This chapter discusses the causes of commonality. The discussion addresses the roles played by various factors. As in the previous chapter, the discussion begins with a cautionary note, which concerns the legal relevance and significance of what is commonly regarded as the legacy of ‘European common law’. The discussion continues with a distinction between two types of causes of commonality. Some concern the spontaneous developments of national legal systems, either in adhesion to the ‘nature of the things’ or following a foreign model. Others are induced by European integration, including the definition of general principles, legal harmonization, and institutional isomorphism.
1 The Legacy of ius commune: A Qualified View
As observed earlier,613 previous studies concerning the common core took history into account. At the beginning of his innovative research, Schlesinger affirmed that his hypothesis – that is, between legal systems there were not only differences but also ‘shared and connecting elements’ that could be formulated ‘in normative terms’ – gained plausibility from historical studies.614 There were two sides to the same coin. During the seven centuries that elapsed between the emergence of the first scholarly works and the codification of private law in most civil law countries, there had been various waves of migration and the reception of legal ideas and institutions. Accordingly, legal comparison had been characterized by what Schlesinger called an ‘integrative’ approach; that is, one ‘placing the main accents on similarities’, as opposed to the following period characterized by contractive comparison, during which the emphasis was on differences.
Subsequently, as European integration has advanced, a distinction has emerged between two possible uses of historical studies. The first is to look at history as confirming the plausibility of the working hypothesis. So long as there has been a long period in which the differentiation of numerous legal orders coexisted with the existence of some shared legal formants, in particular
Firstly, and obviously, there are some analogies between the current time and the long period of ius commune, especially from the viewpoint of the relationships between legal orders, which affected not only continental Europe, but England too.615 The phrase ‘European common law’ has an appeal for many lawyers. However, historians of law have repeatedly and convincingly pointed out the institutional diversity between the two historical periods. Three distinctive traits, in particular, have been highlighted: the existence of the States, with their panoply of legal sources,616 the incomparably greater role of legislation, and their persistent monopoly on the legitimate use of force, though what is ‘legitimate’ now also reflects common principles. Our factual analysis has confirmed this, with regard to police powers, which belongs only to national authorities, though they must exercise such powers in conformity with the obligations stemming from membership of regional organizations.617
Secondly, a specification is needed with regard to a recurring theme: whether and to what extent national legal systems share a common basis or substratum in Roman law. The language in which this opinion is expressed differs. Some writers have spoken of the direct influence of Roman law on modern public law. Others have held that Roman law has been no more than a source of inspiration for administrative law. Both opinions will be briefly addressed here.
Lawyers who have evinced an interest in Roman law have not been motivated by purely historical interest. They have sought to draw upon this great tradition to determine the direction which modern public law should pursue. The objective has been both descriptive and prescriptive. In descriptive terms, many have observed that Roman law provides a vast arsenal of both legal concepts, such as imperium and right, as well as the distinction between public law and private law. In prescriptive terms, it has been argued that Roman law developed a concept of respect for the human person, which is preferable to others. Interestingly, different writers such as American historian of law
Hauriou reached a different conclusion. He acknowledged the importance of the Roman conception of public power, which could not simply be based on force but also had to be legitimate.622 However, he argued that Roman political authorities developed a vast administrative regime without being subject to justice themselves. It was only with the development of modern public law that the executive had become subject to justice. This was, for Hauriou, the most salient manifestation of the ‘soumission de l’Etat au droit’, a concept akin to the rule of law.623 Writing in the same years, Cammeo, an Italian administrative lawyer, acknowledged the importance of Roman law in laying the foundations of ‘juridical thought’ but circumscribed it because ‘many influences besides that of Roman law’ had acted during the previous centuries.624 On the one hand, the growth of administrative law has owed so much to recent technological developments, such as the postal service and railways, that it could hardly have any connection with Roman law. On the other hand, he argued that the connection of Roman law with those of several countries had been ‘broken at many points by the French Revolution’. On a more overtly prescriptive tone, he
In a society that is often sharply divided between different visions of the good, and in a legal landscape characterized by a growing variety of individual and collective interests, national laws have recourse to administrative procedure in order to reach decisions and define rules that are both sound and acceptable. The fact that this is increasingly regarded as an instrument of modern government within European laws and that it is subject to principles that are largely similar, if not the same, can hardly be explained by emphasizing the legacy of the past. In fact, it largely depends on other causes, including the individual choices made by national policymakers and the consequences that follow from membership of regional legal orders.
2 The ‘Nature of Things’
In the previous chapters, the ‘nature of things’ has been mentioned more than once. The thematic structure of the argument based on this must now be explained. Two interconnected claims can be delineated. The primary theme is consonant with an old and prestigious school of thought that goes back to the science of legislation, associated with thinkers such as Montesquieu and Smith. The secondary theme is that, with the growth of government caused, among other things, by technological progress, the laws and institutions of modern societies are increasingly similar. Both will be addressed in this section.
As observed earlier, Montesquieu’s approach was innovative because it deviated not only from blind respect for tradition but also from the ancient school of natural law. The fundamental criterion he set out for his enterprise was that
This kind of reasoning became controversial in the following century when the majoritarian view was that the laws reflected, or had to reflect, the spirit of each society. However, it was not abandoned. Writing at the end of the century, Laferrière identified the main issue of administrative law in terms of an appropriate balance between two necessities: achieving the goals set by legislation, and the protection of individual rights. For him, it was axiomatic that the best way to balance such interests was to place jurisdiction over disputes between individuals and the State in the hands of an institution that possessed the technical expertise and experience necessary to ascertain whether discretion had been fairly and appropriately used. Thus, for example, he thought that the creation of an administrative court within the Italian Council of State in 1890 confirmed that, at some stage, public law disputes require a specialized review body.632
During the first half of the last century, this way of thinking about public law has become increasingly widespread. With the greater involvement of the State in society and in the economy, and the expansion of its capacity to impinge upon the interests of both individuals and social groups (or to
A further stimulus for the development of functionalist thinking about public administration and administrative law came from European integration. The impact of both EU law and that of the Council of Europe will be discussed at a later stage in this chapter; meanwhile, it can be observed that the gradual transfer of functions and powers from national to common institutions stimulated new thinking about how the various legal systems dealt with the problems that emerged. From the observation that all the six founding States had administrative bodies that exercised authoritative powers under the control of the courts, one could reasonably conclude that administrative powers and judicial remedies were the ‘natural’ features of modern government. Thus, the Schuman Plan envisaged that both had to be reproduced at Community level.635
There are, however, some difficulties with this way of thinking about the fundamental unity of public law. They can be briefly summarized as follows. There is a risk of assuming that the process of refinement of legal institutions can be regarded as necessarily leading in one direction, while history is replete with differences and failures.636 There is a risk of taking for granted that certain principles can be regarded as optimal for every legal system, regardless of history and institutional context. For example, the gist of Laferrière’s argument – ie, that judicial specialization has several advantages – is confirmed
3 Legal Transplants: Authority, Prestige, and Quality
This theme will be addressed in two ways, one of which is general because it concerns legal transplants, while the other focuses on the borrowings and exchanges examined in the previous parts of this essay.
Rivero can be said to have been a forerunner. After noting in previous studies that public law had been replete with exchanges across national boundaries during the nineteenth century,637 in the early 1970s he examined these phenomena more systematically in the field of administrative and constitutional law.638 He observed that a State, especially in a period of rapid political or social transformation, essentially has two options. The first is to create its legal structures and processes from nothing. The second is to copy, and if necessary to adjust, those of another State. He argued that the latter option was empirically prevalent. He brought this argument to a further point by asserting that the entire history of constitutions, apart from a few prototypes, was studded with borrowings and transpositions.639 He made more than a mere hint at the metaphor of the transplant, drawn from surgery. Both the phenomena and the terminology (prototypes and transplants) were thus well identified, though not all subsequent academic works have shown adequate knowledge
Few years later, Watson published his seminal work on legal transplants, reaching the same conclusion from the viewpoint of private law.640 He argued that if we pay attention to the development of law over a long period of time and in several societies, it becomes evident that ‘the transplanting of individual rules or of a large part of a legal system is extremely common’,641 the reception of Roman law in Germany and the spread of civil codes based on the Code civil des Français being only some of the most notable examples. Turning from description to explanation, he argued that ‘transplanting is in fact the most fertile source of development’ of legal systems.642 There is more than one reason why this is so. Transplants provide reformers with solutions that have the advantage of being ‘socially easy’.643 This is the case, in particular, when the receiving society is less advanced than the exporting one.644 It is also the case when two societies are equally developed, but in one of them, many are dissatisfied with the ambiguities and gaps that beset the legal system, and reformers can point out that a certain legal mechanism has the further advantage of having been successfully tested elsewhere. From these two reflections, it follows that legal transplants rest on a variety of rationales, including authority (in the transplants that are said to have a divine origin),645 prestige, and intrinsic quality.646
Legal transplants can be better understood thanks to these studies. They can be either voluntary or coerced. Both private and constitutional law provide examples of the use of external coercion, such as the imposition of the French Civil Code on Italy after 1805647 and the US imposition of the Japanese
When the Napoleonic adventure was at an end … among all the peoples hopes were flaming up and demands were being made for independence and liberty … In Germany, in Italy, in Poland, in Belgium … and among other peoples, there were longings for many things: for juridical guarantees; for participation in administration and government, by means of new or revised representative systems. Since the historical antecedents and existing conditions, the spirits and customs of the various nations were diverse, these demands differed in the several countries in question, as to order of appearance, as to magnitude, as to details and as to their general tone.656
French writers have not disdained the view that emphasizes the prestige of their institutions.657 However, they have shown awareness of the fact that it is precisely the success of the French model of administrative justice that, among other things, has long prevented any serious step in the direction of adopting administrative procedure legislation. In other words, there has been an all too evident bias in favor of the judicial process rather than the regulation of administrative procedure.658 This partly explains why the leadership in innovation was taken by Austria and Spain. These cases
4 General Principles
Parallel developments and legal transplants are driving forces that affect commonality and diversity among national legal systems without any stimulus from regional organizations. However, they are affected by the principles defined by such organizations. These principles are important in themselves because they characterize the legal landscape, especially after 1945. Moreover, only in very limited areas (for example, public procurement, the recognition of professional qualifications, and procedural requirements for the protection of the environment) does the harmonization of laws replace national law and become the new legal framework, usually based on a comparative study of the systems to be harmonized and the choice of a standard. In the great majority of cases, national laws will remain unmodified, but will be subject to common general principles.
Our focus on general principles of law deserves further discussion. While less recent doctrines either ruled out that general principles could
Historically, as indicated earlier, the most important principles materialized in national judicial decisions. In some cases, principles had a meagre legislative basis. In other cases, they filled gaps existing in legislation, the emblematic case being the development of the general principles by the French Conseil d’État. In still other cases, judges applied general principles as inherent elements of their legal systems. Thus, for example, the individual’s right to be heard before an administrative authority takes a decision adversely affecting his interest has been regarded by both the Austrian and Italian administrative courts as a requirement imposed by the nature of things. It is precisely this judicial work that explains why most general principles are unwritten constructs, gradually institutionalized as case law, even though subsequently they have been referred to either by constitutions or by legislation. It is no exaggeration to say that much European public law has been constituted by the construction of general principles.
Taken as a whole, these general principles show what Rivero called parallel development. When judges identify and apply a new general principle to resolve a dispute, the law they make, it is asserted, already exists as a matter of law, to the extent that other judges in neighboring legal systems have developed the same principle in ways that have made it both normal and legitimate for use by all judges. Thus, for example, an Italian administrative court has held that the necessity to annul or withdraw unlawful acts or measures taken by public authorities must be regarded in the light of the settled jurisprudence of German administrative courts.660 Not surprisingly, those who worry about the destabilizing effects of judicial lawmaking, and who believe that judges can
The existence of general principles shared by a plurality of legal orders is not only significant from a factual perspective. It also entails normative consequences. In this respect, a distinction must be made between two ways in which general principles are individuated. First, legal assimilation is enhanced by the standards defined by the Council of Europe. Although it has no legislative authority, the recommendations adopted by its Committee of Ministers draw inspiration from the laws of the member States and are often regarded as indicative of best practices. Among these recommendations, three should at least be mentioned. The first is the recommendation of 1980 concerning the exercise of discretionary powers by administrative authorities, which, among other things, requires them to respect the right to be heard in adjudicative procedures.661 The second is the Recommendation of 1987 regarding administrative procedures affecting a large number of persons, which defines principles which all member States are required to respect, including the participation of persons claiming to have either an individual or collective interest that is potentially affected by administrative action.662 A more recent recommendation on good administration includes the principles according to which public authorities must act within a reasonable time limit and must provide individuals with an appropriate opportunity to participate in the procedures affecting them.663 These standards of good administrative conduct promote the respect of procedural values in the interpretation and application of the principles that legislators developed prior to the echr, or subsequently. They can be, and increasingly are, considered by the courts, which read legislation as far as possible to be compliant with them.664
Secondly, when the courts regard a certain norm as a general principle of law, important consequences stem from it. On the one hand, general principles express values essential to modern legal orders. In this respect, they are relevant from an axiological perspective. It is in this sense that Rivero, among others, argued that the founders of the ec shared a set of fundamental values, which provided the repository of principles against which legal control of
General principles bind national authorities when they act within the scope of the treaties, regardless of whether such principles exist within the domestic legal order. This is a consequence of the existence of a duty for all the organs of each State to obey the law. It follows that they must apply precepts of, for example, legal certainty, protection of legitimate expectations, and due process. National courts and other institutions, including those with advisory functions and higher audit institutions, ensure this duty is respected. The other consequence is that legal assimilation is greater than before regional legal orders were established.
5 Legal Harmonization
While general principles, defined either judicially or in recommendations, have a broad scope of application, legal harmonization is a product of EU law in particular areas. It differs from unification of the law, as it serves to coordinate national laws in order to remove obstacles to the Common Market.668 It is the product of a twofold political choice. There is, first, the choice agreed by the drafters of the treaties to entrust common institutions with the power to adopt norms aiming at harmonizing national legal systems. Then, there is
The aim of integration was obviously of far wider scope than harmonization,669 but the latter, too, had a broad scope of application, as it concerned the Common Market. It was precisely for this reason that different strategies were available to obtain economic integration. In abstract terms, more than one option was available. One option was to keep national regulatory autonomy, but to exercise it in respect of the principle of non-discrimination. As a result, producers would have had to adapt their goods to the requirements set by each State. Another option was the multilateral enactment of identically structured and worded statutes by the member States. There was still another option: the adoption of a regulation or directive by the institutions of the ec, with the purpose of overcoming national diversity. A choice had, therefore, to be made.
The drafters of the Treaty made their choice, identifying both a problem and the solution. The problem was the existence of ‘such legislative and administrative provisions of the Member States as have a direct incidence on the establishment or functioning of the Common Market’.670 The problem was not, therefore, national diversity in itself, but its negative impact on the Common Market. Harmonization was the solution, with a slight differentiation between the title of the third chapter of Title i of the Treaty and the text of Article 100. The rubric of Chapter 3, in the French text, referred to the ‘rapprochement des législations’ (similarly, the Italian text used the phrase ‘ravvicinamento delle legislazioni’ and the German one the phrase ‘Angleichung der Rechtsvorschriften’): the approximation of laws. The text of Article 100, however, had a wider reach, because it included both legislative and administrative provisions. Article 100 expressly equated legislative and administrative
The implementation of this norm has, however, proved to be difficult. Before 1978, some harmonizing directives were adopted, but they entailed significant negotiation costs, as it implied the transfer of sovereignty from the national to the supranational level and met the opposition by special national interest groups.671 The difficulties that emerged in reaching political agreements within the Council of ministers explain why the Commission readily endorsed the alternative solution envisaged by the ecj in its Cassis de Dijon ruling; that is, mutual recognition of national legal rules.672 Many commentators have agreed that the new strategy was preferable to the old ones, on the grounds that regulatory powers remained in the hands of national authorities, especially with regard to the marketization of goods. Others, however, have observed that there is another, horizontal, type of transfer of sovereignty, distinct from the vertical type associated with harmonization.673 Moreover, with regard to services, the EU has adopted several directives. Some of them, eg, the directives that liberalize the telecommunications, electricity, and gas markets, define the general principles which national regulatory authorities must apply. Included among these principles are those of non-discrimination, transparency and public consultation.674 Since the early 1970s, other directives, especially those concerning public procurements, lay down the general principles of open competition and transparency. Throughout the years, these directives have also included increasingly detailed provisions requiring contracting authorities to respect certain publicity requirements, as well as to abide by certain procedures in the choice of private contractors.675 The shared legal framework has thus become increasingly similar to a sort of code, thus reducing room for national regulatory autonomy.676
It can thus be noted by way of conclusion that the relationship between national laws and the law of the two regional organizations has a twofold dimension. On the one hand, Rivero’s remark that the most frequent way to shape new institutions is to borrow from others is confirmed, in the sense that both European courts have drawn inspiration from national administrative laws. On the other hand, the last seven decades have ‘had the effect of bringing the public law systems of the differing European countries closer together’ and has increased the awareness of the mutual dependence of its various component parts.679 It is for this reason that a further aspect deserves adequate attention, namely, the adjustment of those components to the perceived necessities, which will be examined in the next section.
6 Institutional Isomorphism
There is still another factor of commonality which bears some analogies with others; that is, institutional isomorphism. As a first step, we clarify the meaning of this expression. Some of its manifestations in the field of administrative law will then be considered.
The term ‘isomorphism’ is used both in mathematics and in social sciences. In mathematics it designates two or more structures of the same type and having the same properties (isomorphism is, in effect, derived from the Greek concepts of equal form or shape). As a consequence, they cannot be distinguished from the viewpoint of the structure alone, while there may be additional elements. The social sciences have built on the concept of isomorphism, especially in the world of organizations, in order to seek to explain
This theory can provide a better understanding of some of the phenomena we identified earlier. It explains why certain changes are necessary to honor legal commitments, such as the due process of law, for instance. Institutional isomorphism also explains the adoption of general legislation on administrative procedure by new entrants to the EU. Whereas in the founding States and
7 The Growing Impact of Common Standards
At the end of the preceding chapter, it was observed that a comparative approach that emphasizes only commonality would be, prescriptively, particularly weak in the European context and that an approach emphasizing only diversity would be equally weak. Two arguments support the latter remark.
First, there are not only standards of administrative conduct that are shared by all national legal systems, or by most of them. There are also the standards established by supranational laws. For example, national authorities are required to respect the Charter of Fundamental Rights, of the same legal value as EU treaties. Among the protected rights is the right to good administration, which is recognized and protected by Article 41. This states that ‘every person has the right to have his or her affairs handled impartially, fairly and within a reasonable time’, and goes on to specify that this right includes the right to be heard, access to files, and the duty to give reasons. Even if this is considered a closed list, it can nevertheless be argued that the meaning, for instance, of the right to be heard should be considered in the light of the standards shared by European legal orders, including the right to prior notification and legal assistance. If, on the other hand, the right to good administration is regarded as an open repository of shared standards, it can be interpreted against the background of these standards, thus ensuring procedural safeguards against arbitrariness, unfairness, and favoritism, as well as providing the opportunity for judicial review.
Above, Chapter 10, § 1.
Schlesinger, ‘The Common Core of Legal Systems: An Emerging Object of Comparative Study’ (n 548) 65.
Gorla and Moccia (n 595) 144. See also HE Yntema, ‘Roman Law and its Influence on Western Civilization’ (1949) 835 Cornell L Rev 77 (for the remark that even in the area of Anglo-American common law ‘the Roman conceptions had had pervasive … influence’).
AM Hespanha, Cultura juridical européia: sintese de un Milénio (Almedina 2012).
Above, Chapter 8, § 5.
CH McIlwain, ‘Our Heritage from the Law of Rome’ (1941) 19 Foreign Affairs 605.
id, 597.
C Schmitt, Die Lage der europäischen Rechtswissenschaft (1950), English transl ‘The Plight of European Jurisprudence’ (1990) 83 Télos 35. For a retrospective, see C Tomuschat, ‘Carl Schmitt’s Diagnosis of the Situation of European Jurisprudence Reconsidered. Autonomy of Basic Elements of the Legal Order?’ (2020) 80 Heidelberg J Int L 709.
See also F Wieacker, ‘Foundations of European Legal Culture’ (1990) 1 ajcl 1 (same remark).
M Hauriou, Principes de droit public (Dalloz 1910; 2010) 331.
id, 333. See, however, N Cornu-Thénard, ‘Le modèle romain du “corps du droit administrative” dans la pensée de Maurice Hauriou’ (2015) 41, 209, at 222 (arguing that drew on Roman law to build his theory of administrative decisions’ executory nature).
F Cammeo, ‘The Present Value of Comparative Jurisprudence’ (1918) 4 Am Bar Ass J 645, at 649.
id, 650.
Garcia de Enterria, La formación del Derecho Público europeo tràs la Revolución Francesa (n 41) 58 and 80.
Tocqueville, De la démocratie en Amérique (n 13) 57 (pointing out that equality was the most striking feature of the US).
Montesquieu (n 16) 115.
For this distinction, see W Maihofer, ‘Droit naturel et nature des choses’ (1965) 51 Archives for Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy 233.
Montesquieu (n 16) 328. This shows that between Montesquieu and Smith there was a difference of emphasis on progress, but not the diversity asserted by Loughlin (n 23) 5.
See the last section of A Smith, The Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759), ed by EG West (Liberty Fund 1969) 535.
Laferrière (n 100) 15.
FH Lawson, ‘Review of C.H. Hamson, Executive Discretion and Judicial Control and B. Schwartz, French Administrative Law in the Common-Law World’ (1955) 7 Stanford L Rev 159. See also Schlesinger, ‘The Common Core of Legal Systems: An Emerging Object of Comparative Study’ (n 548) 65 (for the remark that decision-makers, though ‘widely separated by time or space, more often than not would respond in a similar way’).
Rivero, Cours de droit administratif comparé (n 71) 15 (noting the ‘similitude des problèmes administratifs modernes, largement commandée par des facteurs techniques identiques de pays à pays’).
See G Frankenberg, ‘Critical Comparisons: Re-thinking Comparative Law’ (1985) 26 Harv Int’l L J 411.
J Rivero, ‘Maurice Hauriou et le droit administratif’ (1968) in Pages de doctrine (lgdj 1980) 34.
J Rivero, ‘Les phénomenènes d’imitation des modèles étrangers en droit administratif’ (1972) in Pages de doctrine (lgdj 1980) 459.
id, 459.
Watson (n 19). There has been much discussion about Watson’s theory, with a distinction depending on whether the transferability of legal institutions and norms is either accepted albeit in a relative manner, or excluded in general terms: for the first position, see O Kahn-Freund, ‘On Uses and Misuses of Comparative Law’ (1974) 37 Modern L Rev 1 and E Stein, ‘Uses, Misuses – and Nonuses of Comparative Law’ (1977) 72 Northwestern Univ School of L 198; for the other, see P Legrand, ‘The Impossibility of Legal Transplants’ (1997) 4 Maastricht J Eur & Comp L 111.
Watson (n 19) 95.
id, 96.
id, 97.
id, 88.
id, 89 and 100.
id, 99.
See A Kocourek, ‘Factors in the Reception of Law’ (1935) 10 Tul L Rev 209 (distinguishing accord from conflict and assimilation from imposition).
For further analysis, see HS Quigley, ‘Revising the Japanese Constitution’ (1959) 38 Foreign Affairs 140 (for a critical assessment of the ‘foreign imposition not wholly suited to a people of very different legal and social tradition’, such as that of Japan). But see also J Williams, ‘Making the Japanese Constitution: a Further Look’ (1965) 59 Am Pol Sc Rev 665 (for whom more recent studies have brought additional information showing that the Japanese side supported innovations).
On the concept of diffusion, see Twining (n 257) 203; S Farran and C Rautenbach, ‘Introduction’ in S Farran, J Gallen, J Hendry and C Rautenbach (eds), The Diffusion of Law. The Movement of Laws and Norms Around the World (Routledge 2016) 2.
Laferrière (n 100) v.
id, ix. The citation was taken from Goodnow, ‘The Executive and the Courts’ (n 134) 557. See, however, F Melleray, ‘Les trois ages du droit administratif comparé o comment l’argument de droit comparé a changé de sens en droit administratif français’ in F Melleray (ed), L’argument de droit comparé en droit administratif français (Bruylant 2007) 17 (for the remark that Laferrière recognized the importance of context).
FJ Goodnow, ‘Review of Laferrière, Traité de la jurisdiction administrative et des recours contentieux’ (1896) 1 Pol Sc Quart 352.
HG Crossland, ‘Right of the Individual to Challenge Administrative Action before Administrative Courts in France and Germany’ (1975) 4 Int & Comp L Q 707, at 745.
E Garcia de Enterria, ‘Le contrôle de l’administration: techniques, étendue, effectivité des contrôles, contentieux administrative objectif et subjectif à la fine du xxe siècle: analyse historique et comparative’ (2000) 53 Rev admin 125, at 131.
A Salandra, La giustizia amministrativa nei governi liberi (con speciale riguardo al vigente diritto italiano) (Unione Tipografico-Editrice 1904) 146.
B Croce, Storia d’Europa nel secolo decimono (1932), English translation, History of Europe in the Nineteenth Century (Harcourt, Brace and Company 1965) 3–4.
R Alibert, ‘The French Conseil d’Etat’ (1940) 3 Modern L Rev 257, at 265; Galabert (n 136) 700.
JB Auby, ‘Introduction’ in Melleray (n 651) 9.
See Stein, Legal Evolution. The Story of an Idea (n 571) 199 (for the remark that, of the various factors indicated by Montesquieu, those of a political nature, such as the nature of government, seem to prevail over other factors).
Tribunale amministrativo regionale of Trento, decision No 305 of 2009.
Recommendation No R (80) of 11 March 1980.
Recommendation No R (87) 16 of 17 September 1987.
Recommendation No R (2007) 7 of 20 June 2007.
P Birkinshaw, European Public Law (Wolters Kluwer 2014) 289 (noting the influence of the Council of Europe on the substantive and procedural laws of its members); Stirn, (n 81), 45.
Rivero, ‘Vers un droit commun européen: nouvelles perspectives en droit administratif’ (n 81) 389.
ECtHR, Judgment of 20 October 2009, Lombardi Vallauri v Italy. For further remarks from a UK perspective, see P Craig, ‘The Human Rights Act, Article 6 and Procedural Rights’ (2003) 47 Public L 753.
For further discussion about the echr, see A Stone Sweet and C Ryan, A Cosmopolitan Legal Order (Oxford up) 155 (arguing that the Convention goes well ‘beyond rights minimalism’).
See E Stein, ‘Harmonization of European Company Laws’ (1972) 37 Law & Contemp Probl 318, at 324 (distinguishing harmonization from the unification pursued by the Nordic Council).
For further analysis, see G della Cananea, ‘Differentiated Integration in Europe After Brexit: A Legal Analysis’ in I Pernice and AM Guerra Martins (eds), Brexit and the Future of EU Politics. A Constitutional Law Perspective (Nomos 2019) 45 (distinguishing two visions of European integration, one aiming at achieving ‘ever closer union’ and the other favorable to a wider and looser union); A von Bogdandy, ‘European Law Beyond Ever Closer Union Repositioning the Concept, its Thrust and the ecj’s Comparative Methodology’ (2016) 22 European L J 519 (suggesting that a new idea, the European legal space, should be explored, rather than the ‘ever closer union’, which is characterized by the goal of further integration).
Article 100 (1) of the Treaty provided that: ‘The Council, acting by means of a unanimous vote on a proposal of the Commission, shall issue directives for the approximation of such legislative and administrative provisions of the Member States as have a direct incidence on the establishment or functioning of the Common Market’. For further analysis of the various national texts, see JG Polach, ‘Harmonization of Laws in Western Europe’ (1959) 8 ajcl 153.
W Feld, ‘Legal Dimensions of British Entry into the European Community’ (1972) 37 Law & Cont Probl 247, at 257 (referring to the directive aiming at creating an ec company law).
ecj, Case 120/78, Rewe-Zentral ag v Bundesmonopolverwaltung für Branntwein.
P Craig and G de Burça, EU Law: Text, Cases, and Materials (5th edn, oup 2011) 596.
See, for example, the EU directive n. 2002/21 on a shared regulatory framework for electronic communications networks and services, in particular Articles 6 and 12 (regulating consultation and transparency mechanisms and establishing that during consultation ‘all interested parties must be given an opportunity to express their views’).
ec Directive n. 2004/18 (Public Sector Directive) for the coordination of procedures for the award of public works contracts, public supply contracts and public service contracts.
S Arrowsmith, ‘The Past and Future Evolution of ec Procurement Law: from Framework to Common Code?’ (2006) 35 Public Contract L J 337; id, ‘The Purpose of the EU Procurement Directives: Ends, Means and the Implications for National Regulatory Space for Commercial and Horizontal Procurement Policies’ Cambridge Ybk European Legal Studies 14/2012, 1.
D Thompson, ‘Harmonization of Laws’ (1965) 3 J Common Market St 302, at 304.
Leyland and Anthony (n 27) 59.
Craig, Administrative Law (n 23) 324. Fromont (n 4) 3 (same remark).
I am grateful to Alec Stone Sweet for drawing my attention to this body of literature.
PJ Dimaggio and WW Powell, ‘The Iron Cage Revisited: Institutional Isomorphism and Collective Rationality in Organizational Field’ (1983) 28 Am Sociol Rev 147, at 148. See also JW Meyer and B Rowan, ‘Institutionalized Organizations: Formal Structure as Myth and Ceremony’ (1977) 83 Am J Sociol 340.
Dimaggio and Powell (n 681) 148–9.
id, 150.
For example, 1964 saw a meeting of Dutch and Italian administrative judges. Regular meetings are organized in the framework of aca-Europe, the association of councils of State and supreme administrative courts.
Thirty-four jurisdictions are represented within the network, as the judges of EU member States are joined by those of Albania, Montenegro, Serbia, and Turkey, which have observer status, while those of Norway, Switzerland and the United Kingdom are invited as guests.
ECtHR judgment of 7 June 2001, Kress v France (Application No 39594/98). For further analysis, see J Bell, ‘From ‘Government Commissioner’ to ‘Public Reporter’: A Transformation in French Administrative Court Procedure?’ (2010) 16 Eur Public L 533. See also Fromont (n 4) 4 (for other examples of national rules revised in order to ensure compliance with EU law).