In this chapter, I would like to point to Bernard Stiegler’s work and his post-phenomenological inquiry into technics qua pharmakon as an important supplement to the mimetic turn in posthuman studies.1 In his philosophy, the human is understood through the initial flaw of forgetfulness. Forgetfulness is also a condition of memory, as humans correct it by remembering. What is remembered is the lost “technics” (from the Greek techne, meaning skills and knowledge), which is inseparable from memory. “Technics” is used in the plural to refer to technique, technicity, and technology.2 One avenue to explore could be Stiegler’s discussion of disorientation as a competition or rivalry, but with a sense of admiration and imitation. Disorientation happens because knowledge automatically produced by technics not only precedes but also exceeds humans. This is confusing us, as we must always think of new technics for access to knowledge. Stiegler’s reflections on the disorientation of knowledge amount to a pharmacology of imitation. The pharmacology of imitation is especially important because it points to its double-edged nature: It orients as much as it also disorients. Forgetfulness is both disorientation by oblivion and orientation by remembering. In other words, disorientation, which leads to the loss of knowledge, is also the condition of the discovery of loss. From the very start, “the human is not what is given, but what must be produced […], re-produced and repro-duced.”3
Memory is pharmacological as it assumes both remembrance and oblivion, and this is the condition of the constitution of the human. Since memory produces the human unconsciously as a faulty subject, the conscious constitution is made by thought or noesis as Stiegler uses the term elsewhere. From this
It is crucial to remember that our history consists of translations and instead of falling prey to nostalgia, there is always a chance to become different by making sense of and producing new meanings out of the meaningless signs residing in memory. Now all memory is recorded and made available through multiple forms of data. In this way, thought is entering into the lives of subjects without their realizing it, because machines are used by people unconsciously producing meanings while depriving subjects of “sensibility via calculation.”7 This situation of unconscious imitation or biomimesis threatens to eliminate thought, but I argue that it also opens up the possibility of new thought through conscious emulation or noomimesis. Since my focus is on the notion of noomimesis, I will not focus on a detailed explanation of biomimesis, which
The demand for noomimesis emerges from the conflict between unconscious automatism and conscious autonomy retained through the awareness of knowledge and described by Vladimir Vernadsky as the noosphere.9 Influenced by Bergson’s philosophy10 and relying on his own distinguished knowledge of geology, especially his research in soil studies, Vernadsky defined the noosphere as the inevitable extension of the biosphere. This theory precedes current theories of the Anthropocene and extends the study of signs emerging in the biosphere to the noosphere and the semiosphere (the sphere of signs).11 It states that the stratification of the Earth and its subjects by previous intellectual systems automatically overcome the human, while at the same time opening up a new possibility for autonomy through knowledge of entropy. This autonomy through knowledge of entropy is developed by Stiegler as “negentropy” or “negative entropy” in order to demonstrate the potential of humans to overcome the critical situation of disorientation in a world dominated by technologies.12
This knowledge constitutes subjects as semi-autonomous semiurgs (sign-makers), enabling the production of new meanings to overcome the crisis. Due to the constant translations, signs previously produced by memory lose their meaning without losing their formal appearance. They are simply separated from their initial meaning and exteriorized as the memory of the past. The production of new signs out of meaningless signs that reside in the exteriorized memory is a driving force of noomimesis.13
1 Knowledge and Mimesis in the Age of the Anthropocene
The Anthropocene, often understood as an age of posthuman technological proliferation, is also an age of disorienting knowledge of how to live, work, and think due to the automation that technologies produce. This situation creates a panic in the face of technologies surpassing humans, while at the same time opening the way to the discovery of new ways of translation. I use “translation” in the sense that this English word derives from the Latin word translato: trans, “across” + ferre, “to carry” or “to bring” (latio, derived from latus, is the past participle of ferre). Thus, translato is “a carrying across” or “a bringing across,” which assumes translations occur in time and place. What Jacobson calls “rewording”—an interpretation of verbal signs by means of other signs in the same language—is in my work understood as a decomposition of meaningless signs into meaningful ones.14 These meaningless signs, as will be made clearer below, are technical objects preceding the emergence of meaning that give rise to newer technical objects.
The notion that technics precedes thought and the human is the product of technics, as theorized by Bernard Stiegler, is also the starting point of my argument for posthumanism being a condition of any existence. Following Stiegler, I use the term “technics” in the plural, which includes the triad of technique, technicality, and technology. Although technics also includes technology, they are not synonymous. Technics refers to the meaning of technology, while technology refers to domains of technical action, such as industry or cyberspace, to give but two examples. If technics precedes thought, which in its turn produces humanity, then becoming human is the result of the contingency of technics, of the chance encounter, and therefore becoming human means overcoming this contingency by translation. It is possible only by the understanding (bearing in mind that the “understanding” is also technique) of meaningless signs and assembling them according to understanding.
In his work, Stiegler makes two interrelated claims: that “technics” is the main question of all futures to come, and that “technics” is what philosophy has repressed or excluded throughout its history. Understanding technics therefore is primarily to gain an understanding of all futures to come and the question of “the return of the repressed.”15 Philosophy’s exclusion of technics is the denial of the human as the product of technics, whereas science more convincingly demonstrates that the human is the product of technics. For
The formation of humans through the process of exteriorization always already demands a “return” to this primal impulse, to this mimetic relationship, therefore there is always the demand for the new mimesis. The “always already” is not present as a memory, but effective as temporal potentiality, something to come or to be set forward. The new mimesis emerges from the possibility of memory as a default of forgetting. It should also be noted that the role of technics here is twofold. These technics preceding humans constitute subjects unconsciously, both logically and pathologically, as Nidesh Lawtoo explains following Nietzsche’s notion of “the phantom of the ego. ”18 It is also at the core of biomimesis, which means technics constitutes subjects pathologically, yet technics also constitutes humans noetically, like in Aristotle’s notion of the noetic soul.19 So, becoming human is on the one hand biological and on
In these circumstances, the task of philosophy is to think of a good imitation that overcomes the difficulties and challenges imposed by posthumanist theories. One of the difficulties is the ongoing struggle created by the so-called object-subject relationship, with the crucial question of memory. In order to overcome this challenge, which is cardinally changing our view of time and subjectivity, we also need to think of good imitation, which brings together images and thought, art and philosophy in the world of hyperchaos and contingency. Although the world exists independently from humans and technics precede humans, the question of “time after” persists.20 The time after is the point of the irreversible separation of the world from its image, yet it is also a reminder and a record of the memory of this separation, which contains traces of “the transient, the fleeting and the contingent.”21
The time after demands the imitation of technics, which are embedded in human memory. The time after is the point of irreversible separation of the world and its signs. These signs are storage spaces of the contingent, transient, and temporal. The time after is not a copy of the contingent or its signs, but a delicate image that forms the exterior space of the memory of separation that is recorded in these signs. This memory does not reside in the human, but is exteriorized and exists outside the human with the potential to produce meaning. The human is a fiction that produces its own fictional existence out of these meaningless signs by giving them a new meaning. Stiegler calls this exteriority “the third retention,” which I find very convincing and will refer to as the posthuman memory with the potential to create a model of post-artistic mimesis.
The third, or tertiary retention, means that memory is recorded by technologies and separated from the human; it exists as a reminder and at the same time as a potential assistance as a support for remembering. In Stiegler’s definition, tertiary retention (third memory) is the hidden condition of possibility, of the play between what Husserl called primary retention and secondary retention.22 Throughout his work, Stiegler (drawing on Husserl) speaks of retentions, whereby primary retentions are sense perceptions, secondary
Becoming human is the internalization of the exterior, with understanding playing a crucial role in this. It is worth adding here that signs exist only in technologies of memory, that is mnemo-technologies, and signs are memories of time. Any technique is the absence of the imitation and time after is imitation that reconstructs by translating the time that is absent in the technics. Although technics already contain memory, that memory does not necessarily correspond to time, whereas time comes into existence by remembering but also equally by forgetting. The time after is also the time of the retention, which either excludes or includes the missing dimension of time embodied in memory. It is what I call “time which is lost,” and this loss is the condition of the gain. Like the time before, the time after also exists independently as the carrier of the trace of contingency.
According to recent theories, time does not exist, and any contingency is explained by the persistence of “the ancestral” or before thought,23 but other theories, such as Derrida’s deconstruction followed by Stiegler, hold that there are traces of time.24 These traces are memory and history, and they are translational technics. Traces of time give rise to the recognition of the human subject that produces technics. The challenge created by most posthumanist theories is an attempt to dispose of the “subject” altogether in order to create a “perfect” world of objects.25 I think that when it comes to humanism or posthumanism, they are not products either of the subject or of the object as creation
Becoming human, from its inception, has been a matter of imitation and the human can make its own image by extending itself into something else, into another technique. The other word for imitation is the persistence of the abovementioned question of memory (imitation as remembering), where forgotten or lost time is embodied. To imitate is to remember, but it also entails oblivion. To speak of the “origin” of the human already means speaking of the imitation, which also means that the human born by such imitation is always already a fiction. Analogously, we can speak of “cyborgs” as imitations. Hence, there is a need to understand imitation as the pharmacological effect, which is a double-edged act of producing good and evil, or pathologies and patho-logies simultaneously.28 Stiegler’s theory of technics and time introduces humans merely as fiction and the product of technics.29 Humans are always in default and the fault, or imperfection, is at the same time the condition of “correcting” the fault. But because of the pharmacological nature of this act, there is the danger of becoming adapted by the imitation. Yet, at the same time, there is the possibility of adopting from the imitation to change one’s perspective.
Good imitation, in this sense, is understood as changing the perspective of the self by becoming the other through the assistance of technics. It should
It is worth mentioning here, albeit briefly, that becoming is also to be understood as “acting out,” which takes place during the encounter with the repressed in the realm of mnemo-technologies.32 Acting out may be understood as the gain of the loss and rediscovery of lost knowledge through understanding and having an intention for acting. This kind of mimesis as a re-contextualizing of the existing signs, for translating them into the subject’s personal repertoire is crucial to noomimesis. It is a term for knowing and mimicking as a matter of becoming a part of the collective consciousness through the use of signs. These signs provide technological conditions for translations. The technical condition precedes the realization of thought, such as the use of, for example, alphabetic writing: in order to write, one needs to first learn letters of the alphabet. Writing is the exteriorization of one’s thought by the use of meaningless signs, such as letters of the alphabet; taken separately they are just signs, but combined together they become words, sentences, and finally meanings.
We become human and invent the missing dimension of time with the assistance of technics. As is well known, techne as art was also the industrial model for ancient philosophy, which assumed the complicated nonlinear relationship with the primary model. This is also true for our highly technologized age of the Anthropocene. This nonlinear relationship concerns, first and foremost, the temporality of technics and aggregates produced/imitated by them. What is produced by technics are meaningless signs. These signs are the main context of technics: They precede humans by becoming but also overcome humans by changing the perspective; they are called “meaningless” because the human is
Trying to discover a model of connectivity immediately points to the loss, which resides in signs of this incomplete evidence. It gives rise to the possibility of assembling these signs in order to discover their meaning and to gain the lost dimension of time. This, in turn, gives rise to a temporal formation of subjects and this formation is not due to the human’s “original experience.” Instead, it is the ability to assemble inhuman, contingent meaningless signs.34 The human is not a cause of this event of assembling or its final goal: the human is the quasi-cause of this event rather than the negotiator of the original experience. Deleuze and later Stiegler paid attention to this aspect of experiencing.35 It is also in this sense that the human is a fiction, which depends upon the
All in all, noomimesis addresses these questions by combining two terms, noesis and mimesis, both of which are understood as techniques exemplified here as speaking, writing, and imaging. Although these technics have been designed in many respects to imitate our senses, they do not share the limits of our senses. It is our senses that are limited and in need of assistance. Technics extend human senses, yet they also expand the range of our senses in some way through exposure to a technical way of seeing, thinking, and imaging. Images are not imitative of natural perception, they imitate technics. Technics liberate perception from its natural settings and offer us means to exceed our habits and gain access to the flow of signs. As such, technics become a technology of new perceptive and political possibilities. These possibilities reside in “places of memory”37 such as archives, libraries, and what are now called databases—or what I call recorded memory. A recorded memory is what exteriorizes memory, like a written text or a recorded video. It is knowledge embedded within technology or knowledge understood as the pre-exteriorized characteristic of technology.
Knowledge is embedded in technologies as the collection of meaningless signs that give rise to (post)humans. They exist as an embodiment and form of hybridity between humans and other imitators, and between meaninglessness and meanings. It is possible to say that techno-logy (techne and logos) is knowledge, which consists of the economy of the loss and gain articulated by meaninglessness and meaningfulness. Meaning, made from meaningless
Noomimesis brings thought to existence; otherwise thought does not exist. Thought is brought into existence as a method of grasping knowledge of the “great outdoors,” as mimicking the exterior that resides in the meaningless sign.38 Signs of the “great outdoors” exist as signs of the remainder of the exterior that exists independently of our existence. These meaningless signs are inscribed in every recorded memory and memorized while existing by themselves, from fossils, as reminders of natural geological formations, to the emojis used in electronic communication as reminders of this communication.
These signs have no meaning in the sense that they exist independently of thought and only receive a specific meaning when thinking takes place in relation to them. In other words, although these signs are meaningless, they are given meaning by the “end user” in the time after. In this act, noomimesis leads to the artificial fabrication of the model of the world, which is not the world itself, but its imitated image. This imitated image stands against the meaningless sign of the “great outdoors” as the encounter of the interior with the exterior, while constantly reminding us about the condition of existence as a matter of temporality open to the influences from the outside. The meaningless sign becomes the condition of bringing forward and projecting to the exterior the internal possibilities—also called augmentation. This augmentation is
2 Noomimesis and Transhuman Translations
In the context of posthumanism, transhumanism is understood as the augmentation of humans by their own knowledge. It is the technique that extends the human by bringing forward their “technics”—constantly translating.39 It also means two things: first, the translation of sensibility into the technics of reproduction; and second, the augmentation or bringing forward of one’s intelligibility in the technics. This double-edged activity is alternated intermittently and introduces indeterminacy into an otherwise “deterministic” system and unexpectedly swerves away from its initial destination. It brings together noesis and mimesis on the one hand, and underlies their irreversible separation on the other. This separation is crucial as it is the condition of contextualization and translation. The question that I would like to accentuate is this translation’s automation: the automatic adaptation of the individual on the one hand, and the possible autonomy of changing one’s perspective by adapting on the other. In this process, translation plays the role of the orientation of the recorded memory, of the meaningless sign, which exists as anamnesis and the support for knowing.
The notion that post/transhumanism is the augmentation of humans by knowledge also implies that it may increase the awareness of humans about their own technics. It is both the condition of one’s own making and knowledge of one’s own invention. It is the possibility to act according to this knowledge and avoid the control that automation imposes. It can also allow translating one’s own knowledge into technologies. Since technologies are the results of the exteriorization by signs and this exteriorization is made by, for example, writing, it is also a memory of the lost time, the loss that takes place during automation. This loss is symbolized in images that are signs outside of the meaning. The world consists of these signs as technical objects and this consistency is also the insistence on the third retention or memory, which constitutes the exterior world.
The empty sign, qua true sign, uncovers for us the remarkable fact that meaning is contingent in the constitution of the sign that the sign has no need of meaning in order to be a sign—and that semiotics (the study of signs) intervenes before semantics (the theory of meaning), and independently of it; for it concerns a domain that is autonomous from the latter: the domain of the non-signifying sign.40
The sign (imitation) is meaningless and free of any decision-making (translation, which is also knowledge). Although I agree with Meillassoux that the sign can exist without meaning after it has been reproduced, I absolutely disagree that the sign comes into existence without meaning. It comes into existence as a meaning, but the sign irreversibly loses its meaning after coming into existence. Conversely, the sign that can exist without meaning can also exist with meaning. Even if to understand contingency as the event that is both something that may or may not occur, it is reasonable to say that knowledge is never made according to contingency; knowledge is the internalization of a hypothesis. This hypothesis is fuzzy and never determined; it is either predetermined or overdetermined and only temporarily terminated in a particular context, and shortly after this termination the meaning is lost again while being translated from one context into another. The inscription left behind is the image of translation and it is true to say that images are opening the indirect access to the outside world. Philosophy is questioning this indirect relation by undertaking and realizing what is undertaken. Realization takes place at the boundaries, where limits play a role rather than access or directness. Limits and transgression of limits amount to techno-genesis that also generates a new world by engineering and engendering.
November 2021–June 2022, London
For the full account of Stiegler’s work see Zeigam Azizov, The Time of the Image: A Philosophical Exploration of the Image in the Work of Bernard Stiegler (Cologne: Herbert von Halem Verlag, 2020).
Bernard Stiegler, Technics and Time, 1: The Fault of Epimetheus (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1998), 29.
Bernard Stiegler, Nanjing Lectures 2016–2019 (London: Open Humanities Press, 2020), 97.
Imaging is just one of the meanings of the term “mimesis.” For a more detailed analysis of the origins and different meanings of this complex term, see Gunter Gebauer and Christoph Wulf, Mimesis: Culture-Art-Society (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995), 27.
The semantics of the term “mimesis” already points to the contrast between unconscious and conscious imitation; the coining of the new term only underlines their connectivity and difference.
For genealogical continuity with my argument, see Nidesh Lawtoo, ed., “Posthuman Mimesis,” Special Issue, Journal of Posthumanism 2, no. 2 (2022).
N. Katherine Hayles, My Mother Was a Computer: Digital Subjects and Literary Texts (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005).
See also Nidesh Lawtoo and N. Katherine Hales, “Posthuman Mimesis ii—Connections: A Dialogue Between Nidesh Lawtoo and Katherine Hayles,” Journal of Posthumanism 2, no. 2 (2022): 181–89.
Vladimir Vernadsky, The Biosphere (Oracle, Ariz.: Synergetic Press, 1986).
Henry Bergson, Matter and Memory (Mineola, N.Y.: Dover Philosophical Classics, 2004).
Yuri M. Lotman, Universe of the Mind: A Semiotic Theory of Culture (London and New York: i. b. Tauris, 1990).
Bernard Stiegler, The Negantropocene (London: Open Humanities Press, 2018).
In Platonic philosophy, a demiurge is a being responsible for the creation of the universe, the maker or creator of the world. See Plato, Timaeus and Critas (London: Penguin, 1977), 29. Semiurge, (from the French sémiurgie), is a term coined in the 1970s in works about mass media and widely used by Jean Baudrillard for the critique of the production of new meanings by the creation of new signs, the expansion of the semiosphere. See Jean Baudrillard, Simulacra and Simulation (Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press, 2000), 121–29.
Roman Jakobson, “On Linguistic Aspects of Translation,” in On Translation, ed. by R. Brower (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1959), 232–39.
Sigmund Freud, Five Lectures on Psychoanalysis (London: Penguin, 2004), 87.
André Leroi-Gourhan. Gesture and Speech (Cambridge, Mass.: mit Press, 1993). Another example is the work of Jacques Monod on chance and necessity. See Jacques Monod, Chance and Necessity: An Essay on the Natural Philosophy of Modern Biology (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1971).
It is already by Aristotle and his notion of the hand as a tool of tools, it is a tool which makes tools, it is organon pro organon, organism and language. Aristotle, Categories (Scotts Valley, Calif.: Create Space Independent Publishing Platform, 2016). In the work of Gilbert Simondon, this question received its important transformation, where the hand is understood as a technique which makes technology; Simondon, Gilbert. On the Mode of Existence of Technical Objects. (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2017). Deleuze as well as Derrida, before Stiegler, had already referred to Simondon’s understanding of the hand and the face as technics. Giles Deleuze, The Logic of Sense (London, New York: Continuum, 2004); Jacques Derrida, Of Grammatology (Baltimore, Md.: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1998). Another curious thing is the invention of clothing, which leaves hands and face open, and gloves temporarily hide hands, so does the veil hide away the face, etc.
Nidesh Lawtoo, The Phantom of the Ego: Modernism and the Mimetic Unconscious (East Lansing: Michigan State University Press, 2013).
Aristotle, Categories.
Jacques Rancière, Bela Tarr: The Time After (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2013).
Charles Baudelaire, The Painter of Modern Life (London: Penguin Books, 2010), 17.
Edmund Husserl, The Phenomenology of Internal Time-Consciousness (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2019); Bernard Stiegler, Technics and Time, 2: Disorientation (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 2019).
Quentin Meillassoux, Time Without Becoming (London: Mimesis International, 2014).
Jacques Derrida, “Plato’s Pharmacy,” in A Derrida Reader: Between the Blinds, ed. by Peggy Kamuf (New York: Columbia University Press, 1991), 112–39; Stiegler, Technics and Time, 1, 135.
This is especially true of object-oriented ontology and speculative realism, but also for the metahumanist theories of Stefan Lorenz Sorgner, which seems to influence posthumanist theories without questioning the role of the subject. See, for example, Graham Harman, The Speculative Turn: Continental Materialism and Realism (London: re.Press, 2011). It should also be noted that for theories of new materialism, such as for Rosi Braidotti or Karen Barad the question of subjects is still a very important argument. It is partly because these subjects are excluded ones and their inclusion in history is a matter of the truth or the “intra-action.” Or, in Braidotti’s case, it is a question of “transposition.” Karen Barad, Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the Entanglement of Matter and Meaning (Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 2007); Rosi Braidotti, Transpositions: On Nomadic Ethics (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2006).
Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason (London and Basingstoke: Macmillan Press, 1976).
Jacques Rancière, The Distribution of the Sensible: Aesthetics and Politics (London: Continuum: 2006).
Nidesh Lawtoo and Bernard Stiegler both share an interest in a genealogy of the pharmakon. Lawtoo reflects on Nietzsche and Stiegler develops Derrida’s notion of pharmacy. See Lawtoo, Phantom of the Ego, 27. Bernard Stiegler wrote on this subject throughout his work and he also was the founder in 2010 of the philosophy school Ecole de Philosophie d’Epineuil-le-Fleuriel at Épineuil-le-Fleuriel in France (pharmakon.fr).
Stiegler, Technics and Time, 1, 135–79.
Plato, Great Dialogues of Plato (New York: Signet Classics, 2015), 131.
In passing, I would like to note that Jacob Burkhart also remarked that no explanation of culture ever fully accounts for its works of art because aesthetic activity lies in part outside culture. Influenced by this idea, George Kubler stated that “the idea of art can be expanded to embrace the whole range of man-made things”; George Kubler, The Shape of Time: Remarks on the History of Things (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1962), 2.
Bernard Stiegler, Acting Out (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 2008).
David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1978).
I borrow the notion of “the inhuman” from Lyotard. Jean-Francois Lyotard, The Inhuman: Reflections on Time (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991). I prefer the term “inhuman” to the term “nonhuman,” because the inhuman assumes a connection to the human whereas the nonhuman completely rejects this connection.
“Quasi-cause” is a term coined by Deleuze and later used by Stiegler. Deleuze uses this term elsewhere, yet, the most interesting example is in the life and work of the French poet Joe Bousquet, who was wounded on May 27, 1918, at Vailly near the Aisne battle lines at the end of the First World War. He spent the rest of his life paralyzed, mostly in bed surrounded by his books. His physical incapacity and constant pain caused a retreat from the world but also became the starting point for an extensive body of poetry and writing. As he said, “My wound existed before me, I was born to embody it.” Giles Deleuze, The Logic of Sense (London, New York: Continuum, 2004), 169. See also Bernard Stiegler and Daniel Ross, “The New Conflict of the Faculties and Functions: Quasi-Causality and Serendipity in the Anthropocene,” Qui Parle: Critical Humanities and Social Sciences 26, no. 1 (2017): 79–99.
Roy Bhaskar, Philosophy and the Idea of Freedom (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991).
Pierre Nora, Realms of Memory (New York: Columbia University Press, 1998).
The term “great outdoors” is borrowed from Meillassoux. See Quentin Meillassoux, After Finitude: An Essay on the Necessity of Contingency (London and New York: Continuum, 2008).
My own interest in transhumanism emerges from my reading of Stiegler as well as ai scientist Lotfi A. Zadeh’s work on “fuzzy logic” and McLuhan’s theory of technology as an “extension of man.” See Lotfi A. Zadeh, Fuzzy Sets, Fuzzy Logic, Fuzzy Systems (Singapore: World Scientific Press, 1996); Marshall McLuhan, Understanding Media: The Extensions of Man (Cambridge, Mass.: mit Press, 1994).
Quentin Meillassoux, “Iteration, Reiteration, Repetition: A Speculative Analysis of the Sign Devoid of Meaning,” in Genealogies of Speculation: Materialism and Subjectivity Since Structuralism, ed. Armen Avanessian, (Bloomsbury, 2016), 117–197.
Vernadsky, Biosphere, 481.
References
Aristotle. Categories. Scotts Valley, Calif.: Create Space Independent Publishing Platform, 2016.
Azizov, Zeigam. The Time of the Image: A Philosophical Exploration of the Image in the Work of Bernard Stiegler. Cologne: Herbert von Halem Verlag, 2020.
Barad, Karen. Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the Entanglement of Matter and Meaning. Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 2007.
Baudelaire, Charles. The Painter of Modern Life. London: Penguin Books, 2010.
Baudrillard, Jean. Simulacra and Simulation .Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press, 2000.
Bergson, Henry. Matter and Memory .Mineola, N.Y.: Dover Philosophical Classics, 2004.
Bhaskar, Roy. Philosophy and the Idea of Freedom. Oxford: Blackwell, 1991.
Braidotti, Rosi. Transpositions: On Nomadic Ethics .Cambridge :Polity Press, 2006.
Deleuze, Giles. Empiricism and Subjectivity: An Essay on Hume’s Theory of Human Nature .New York: Columbia University Press, 1991.
Deleuze, Giles. The Logic of Sense. London, New York: Continuum, 2004.
Derrida, Jacques, Of Grammatology. Baltimore, Md.: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1998.
Derrida, Jacques. “Plato’s Pharmacy.” In A Derrida Reader: Between the Blinds, ed. by Peggy Kamuf 112–39. New York: Columbia University Press, 1991.
Freud, Sigmund. Five Lectures on Psychoanalysis .London: Penguin, 2004
Gebauer, Gunter, and Christian Wulf. Mimesis: Culture-Art-Society .Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995.
Harman, Graham. The Speculative Turn: Continental Materialism and Realism. London: re.Press, 2011.
Hayles, N. Katherine. My Mother Was a Computer: Digital Subjects and Literary Texts. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005.
Hume, David. A Treatise of Human Nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1978.
Husserl, Edmund. The Phenomenology of Internal Time-Consciousness. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2019.
Jakobson, Roman. “On Linguistic Aspects of Translation.” In On Translation, ed. by R. Brower (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1959), 232–39.232–39. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1959.
Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Pure Reason. Translated by Norman Kemp Smith,. London and Basingstoke: Macmillan Press, 1976.
Kubler, George. The Shape of Time: Remarks on the History of Things .New Haven, Conn. :Yale University Press, 1962.
Lawtoo, Nidesh, ed. “Posthuman Mimesis.” Special Issue. Journal of Posthumanism 2, no. 2 2022.
Lawtoo, Nidesh. The Phantom of the Ego: Modernism and the Mimetic Unconscious. East Lansing: Michigan State University Press, 2013.
Lawtoo, Nidesh, and N. Katherine Hales. “Posthuman Mimesis ii—Connections: A Dialogue Between Nidesh Lawtoo and Katherine Hayles.” Journal of Posthumanism 2, no. 2 (2022): 181–89.
Leroi-Gourhan, André. Gesture and Speech .Cambridge, Mass.: mit Press, 1993.
Lotman, Yuri M. Universe of the Mind: A Semiotic Theory of Culture. London and New York: I. B. Tauris, 1990.
Lyotard, Jean-Francois. The Inhuman: Reflections on Time. Oxford: Blackwell, 1991.
McLuhan, Marshall. Understanding Media: The Extensions of Man. Cambridge, Mass.: mit Press, 1994.
Meillassoux, Quentin. After Finitude: An Essay on the Necessity of Contingency .London and New York: Continuum, 2008.
Meillassoux, Quentin. “Iteration, Reiteration, Repetition: A Speculative Analysis of the Sign Devoid of Meaning,” in Genealogies of Speculation: Materialism and Subjectivity Since Structuralism, ed. Armen Avanessian, (Bloomsbury, 2016), 117–197.
Meillassoux, Quentin. Time Without Becoming. London: Mimesis International, 2014.
Monod, Jacques. Chance and Necessity: An Essay on the Natural Philosophy of Modern Biology. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1971.
Nora, Pierre. Realms of Memory. New York: Columbia University Press, 1998.
Plato. Great Dialogues of Plato. New York: Signet Classics, 2015.
Plato. Timaeus and Critas. London: Penguin, 1977.
Rancière, Jacques. Bela Tarr: The Time After. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2013.
Rancière, Jacques. The Distribution of the Sensible: Aesthetics and Politics .London: Continuum: 2006.
Simondon, Gilbert. On the Mode of Existence of Technical Objects. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2017.
Stiegler, Bernard. Acting Out. Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 2008.
Steigler, Bernard. Nanjing Lectures 2016–2019. Translated by Daniel Ross. London: Open Humanities Press, 2020.
Stiegler, Bernard. Technics and Time, 1: The Fault of Epimetheus .Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1998.
Stiegler, Bernard. Technics and Time, 2: Disorientation .Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 2019.
Stiegler, Bernard. The Negantropocene. Translated by Daniel Ross. London: Open Humanities Press, 2018.
Stiegler, Bernard, and Daniel Ross. “The New Conflict of the Faculties and Functions: Quasi-Causality and Serendipity in the Anthropocene.” Qui Parle: Critical Humanities and Social Sciences 26, no. 1 (2017): 79–99.
Vernadsky, Vladimir. The Biosphere. Oracle, Ariz.: Synergetic Press, 1986.
Zadeh, Lutfi A. Fuzzy Sets, Fuzzy Logic, Fuzzy Systems .Singapore: World Scientific Press, 1996.