The discussion thus far has been concerned with administrative adjudication. It is now time to examine another administrative function of increasing importance in the business of government, rulemaking.455 Two types of administrative action, contracts and the exercise of police powers, will be considered in the following chapter. Administrative rulemaking has a twofold importance from the perspective of the common core. On the one hand, the procedural issues that it poses are distinct from those concerning administrative adjudication.456 While adjudication is based on the paradigm of the judicial proceeding, with the principles of due process rooted in European laws, rulemaking is akin to legislation and requires distinct procedural tools, such as consultation and participation. On the other hand, there is the question of whether the factual analysis confirms the diversity – pointed out in Chapter 6 – that characterizes general legislation on administrative procedure. As a first step, we will take a closer look at the whole problem of rulemaking. Next, our factual analysis will focus on three cases concerning the existence of the power to adopt rules in the absence of a specific legislative basis, citizens’ consultation before a policy change adversely affecting them and, lastly, the publication of rules. The final section of the chapter will briefly touch on the more general issue of the significance of rulemaking for the common core.
1 Variety of Administrative Rules
In the past, it was often taken for granted that a fundamental division existed – and had to be maintained – between rules and decisions as a consequence of separation of powers. Rules had to be both general and abstract, in the sense of defining standards of conduct for a pre-defined class or category of persons and legal relationships. They had to be adopted by parliamentary bodies, which at the beginning of the twentieth century were regarded as being
Congress passes a broadly worded statute. The agency follows with regulations containing broad language, open-ended phrases, ambiguous standards and the like. Then as years pass, the agency issues circulars or guidance or memoranda, explaining, interpreting, defining and often expanding the commands in the regulations.459
In Europe, the importance of administrative rules was confirmed in the late 1950’s by the Treaty of Rome with a view to legal harmonization.460 Its norms
Administrative rules are highly differentiated. There are interpretative rules (which explain the contents and effects of legislative and regulatory provisions), policy statements, procedural rules, and others governing the organization of an agency such as codes of practice and guidelines for enforcement officers. Moreover, whereas in several legal systems – such as Germany and Italy – public authorities may adopt regulations only if authorized to do so, this is not the case for administrative rules. Sometimes these rules are adopted on the basis of enabling legislative provisions. Other rules are adopted by agencies themselves as an alternative to achieving policy goals through individualized adjudication, which can be controversial.461 Rules will have sometimes have to be applied on a case by case basis, but they will often nevertheless ‘be determinative of the result and will strongly influence the outcome’.462 Other times, they will be directly binding, like regulations.463 The question that thus arises is how administrative rules can be discerned. Various elements appear to be of legal relevance in this context, including the general applicability of a precept and its future effects. A precept is regarded as being general when it applies to a pre-defined class of persons or legal entities, though they are still relatively few. It must also be prospective, in the sense that it applies not only to legal relationships or situations existing at the time of the enactment but also to those that come into existence later.464
From the practical point of view, there are various advantages associated with the increase of administrative rules but also some drawbacks. Rulemaking serves to organize the work of government officers, thus promoting efficiency.
2 Standardless Discretion?
Some words should be said to explain the choice of the first issue, which is of particular importance from the perspective of the common core. Until some decades ago, in Europe there were two opposite visions of the relationship between rules and discretion. One was reflected in the no-fettering rule, while the other required public authorities to rigorously limit and structure their discretionary powers.
The first position prevailed in Britain and other Westminster-type democracies. It was clearly expressed by the House of Lords in the well-known British Oxygen case.468 What was established was that a public body may not unlawfully fetter a discretionary power granted by statute. The underlying basis was, ultimately, the doctrine of parliamentary sovereignty. Thus, even if Parliament
Conversely, in both Germany and Italy, administrative courts held that if legislation did not define standards for exercising discretion in individual cases, the public authority was required to predetermine the canons of conduct.471 Otherwise, there was the risk that discretion could be used very differently from case to case and thus degrade into arbitrariness. The phrase coined by German lawyers, ‘Selbsbindung der Verwaltung’, expresses the idea that the administrative authority must, first, adopt a binding rule governing its action and, second, respect it. The bindingness of the rules adopted by public authorities was justified, also in other European legal cultures, by the principles of coherence and legal certainty expressed in the maxim patere legem tuam quam ipse fecisti (that is, you are bound by your own rule).472
On the other side of the Atlantic, in his essay on discretionary justice, Davis’ dissented from Dicey. He also dissented from ‘European writers [considering] what they call ‘the principle of legality’ to mean that discretion must be guided by rules’.473 Empirically, he found that both police and border control officers, as well as prosecutors, exercised very broad discretionary powers and argued that, in order to avoid arbitrariness, they had to limit their discretion, structure its exercise, and thus make it accountable.474 This was an important step beyond the simplistic ideals that dominated the liberal period, according to which discretion had to be eliminated, and opened up the field for new thinking about the relationship between rules and discretion.
Prescriptively, Dicey was a liberal and was thus concerned with what was later called administrative despotism,475 while Giannini was a public lawyer who developed a functionalist approach to public law in the interwar period and beyond. They opined that, with the widening of the sphere of government, the use of discretionary powers was simply necessary for the efficient conduct of business and, ultimately, for the promotion of social change. Several consequences followed on from this. Social interests, rather than legal rules, lay at the heart of the legal order, and the courts of law were deemed ill-equipped to control the exercise of discretion, particularly with regard to the issues arising under social legislation. The no-fettering doctrine thus appeared to him as one the most striking differences between the English legal system and what he called ‘the continental system’.476 In the former, if a public authority relinquishes exercise of statutory discretionary power, its conduct is incompatible with the law. Referring to the no-fettering doctrine was, in sum, a way of expressing greater faith in administrative bodies than in courts. However, the more legislation was characterized by broad, open-textured provisions, the more it became necessary to discipline the exercise of discretion, as will become clear from the discussion to follow.
Descriptively, things differ from the way in which they were portrayed. In the UK, the fact that an agency does not have express power to adopt standards of administrative conduct does not, per se, imply that they are invalid if it adopts them. Invalidity would be sanctioned by the courts when a standard works as an inflexible or invariable rule, in the sense that it prescribes the conduct of administrative officers rather than assisting them in their exercise of discretionary power. In other words, exercising such power must not be determined automatically by a rigid choice made in advance. This is the context in which the no-fettering doctrine has been seen in relation to public law values of fairness and transparency. Thus, for example, in Bushell, the House of Lords held that ministers, in exercising their discretion, ‘as in exercising any other administrative function …, owe a constitutional duty to perform
While the above contributes to clarifying the substantive side of the question concerning the admissibility of rules aiming to structure the exercise of discretion, their effects can only be discerned by looking at the relevant legislative provisions granting a public authority discretionary power, in addition to observing governmental practice and judicial interpretation. There is, moreover, a procedural side concerning the ways a public authority may make rules. Various mechanisms can be used to control it, including parliamentary scrutiny, consultation, and judicial review.
Our hypothetical case regards the rules regulating the disbursement of public money. We assume that parliamentary legislation enables public money to be granted to toy manufacturers that promote a particular social goal: greater environmental awareness in children under the age of ten. According to this legislation, the Department of the Environment can award grants to the producers of the new games. The Department decides to establish some rules of practice, including one whereby it would not award grants for any game costing more than a certain amount of money. When a producer applies for a grant for a new game, its application is rejected on the grounds that the sale price of the game exceeds the amount of money established in advance. The producer thus brings a claim before the court, claiming that, before defining its rules of practice or standards, the Department should have consulted the stakeholders, instead of acting unilaterally. The public authority objects that there is no legislative provision requiring it to consult stakeholders before adopting any rule
The distinction just made between the two limbs of our hypothetical case is helpful from a comparative perspective. As far as the first limb is concerned, all the legal systems examined recognized the existence of legal rules that do not directly affect the rights and interests of individuals, but confine and structure the discretionary powers granted to public authorities. They admit the adoption of rules of this type and distinguish. One thing is whether administrative rules are inflexible, insofar as they leave no measure of discretion to decision-makers, for instance by indicating a mandatory process rather than a recommended but optional one. Another thing is whether rules are conditional or flexible, for example by allowing officials to do something if a certain circumstance is fulfilled, which comes close to the idea of how discretion should be exercised ‘normally’ but not invariably. Moreover, the importance of consultation is recognized.480 There are, obviously, variants concerning, for example, the existence of a general duty to predetermine the standards of administrative conduct (which in Italy has been codified by administrative procedure legislation but does not exist elsewhere),481 a duty to consult stakeholders before adopting rules aiming at interpreting or implementing legislation, and the binding nature of implementing rules. It is for the courts, therefore, to define the possible role of consultation.482
There are three relevant aspects for this purpose: legislative intent, precedents, and general principles. Courts look at the language of legislative provisions in order to see if it there is an explicit or implicit support for consultation. In the former case, the absence of consultation will be regarded as a procedural infringement. In the latter, it will be regarded as a choice that requires appropriate justification. The courts will also consider past government practice. Thus, for example, if in other cases the same public authority has consulted
Conversely, as regards the other limb of our hypothetical case, namely judicial reaction, there is disagreement between the legal systems included in our comparison. In some of them, notably in the UK, unless there is something in the wording of the statute that indicates Parliament’s intent to grant the public authority the authority to issue guidelines or rules, the courts will most probably quash the challenged rule. The reason is, that the rule is used not as a flexible but as a mandatory tool and, consequently, leaves no margin of discretion to government officials; in other words, it is entirely binding on the decision-makers.483 Conversely, in other legal systems such as those of Italy and Serbia, the judge will probably be satisfied with ascertaining that a standard of administrative conduct has been pre-determined and has been respected in the particular case. Though the latter feature does not focus on the rule itself, but on its application, it must not be neglected because it evokes the existence of an enforceable legitimate expectation. In still other legal systems, a court will deem that, if there is a procedural weakness, it can be remedied and will require the public authority to carry out a consultation before the end of the judicial process.
3 Consultation before Policy Change
Given the importance of the administrative choices that affect the public at large, the analysis of another case has been deemed advisable. It concerns consulting the public before a decisive policy change. The previous discussion is also relevant here, as is general legislation on administrative procedure. There are, however, some distinctive traits, which will be discussed shortly after setting out the hypothetical case.
We imagine that under national legislation local authorities are required to provide a comprehensive library service. The term ‘comprehensive service’ is not defined in the legislation, however. It is the responsibility of local authorities to determine how to deliver public library services in the light of local needs and available funding. But there is a legislative duty to consult users, and the Ministry for culture and media can order an inquiry when there is a concern that a local authority is failing to fulfil its duties. When a local authority announces on its website that it is going to close three of its five public libraries and drastically reduce the opening hours of the remaining two libraries, a consumer association challenges this change of policy and argues that it ought to be consulted before a final decision is taken. The local authority simply asserts that its decision is due to financial difficulties and adopts the decision. The consumer association then brings a case before a court on the grounds that: a) the duty to consult users should be taken very seriously when a decision is likely to deprive them of existing benefits; b) consultation should thus occur when proposals are at a formative stage rather than on the point of being adopted; c) the local authority should consider more than one option, weighing up their advantages and disadvantages, also in the light of the users’ observations. As in the previous case, we seek to understand whether the court would endorse any of these arguments and, if so, whether it would be willing to quash the challenged decision.
At least two distinctive traits between this case and the previous one deserve a mention. The first is that in this case the focus is on determining a policy,
It is clear from our comparative analysis that legal systems differ as to how services must be performed, as well as whether interested individuals and groups should be given an opportunity to submit statements and produce evidence supporting or opposing the proposed policy change.484 Several consequences flow from this difference, including whether the public authority should make public a concise general statement about the purposes of its action. There is, first of all, divergence concerning the existence of national legislative provisions governing the organization of public libraries. Lithuania has legislation of this type, while other nations do not. Secondly, there are differences in procedural requirements. While our hypothetical case supposes that a legislative duty to consult users exists and then goes on to ask what the consequences of its infringement would be, in reality such a duty does not exist outside but a few legal systems. This is not the case, for example, with Hungary, while in Germany the rules governing local planning might be applied, by way of analogy. Spain is at the opposite end of the spectrum as it has legislation requiring public consultation before a public service may be severely reduced or dismantled. Thirdly, judicial attitudes towards consultation differ remarkably. The Spanish legal system is, again, illustrative of increased participatory rights, because courts will annul an act which implements policy change carried out
However, there is an area of agreement between almost all those legal systems on two general points. First, with the notable exception of Hungary, there is an emerging propensity of both legislators and judges to promote the citizens’ right to be provided with a meaningful opportunity to make their voices heard before a public authority makes a policy change which may adversely affect them. General legislation on administrative procedure would be applied, for example, within the legal systems of Italy and Ukraine. Second, if there is a legislative duty to consult users before making a policy change, as is supposed in our hypothetical case, then the local authority is required to take it seriously everywhere. Thus, for example, in the UK the courts enforce the duty to act fairly, also in the light of the democratic principle that the public must be involved in policy choices affecting it. Similarly, in Italy, the administrative court would most probably endorse the applicant’s claim that if the local authority is unable to prove that the decision severely cutting services was the only possible one in view of financial difficulties, and annul it.491 In Belgium,
4 Partially Unpublished Rules
Another controversial issue concerning administrative rules is information. This is controversial because administrative rules are governed by different norms from those that govern administrative adjudication and legislation. Briefly, the most basic requirement is that decisions regarding individuals must be notified to their addressees, though some legal systems have set a higher standard in the sense that identifiable third parties must also receive notification, for example when the issuance of a building permit for a factory impinges on the interests of neighbors. As regards legislation, a traditional feature of liberal democracies is that it must be published in some form if it is to be obeyed and respected. It normally comes into operation either on the date it is published (as distinct from the date on which it is made) or on a subsequent date. The underlying rationale in France is the principle dating back to the Revolution that legislation must be accessible to the public.494
It is much more difficult to find administrative rules than it is to gain access to legislation. Part of the problem depends on the fact that there is no uniform approach to the nomenclature of administrative rules. Another part of the problem regards publication. On the eve of the adoption of the US apa, an American observer pointed out that not only were individuals no longer able to readily inform themselves about the numerous rules applicable to their conduct, but government officers too were ‘unable to find their
Among all these issues, our hypothetical case focuses on the question of publication. Suppose that during a pandemic, the Minister of Health defines the prices of various types of face masks in an order that also establishes
At first sight, in this case, the area of disagreement between the legal systems examined seems broader than in those examined earlier. It would appear, in particular, that there is a profound difference between the legal systems where publication is required as a condition for the validity of the rules, and the other legal systems, where publication is regarded as a mandatory requirement and the breach of which inevitably invalidates the act to which it relates, and, lastly, the systems in which it is considered a directory requirement, in the sense that its breach does not necessarily have this effect. Greece, France, and the UK exemplify these differing solutions. In Greece, the courts do not accord weight to the label of an act as a circular or guideline. If these acts impose duties on government officials or impinge on citizens’ lives, be it favorably or unfavorably, courts require publication as a condition for validity, like regulations.501 In France, after an attempt to eliminate circulars en masse, the general norm established by administrative procedure legislation502 is that government guidance, including circulars and instructions that interpret legislation or define administrative procedures, must be published. In the absence of publication, they are abrogated. But the Code also clarifies that unpublished circulars are not applicable, and public authorities are prevented from using them in their relationships with citizens. Accordingly, whether or not an unpublished rule is still valid, it cannot have legal effects. Lastly, in the UK the facts of the leading
It must be observed, however, that the area of disagreement is considerably narrowed if one takes into consideration the criteria defined by the courts. In this regard, it has been found that, according to the French administrative courts, the norm of the Code does not apply, for example, to a circular determining the standard of conduct for certain government officials. As a result, the fact that the circular was unpublished has not determined its abrogation. Moreover, and more importantly for our purposes here, it has been found that an unpublished rule cannot be applied adversely to individuals in the decisions directly and adversely affecting them.504 This comes close to the solution adopted in the UK, as well as in other common law systems, including the US, where a person may not be required to resort to, or be adversely affected by, an unpublished rule, unless that person has actual knowledge of it.505 This shows, in contrast with the first impression, that, in terms of the actual results reached in our factual analysis, the area of disagreement becomes less significant if one considers not only the ready applicable norms but also a host of other rules and doctrines decisive for their interpretation. Underlying this area of agreement is a common concern for legal certainty, which is not seen as a general ideal but a principle that prevents public authorities from applying unpublished rules.506
5 An Unexpected Area of Agreement
Turning from the specific findings to the broad over-all picture, two aspects should be considered: what could be expected and what has been found. As observed in Chapter 6, administrative procedure legislation is characterized by diversity in two ways: most, but not all, European legal systems have adopted one kind of administrative procedure legislation or another, and even among those legal systems that have one, only a few have defined general norms on rulemaking. One could, therefore, expect that the area of disagreement would be much larger than what has emerged with regard to administrative adjudication. In some instances, our findings confirm what a public lawyer with an adequate knowledge of other legal systems would have expected, for example, with regard to consultation.
However, other findings are at least partially unexpected.507 These refer, in particular, to the power to pre-determine the standards of administrative conduct. The supposed contrast between common law and civil law systems concerning the relationship between discretion and rules was found to produce fewer differences than expected. In lieu of the expected distinctions, there are interlaced areas of agreement and disagreement. To mention one further example, concerning the publication of rules, there is obvious divergence among the legal systems examined as to whether the absence of publication impinges either on the validity of rules or on their effectiveness. But all these legal systems adhere to the same norm that unpublished rules may not be applied against individuals and legal entities. Underlying this norm is the principle of legal certainty. The area of agreement is, therefore, qualitatively at least as significant as the area of disagreement. This reveals an improvement for society as a whole. ‘Citizens are better off’ if they can have adequate knowledge of the rules that, directly or indirectly (that is, through individual administrative decisions applying those rules), impinge on their interests, and can thus more easily verify whether they receive equal treatment.508
See RF Fuchs, ‘Procedure in Administrative Rule-Making’ (1938) 52 Harvard L Rev 259 (for the characterization of rule-making as a function, as distinct from a mere activity); S Croley, ‘Making Rules: An Introduction’ (1995) 93 Michigan L Rev 1511, at 1512 (same thesis).
Fuchs (n 455) 259.
See KC Davis, Discretionary Justice. A Preliminary Inquiry (Greenwood Press 1969) 46 (criticizing, among others, the views of judge Henry Friendly); R Baldwin, Rules and Government (Oxford University Press, 1995) (focusing on the legitimacy of governmental processes); A von Bogdandy, Gubernative Rechtsetzung. Eine Neubestimmung der Rechtsetzung und des Regierungssystems unter dem Grundgesetz in der Perspektive gemeineuropäischer Dogmatik (Mohr 2000) (comparing the main European legal systems).
E Forsthoff, Rechtsstaat im Wandel: verfassungsrechtliche Abhandlungen, 1950–1964 (Kohlhammer 1964).
US Court of Appeals, District of Columbia, Appalachian Power Company v epa (2000), § ii. See also, for a comparison between the US and France, S Rose-Ackerman and T Perroud, ‘Policymaking and Public Law in France: Public Participation, Agency Independence, and Impact Assessment’ (2013) 19 Columbia J Eur L 225, at 227 (for the remark that rules ‘cannot be the sole responsibility of the legislature’).
For further discussion, see Chapter 11, § 5.
See DL Shapiro, ‘The Choice of Rulemaking or Adjudication in the Development of Administrative Policy’ (1965) 78 Harvard L Rev 921 (criticizing the agencies’ reluctance to use rulemaking procedures) and A Scalia, ‘Back to Basics: Making Law Without Rules’ [1981] Regulation 25 (calling for attention on procedural burdens imposed on rule-making).
See see Craig, Administrative Law (n 23) 398 (on the ‘tremendous variety’ of administrative rules); P Cane, Controlling Administrative Power. An Historical Comparison (Cambridge up 2016) 269.
See SA De Smith, ‘Sub-Delegation and Circulars’ (1949) 12 Modern L Rev 37, at 43 (for the remark that ‘many circulars do affect the rights of the public’).
For further discussion, see § 3.
Whether rules may also reduce litigation is still another question.
See S Rose-Ackerman and T Perroud (n 459) 306.
Aarhus Convention on Access to Information, Public Participation in Environmental Decision-making and Access to Justice in Environmental Matters, adopted in 1998 and entered into force in 2001. On the Convention’s status, see the ruling of the cjeu in Case C-240/09, Lesoochranárske zoskupenie vlk v Ministerstvo životného prostredia Slovenskej republiky (holding that, though the Convention has no direct effect in domestic law, national courts must interpret rules concerning administrative and judicial proceedings in accordance with the Convention’s objectives, as set out by Article 9).
British Oxygen Co Ltd v Board of Trade [1971] ac 610. This precedent has been cited, among others, by R. (Sandiford) v Foreign and Commonwealth Secretary [2013] ewca Civ 581, § 59.
Wade, Administrative Law (n 442) 60.
MS Giannini, ‘Prefazione’ in W Wade, Diritto amministrativo inglese (Giuffrè 1965) xv-xvi.
This doctrine emerged in the 1930s in the case law of Italian administrative courts. As regards Germany, for a recent reappraisal, see the judgment of the Bundesverwaltungsgericht (Federal Administrative Court) of 17 January 1996, 11 C.95, Neue Juristisches Wochenschrift, 1996, 1766.
See C Perelman, Logique juridique (Dalloz 1976) 147 (discussing also the other maxim venire contra factum proprium).
Davis, Discretionary Justice (n 457) 31 (referring, in particular, to Duguit).
id, 219.
See Lord Hewart, The New Despotism (Benn 1929).
Giannini (n 470) xvi.
Bushell v Secretary of State for the Environment (1981). For further remarks, see Jowell (n 217) (delineating the contours of the “principle … of consistency”).
P Daly, Understanding Administrative Law (Oxford University Press 2021) 57 (emphasis in the original).
On this distinction, see L Di Qual, La compétence liée (lgdj 1964) 368.
See, for example, in the UK, the ruling of the House of Lords in R. v Secretary of State for Health, ex parte US Tobacco International Inc (1992), in which a ban on tobacco was held invalid because during the procedure the company was not told the scientific grounds on which the ban was based.
Article 12 of the Italian apa requires public authorities to predetermine the ‘criteria and ways’ in which they will act.
For example, the French Conseil d’Etat held that certain acts of general applicability, such as circulars and guidelines, may not be contested judicially if they have no binding effects: judgment of 12 June 2020, No 418142, gisti.
This is the case with the UK, which however is not isolated: see the answer provided in the Belgian report in the case discussed in the next section: Renders (n 454) 273.
See T Ziamou, ‘Public Participation in Administrative Rulemaking: the Legal Tradition and Perspective in the American and European (English, German, Greek) Legal Systems’ (2000) 71 Heidelberg J Int L 42 (2000).
O Mir Puigpelat, ‘Spain’ della Cananea and Andenas (n 436) 283.
Nason (n 448) 285.
Weidemann (n 453) 277.
V Neubauer, ‘Austria’ della Cananea and Andenas (n 436) 272.
See again Nason (n 448) 285, noting the similarity of the fact of our hypothetical case with R(wx) v Northamptonshire County Council [2018] ewhc 2178 (Admin).
A Andrijauskaite, ‘Lithuania’ della Cananea and Andenas (n 436) 280.
DU Galetta and P Provenzano, ‘Italy’ della Cananea and Andenas (n 436) 279.
Renders (n 454) 273–274.
D Costa, ‘France’, in della Cananea and Andenas (n 436) 276.
This is amply illustrated in a report by the Conseil d’Etat, Publication et entée en viguer des lois et de certains acts administratifs (La documentation française 2001) 15. In other legal systems, such as Spain, the retroactivity of administrative acts is explicitly prohibited by administrative procedure legislation: S Muñoz Machado, Tratado de derecho administrative y derecho pùblico general (2nd edn, boe 2019) 93.
AK Kuhn, ‘The Administrative Procedure Act and the State Department’ (1946) 40 Am J Int L 784. See also LA Jaffe, ‘Publication of Administrative Rules and Orders’ (1936) 24 Am Bar Ass. J. 393, at 394 (same remark) and, for the UK, De Smith, ‘Sub-Delegation and Circulars’ (n 463) 42 (observing that ‘it is unsatisfactory that the public may be without means of access’ to rules).
A Buttgenbach, Manuel de droit administratif (3rd edn, Larcier 1966) 23.
See DJ Lanham, ‘Delegated Legislation and Publication’ (1974) 37 Modern L Rev 510.
PL Strauss, ‘The Rulemaking Continuum’ (1992) 41 Duke L J 1463, at 1464.
See Davis, Discretionary Justice (n 457) 79 (for whom regulations should be published and readily available).
See L Fuller, The Morality of Law (Yale University Press 1969) 51.
Ziamou (n 484) 49.
Article L 312–2 of the Code adopted in 2016.
House of Lords, Regina v Sheer Metalcraft Ltd (1954). For further comments, see Lanham (n 497) 512 (suggesting that there is a presumption that Parliament does not intend its delegates to make rules which come into force before they are published).
Conseil d’Etat, decision of 19 December 2016, Application No 405471, association La Cimade. See also the decision of 7 July 2019, Application No 427638, Ligue des droits de l’Homme et Conféderation Générale du travail, concerning the interpretation of the provision of the Code.
US apa, § 552. For further remarks, see Strauss (n 498) 804.
See Muñoz Machado (n 494) 93; Lanham (n 497) 516.
See F Moderne, ‘Préface’ in A Brewer-Carias, Les principes de la procedure administrative non contentieuse (Economica 1992) 2.
Strauss (n 498) 808.