La Rhétorique d’Aristote comme moyen de diffusion des idées politiques aristotéliciennes dans la philosphie politique arabe : Les Didascalia Rhetoricam ex glosa Alpharabii”, in Well begun is Only Half Done: Tracing Aristotle’s Political Ideas in Medieval Arabic, Syriac, Byzantine, and Jewish Sources, ed. V. Syros (Tempe, 2011), pp. 49–71.
The author uses in this chapter the transliteration system proposed in the journal Arabica.
About this debate in the French philosophical context between Pierre Aubenque and René-Antoine Gauthier, see Enrico Berti, “Phronèsis et science politique”, in Aristote politique, eds. P. Aubenque and A. Tordesillas (Paris, 1993), pp. 435–459.
See on this interpretation, Richard Kraut, Aristotle on the Human Good, (Princeton, 1989).
For further readings on the reception of this text and the various influences it had on Arab philosophers, see Cristina D’Ancona, “The Textual Tradition of the Graeco-Arabic Plotinus. The Theology of Aristotle, Its “ruʾūs al-masāʾil”, and the Greek Model of the Arabic Version”, in The Letter before the Spirit: The Importance of Text Editions for the Study of the Reception of Aristotle, eds. A.M.I. van Oppenraay and R. Fontaine (Leiden/Boston, 2012), pp. 37–71.
Regarding the reception of Aristotle in the Arabic context, see Gerhard Endress, “L’Aristote arabe : réception, autorité et transformation du Premier Maître”, in Medioevo 23 (1997), pp. 1–42, Ahmed Alwishah and Josh Hayes, Aristotle and the Arabic Tradition (Cambridge, 2015), Charles Butterworth (ed.), The Political Aspects of Islamic Philosophy. Essays in Honor of Muhsin S. Mahdi (Harvard, 1992) and Rafael Ramón Guerrero, “Recepción de la Ética Nicomaquea en el mundo árabe: la teoría de la virtud en la filosofía islámica”, in Studia graeco-arabica 4 (2014), pp. 315–334.
See Leo Strauss, Farabi’s Plato, American Academy for Jewish Research, Louis Ginzberg, Jubilee Volume, 1945, pp. 357–393, Leo Strauss, “How Farabi Reads Plato’s Laws”, in Mélanges Louis Massignon, Institut Français de Damas, 1957, Vol. 3, pp. 134–154, Muhsin Mahdi, “Philosophy and Political Thought. Reflections and Comparisons”, in Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 1 (1991), pp. 9–29.
For an illustration of this kind of interpretation of al-Fārābī, see Joshua Parens, Metaphysics as Rhetoric: Alfarabi’s Summary of Plato’s “Laws” (Albany, 1995).
See for example, Charles Butterworth, “Averroes’ Platonization of Aristotle’s Art of Rhetoric”, in La Rhétorique d’Aristote: traditions et commentaires de l’Antiquité au XVIIe siècle, eds. G. Dahan and I. Rosier-Catach (Paris, 1998), pp. 227–240.
For a clarification of these questions, we would like to refer to our work, “Leo Strauss and Arab Philosophy: Medieval versus Modern Enlightenment”, in Diogenes, Number 226, Volume 57, Issue 2, 2010, pp. 101–119. At the time of completion of this work, we read David Wirmer’s article “Arabic Philosophy and the Art of Reading. I. Political Philosophy”, in La philosophie arabe à l’étude. Sens, limites et défis d’une discipline moderne, eds. J.-B. Brenet and O.L. Lizzini (Paris, 2019), pp. 179–244, which deals with the Straussian reading of Arab philosophy. This work will be discussed in another publication.
Richard Walzer offers a perfect example of this approach in the commentary of his edition and translation of one of the major texts by al-Fārābī on the Virtuous City. See Al-Fārābī, On the Perfect State (Mabādiʾ ārāʾ ahl al-madīna al-fāḍila), revised text with introduction, translation, and commentary by R. Walzer (Oxford, 1985).
For textual influences, see in particular Vasileios Syros (ed.), “Forgotten Commentators Society: Aristotle’s Political Ideas in Arabic, Syriac, Byzantine, and Jewish Garb”, in Well begun is Only Half Done, Tempe, Arizona, ACMRS, 2011, pp. 1–16, Vasileios Syros, “A Note of the Transmission of Aristotle’s Political Ideas in Medieval Persia and Early-Modern India. Was There any Arabic or Persian Translation of the “Politics”?”, in Bulletin de philosophie médiévale 50 (2008), pp. 303–309, Vasileios Syros, “Political Treatise”, in Handbook of Medieval Studies, Volume 3, ed. A. Classen (Berlin/New York, 2010), pp. 2000–2021, Shlomo Pines, “Aristotle’s Politics in Arabic Philosophy”, in S. Pines (Author) and S. Strousma (Editor), Studies in the History of Arabic Philosophy (Jerusalem, 1996), pp. 251–261, Rémi Brague, “Note sur la traduction arabe de la Politique. Derechef, qu’elle n’existe pas”, in Aristote politique, eds. P. Aubenque and A. Tordesillas (Paris, 1993), pp. 423–433.
Averroes Commentary on Plato’s Republic, (edited with introduction, translation and notes) E.-J. Rosenthal (Cambridge, 1956), p. 112. The Arabic original of this text has been lost; it has been preserved thanks to a Hebrew translation by Samuel ben Judah at the beginning of the 14th century in Provence. In 1331, Joseph Caspi summarised it, then two Latin translations were published, first by Elia del Medigo in 1491, then by Jacob Mantinius in 1539. In the twentieth century, E.-J. Rosenthal translated it into English as Averroes’ Commentary on Plato’s “Republic” (Cambridge, 1956), then R. Lerner produced a second English version, Averroes on Plato’s Republic (Ithaca/London, 1974). We have used the translation of E.-J. Rosenthal in this chapter.
Al-Kindī, al-Rasāʾil al-falsafiyya (Philosophical Epistles) (Cairo, 1950), p. 384.
Ṣāʿid al-Andalusī, Ṭabaqāt al-umam (Beirut, 1912), p. 26.
Al-Masʿūdī, al-Tanbīh wa l-išrāf, French translation by C. de Vaux, Livre de l’avertissement et de la révision (Paris, 1896), p. 166.
Al-Fārābī, Kitāb al-ḥurūf (the Book of Letters), ed. M. Mahdi (Beirut, 2004), p. 91.
We agree with the opinion of R. Brague who discussed this point in his article “Note sur la traduction arabe de la Politique. Derechef, qu’elle n’existe pas”, in P. Aubenque and A. Tordesillas, Aristote politique, p. 432.
See the text of this treatise in Miklós Maróth, The Correspondance Between Aristotle and Alexander the Great (Budapest, 2006), pp. 85–101. Concerning Miskawayh, see Tartīb al-Saʿādāt (The Order of Happiness)”, ed. al-Suyūṭī (Cairo, 1928), p. 59.
Al-Fārābī, Iḥṣāʾ al-ʿulūm, ed. O. Amine (Cairo, 1931), p. 105.
See Miskawayh, Al-Ḥikma l-ḫālida (Eternal Wisdom), ed. A. Badawi (Cairo, 1952), and Ibn Fātik, Muḫtār al-ḥikam wa maḥāsin al-kalim (The Dicts and Sayings of the Philosophers), ed. A. Badawi (Beirut, 1980).
See the summary of these passages in Shlomo Pines, “Aristotle’s Politics in Arabic Philosophy”, pp. 252–253. Note that quotes suggesting that they come from Politics are juxtaposed against other quotes from Nicomachean Ethics.
For the text used by Arab philosophers, see Anna Akasoy and Alexander Fidora (eds.), The Arabic Version of The Nicomachean Ethics (Leiden/Boston, 2005).
See our work, “Al-Farabi”, in Le bonheur. Dictionnaire historique et critique, ed. M. Gally (Paris, 2019), pp. 245–249.
Al-Fārābī, al-Tanbibīh ʿalā taḥṣīl al-Saʿāda, ed. Jaʿfar al-Yasin (Beirut, 1992), pp. 227–265.
Miskawayh, Tartīb al-Saʿādāt. For a presentation of the contents of this text, see Roxanne D. Marcotte, “Ibn Miskawayh’s Tartīb al-Saʿādāt (The Order of Happiness)”, in Monotheism and Ethics: Historical and Contemporary Intersections among Judaism, Christianity and Islam, ed. Y. Tzvi Langermann (Leiden/Boston, 2011), pp. 141–161.
Concerning Avempace, see the exhaustive study of the influences of Aristotelian sources on this author in Jules Janssens, “Ibn Bājja and Aristotle’s Political Thought”, in Well begun is Only Half Done, pp. 73–95.
See on this topic my article, “Le statut de la raison pratique chez Avempace”, in Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 21 (2011), pp. 85–109.
See Dominic J. O’Meara, Platonopolis, Platonic Political Philosophy in Late Antiquity (Oxford, 2003), pp. 53–68.
See Penser l’Économique, texts by Bryson and Ibn Sînâ, ed. and trans. Y. Seddik and Y. Essid (Tunis, 1995), and concerning economic dimension of tadbīr, Y. Essid, A Critique of the Origins of Islamic Economic Thought (Leiden/New York/Köln, 1995).
Nasīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī, The Nasirean Ethics, trans. from the Persian by G.M. Wickens (London, 1964), p. 28. For the Arabic version, see J. Lameer, The Arabic Version of Ṭūsī’s Nasirean Ethics (Leiden/Boston, 2015), pp. 82–83.
This trend can be seen, for example, in Faḫr al-dīn al-Rāzī, Šarḥ ʿuyūn al-ḥikma, vol. 2 (Cairo, 1986), pp. 6–16, al-Dawwānī, Akhlaq-i Jalali, trans. W.T. Thompson, Practical Philosophy of Muhammedan People (London, 1839), and Ṭāš Kubrā Zādeh, Miftāḥ al-saʿāda, vol. 1 (Beirut, 1985), pp. 378–394.
Ibn Sīnā, Manṭiq al-mašriqiyyīn (Cairo, 1910), p. 7. See also Risāla fī aqsām al-ʿulūm al-ʿaqliyya, in Tisʾ rasāʾil (Constantinople, 1880), pp. 73–74.
On Avicenna’s lack of interest in practical philosophy, see Dimitri Gutas, Avicenna and the Aristotelian Tradition (Leiden/Boston, 2014), pp. 292–296 and pp. 497–498.
Al-Fārābī, Selected Aphorisms, in Alfarabi, Political Writing, trans. C.E. Butterworth (Ithaca, 2001), § 25, p. 23.
Al-Fārābī, Selected Aphorisms, § 26, p. 24.
Avicenna, Manṭiq al-mašriqiyyīn, pp. 7–8.
Al-Fārābī, Kitāb al-siyāsa al-madaniyya (Political Regime), trans. C.E. Butterworth, in Alfarabi, The Political Writings, Volume II (Ithaca, 2015), pp. 60–61. We have slightly modified the translation.
Avempace, The Governance of the Solitary, trans. L. Berman, in Medieval Political Philosophy: A Sourcebook, eds. R. Lerner and M. Mahdi (New York, 1967), p. 125.
See Makram Abbès, “Gouvernement de soi et des autres chez Avempace”, in Studia Islamica 100/101 (2005), pp. 113–160.
Averroès (Ibn Rushd), Commentaire moyen à la Rhétorique d’Aristote, ed. and trans. M. Aouad, vol. 2 (Paris, 2002), p. 68.
Averroes’ Commentary on Plato’s Republic, p. 214.
Ibn Khaldūn, The Muqaddimah. An Introduction to History, trans. F. Rosenthal (Princeton, 1958), chapter III: section 50, p. 138.
Dimitri Gutas, “The Meaning of madanī in al-Fārābī’s ‘Political’ Philosophy”, in Mélanges de l’Université Saint-Joseph 57 (2004), p. 259.
We find this term in Avempace’s Commentary on the Logic of al-Fārābī, Al-Taʿālīq al-manṭiqiyya, ed. M.I. Alouzad (Tunis, 1997), p. 27.
Gutas, “The Meaning of madanī in al-Fārābī’s ‘Political’ Philosophy”, p. 261.
Gutas, “The Meaning of madanī in al-Fārābī’s ‘Political’ Philosophy”, p. 263.
Gutas, “The Meaning of madanī in al-Fārābī’s ‘Political’ Philosophy”, p. 264.
The same is valid for the intellectual traditions developed in the West. Does Machiavelli approach politics as Bodin, Erasmus, Bossuet or Thomas More do, only choosing authors close in time? The range of approaches (theological-religious, historical-literary and legal-institutional) should not result in the exclusion of one aspect in favour of another. In our view, they try to account for the complexity of relations between people, which reflect their political condition in different ways.
For conceptual clarifications, we would refer to our work, “Le concept de politique dans la pensée islamique. Qu’est-ce que la ‘siyâsa’ ?” (“The Concept of Politics in Islamic Thought. What is siyâsa?”), in Archives de Philosophie 82/4 (2019), “Penser la politique en Islam”, pp. 683–699.
This is what leads Dimitri Gutas, “The Meaning of madanī in al-Fārābī’s ‘Political’ Philosophy”, p. 269, to consider Dunlop’s translation, “statesman” incorrect.
Al-Fārābī, Selected Aphorisms, in Alfarabi, Political Writing, § 4, p. 12.
Al-Fārābī, Iḥṣāʾ al-ʿulūm, pp. 102–107.
In contemporary times, the word is used to refer to “civilization” and is synonymous with tamaddun, a word of the same root. The roots of this meaning are already present in the analysis put forward by Miskawayh, as shown below.
Miskawayh and al-Tawḥīdī, al-Hawāmil wa l-šawāmil (Cairo, 1951), p. 250.
Aristotle, Politics, trans. E. Barker (Oxford, 1995), I. 2, 1252b 29–30, p. 10.
Aristotle, Politics, p. 333.
Aristotle, On Politics, III, 17.
John J. Mulhern, “Politeia in Greek literature, inscriptions, and in Aristotle’s Politics: Reflections on translation and interpretation”, in Aristotle’s Politics: A Critical Guide, eds. T. Lockwood and T. Samaras (Cambridge, 2015), p. 84.
Mulhern, “Politeia in Greek literature”, p. 100.
See Charles Genequand, “Loi morale, loi politique : al-Fārābī et Ibn Bāǧǧa”, in Mélanges de l’Université Saint-Joseph 61 (2008), pp. 501–502.
Genequand, “Loi morale, loi politique”, p. 503.
See Richard Kraut, Aristotle. Political Philosophy (Oxford, 2002), Malcolm Schofield, “Aristotle’s Political Ethics”, in The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. R. Kraut (Malden, 2006), pp. 305–322, Emma Cohen de Lara, “Aristotle’s Politics: Ethical Politics or Political Realism”, in Aristotle’s Practical Philosophy. On the Relationship between his Ethics and Politics (Dordrecht, 2017), pp. 13–33, Richard Bodéüs, Politique et philosophie chez Aristote (Namur, 1991), particularly ch. I “Les dimensions de l’excellence politique”, P.-M. Morel, Aristote (Paris, 2003), and Pierre Pellegrin, L’excellence menacée. Sur la philosophie politique d’Aristote (Paris, 2017).
Michel Crubellier and Pierre Pellegrin, Aristote. Le philosophe et les savoirs (Paris, 2002), pp. 188 and 208.
Averroes’ Commentary on Plato’s Republic, p. 112.
Miskawayh, al-Fawz al-aṣġar, French translation by R. Arnaldez (Tunis, 1987), p. 56.
Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, book II 1, 1103a.
This is what he does in a treatise entitled al-Tanbibīh ʿalā taḥṣīl al-Saʿāda (“Reminder of the Way to Happiness”) or in the Selected Aphorisms.
Al-Fārābī, The Attainment of Happiness, in Alfarabi’s Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle, trans. M. Mahdi (New York, 1962), p. 13.
Averroes’ Commentary on Plato’s Republic, pp. 188–197.
For Avempace, see Risālat al-wadāʿ (Letter of Farewell), in Rasāʾil Ibn Bāǧǧa al-ilāhiyya (Opera mataphysica), ed. M. Fakhry (Beirut, 1991) and Épître de l’adieu, in Ibn Bāǧǧa, La conduite de l’isolé et deux autres épîtres, introduction, critical edition of the Arabic text, translation and commentary by C. Genequand (Paris, 2011), pp. 89–120. The same typology from Avempace is used by Maimonides, with some minor differences. See Maimonides, The Guide for the Perplexed, trans. S. Pines (Chicago, 1974), vol. 2, III 54, pp. 634–636.
Dimitri Gutas, “The Meaning of madanī in al-Fārābī’s ‘Political’ Philosophy”, p. 263.
Al-Fārābī, The Book of Religion, in Alfarabi: The Political Writings, trans. C. Butterworth (Ithaca, 2001), § 15, p. 106.
Al-Fārābī, The Attainment of Happiness, in Alfarabi’s Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle, p. 26.
Al-Fārābī, The Attainment of Happiness, p. 43.
See Michel Crubellier and Pierre Pellegrin, Aristote. Le philosophe et les savoirs, pp. 211–213.
Al-Fārābī, The Attainment of Happiness, p. 46.
Al-Fārābī, The Attainment of Happiness, pp. 23–24.
See Alain de Libera, Penser au Moyen Âge (Paris, 1991), p. 147.
Al-Fārābī, Kitāb al-ḥurūf, § 112, p. 133.
Al-Fārābī, The Book of Religion, § 18. p. 107.
See Pierre Aubenque, La prudence chez Aristote (Paris, 1962), in which he brilliantly demonstrated this aspect of Aristotelian political philosophy.
See on this point the illuminating analyses by Deborah L. Black, “Practical Wisdom in Arabic Philosophy”, in Les philosophies morales et politiques au Moyen-Âge, ed. C. Bàzan (New York/Ottawa/Toronto, 1995), pp. 451–464.
Al-Fārābī, Selected Aphorisms, §58, p. 37. See also, Al-Fārābī, The Book of Religion, § 14d, pp. 105–106.
Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics, trans. D. Ross (Oxford, 2009), VI. 12, 1144a 25, pp. 115–116.
Al-Fārābī, Selected Aphorisms, § 39, pp. 31–32.
Al Fārābī, Kitāb al-ḥurūf, p. 132.
For an exhaustive approach to these points, see Emma Gannagé, “Y a-t-il une pensée politique dans Kitāb al-ḥurūf d’al-Fārābī ?”, in Mélanges de l’Université saint-Joseph 57 (2004), pp. 229–257.
See al-Fārābī, Kitāb al-ḥurūf, § 113, pp. 133–134.
With regard to the influence of Aristotle’s Rhetoric on the political ideas of Arab philosophers, see in particular Uwe Vagelpohl, Aristotle’s Rhetoric in the East (Leiden/Boston, 2008), John W. Watt, “Aristotle’s Rhetoric and Political Thought in the Christina Orient and in al-Fārābī, Avicenna and Averroes”, in Well Begun is Only Half Done, ed. V. Syros, pp. 17–47, and Frédérique Woerther, “La Rhétorique d’Aristote comme moyen de diffusion des idées politiques aristotéliciennes dans la philosphie politique arabe: Les Didascalia Rhetoricam ex glosa Alpharabii”, in Well Begun is Only Half Done, ed. V. Syros, pp. 49–71, Charles E. Butterworth, “The Rhetorician and His Relationship to Community: Three Accounts of Aristotle’s Rhetoric”, in Islamic Theology and Philosophy: Studies in Honor of George F. Hourani, ed. M.E. Marmura, pp. 111–136 (Albany, 1984), Charles E. Butterworth, “Averroes’ Platonization of Aristotle’s Art of Rhetoric”, in La Rhétorique d’Aristote: traditions et commentaires de l’Antiquité au XVIIe siècle, ed. G. Dahan and I. Rosier-Catach, pp. 227–240 (Paris, 1998), Charles E. Butterworth, “Rhetoric and Islamic Political Philosophy”, in International Journal of Middle East Studies 3, no. 2 (1972), pp. 187–98, Lameer, Joep, “The Organon of Aristotle in the Medieval Oriental and Occidental Traditions”, in Journal of the American Oriental Society 116, no. 1 (1996), pp. 90–98, Maroun Aouad, “Le texte arabe du chapitre sur la rhétorique d’Ibn Ridwan et ses correspondant dans la Didascalia Rhetoricam Aristotelis ex glosa Alpharabii”, in G. Dahan and I. Rosier-Catach, La Rhétorique d’Aristote, pp. 169–225.
Aristotle, On Rhetoric, I, 2, 1356a 25, trans. G.A. Kennedy (Oxford, 2007), p. 39. “rhetoric is like some offshoot [paraphues] of dialectic and ethical studies (which is rightly called politics)”.
In al-Fārābī and Averroes, there is a true philosophy of religion which is the principal effect of the study of the logical arts, and which has been stimulated by the conflict between philosophers and theologians in Islamic lands. In view of the limits of this work, and the fact that this philosophy is not Aristotelean in origin, this point, which is very important in studying the relationship between religion, philosophy and politics, will not be tackled here.
Averroes, Kitāb al-Kašf ʿan manāhiğ al-adilla wa ʿaqāʾid al-milla, ed. Mohamed-Abid Al Jabri (Beirut, 1998), p. 184.
See on this point Thérèse-Anne Druart, “Al-Fārābī, Ethics and First Intelligibles”, in Documenti e Studi sulla Tradizione filosofica medievale 8 (1997), pp. 403–423. For an overview of the theological and legal schools of thought of Islam, see Anver M. Emon, Islamic Natural Law Theories (Oxford, 2010). See also, Al-Fārābī, On the Perfect State (Mabādiʾ ārāʾ ahl al-madīna al-fāḍila), IV, 13, § 3, pp. 202–205.
See about the figure of Alexander the Great in the East, and his links with Aristotle: Mario Grignaschi, “La “Siyâsatu-l-ʿâmiyya” et l’influence iranienne sur la pensée politique islamique”, in Acta Iranica. Hommages et opera minora, Volume III, Monumentum H. S. Nyberg (Leiden, 1975); “Les “Rasā;ʾil ʾArisṭā;ṭā;līsa ʾilā;-l-Iskandar” de Sā;lim Abū-l-ʿAlā;ʾ et l’activité culturelle à l’époque omayyade”, in Bulletin d’études orientales 19 (1965), pp. 7–83; “Le roman épistolaire classique conservé dans la version arabe de Sâlim Abû-l-ʿAlâ”, in Muséon 80 (1967), pp. 211–64; Faustina Doufikar-Aerts, Alexander Magnus Arabicus (Paris/Leuven/Walpole, 2010).
As far as this corpus, which is largely apocrypha, is concerned, although it has played a fundamental role in the Arab tradition of the mirrors for princes, as well as in the literature of maxims and aphorisms, see the complete text in Miklós Maróth, The Correspondance Between Aristotle and Alexander the Great.
These are controversial points because some passages of Politics, from pieces of the Letters to Alexander that may be considered authentic, as well as the biography of the two men, leave open the question of the evolution of Aristotle’s political thought, and multiply the interpretations which could reconcile the various different sources. See, in connection with this, the discussions relating to the authenticity of one of the pieces of this corpus, Józef Bielawski and Marian Plezia, Lettre d’Aristote à Alexandre sur la politique envers les cités (Wrocaw/Warszava/Krakow, 1970), Pierre Thillet, “Aristote conseiller politique d’Alexandre vainqueur des Perses?”, in Revue des Études Grecques 85/406–408 (1972), pp. 527–542, Pierre Carlier, “Étude sur la prétendue lettre d’Aristote à Alexandre transmise par plusieurs manuscrits arabes”, in Autour de la Politique d’Aristote, Ktema 5 (1980), pp. 277–288. On the specific question of universal government, see Samuel M. Stern, Aristotle on the World-State (Oxford, 1968).
The question of Aristotle’s true opinion on the barbarians remains debatable as in certain texts such as The Nicomachean Ethics (VIII, 1, 1055a 21–22), he puts forward ideas on the existence of friendship between men, independently of their ethnic or other origins, which leads to the severe judgments pronounced on non-Greeks being relativized.
Al-Fārābī, al-Radd ʿalā Ǧālīnūs (The Refutation of Galen), in Al-Fārābī, Risāla fī Aʿḍāʾ al-insān, ed. ʿAbd al-Raḥmān Badawī Rasāʾil Falsafiyya li-al-Kindī wa-al-Fārābī wa-Ibn Bājja wa-Ibn ʿAdī (Beirut, 1980), pp. 83–87.
Al-Fārābī, On the Perfect State (Mabādiʾ ārāʾ ahl al-madīnat al-fāḍilah), V, 15, § 11, p. 247. The translation is slightly modified.
Ibn Rušd (Averroes), Talḫīṣ al-qiyās, ed. A. Badawī (Kuwait, 1988), p. 91.
Averroes’ Commentary on Plato’s Republic, p. 153.
George F. Hourani, “Averroes on Good and Evil”, in Reason and Tradition in Islamic Ethics (Cambridge, 1985), pp. 268–269.
Averroès, Commentaire moyen à la Rhétorique d’Aristote, 1. 13. 2 p. 113 & 1. 15. 9, p. 125.
Averroès, Commentaire moyen à la Rhétorique d’Aristote, vol. 1, p. 121.
Dominic J. O’Meara, Platonopolis. Platonic Political Philosophy in Late Antiquity, pp. 53–68.
See for Aristotle, the Nicomachean Ethics, X, 10, 1181b 15, and for al-Fārābī, The Attainment of Happiness, p. 23.
See on this aspect the relevant remarks of Pierre-Marie Morel in the conclusion to his work Aristote, pp. 250–252.