2003 article, originally published in Companion to the history of economic thought, edited by Warren Samuels, Jeff Biddle and John Davis, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 148–66.
(For its abstract see the Abstracts of all chapters, p. 1.)
Contents
Introduction
1 On Marx and his Capital
2 The many Marxes, the many Capitals
3 Interpretations of Marx’s method in Capital
3.1 Historical Materialism
3.2 Critique
3.3 Naturalistic versus socio-historical concepts
3.4 Value-form theory
3.5 Systematic Dialectics
3.6 Conclusions
4 A synopsis of the systematic structure of Capital
Capital I: Production
Capital II: Circulation
Capital III: Destination
Summary
5 Marx’s theory and Marxian theory as a strand
References
Introduction1
Karl Marx is known for a 30-page political pamphlet, The Communist Manifesto, written in 1848 together with Friedrich Engels, and for a 2,200-page socio-economic work, Capital, published in three volumes in 1867, 1885 and 1894, the last two edited by Engels. The collected works of Marx and Engels extend to over 50 thick volumes.
Marx’s magnum opus, Capital, is an analysis of the capitalist system (the term ‘communism’ is mentioned some five times in notes; perhaps five out of 2,200 pages refer in passing to some future society). Marx wrote the work between 1857 and 1878 while living in London. British capitalism provided his main empirical material.
The changing appreciation of Capital throughout the twentieth century has been influenced by both the degree to which other works of Marx were, or could be, taken into account (§2) and, relatedly, developing methodological views (§3). A reading of the work (§4) is bound to take methodological sides.
1 On Marx and his Capital
Marx was born in 1818 in Trier and died in 1883 in London. He studied law and philosophy and received a PhD in 1841. Trained to pursue the positions of either a state official or university professor, both his studies and the repressive political climate in Prussia induced a different course. During his student years he helped fight for democratic rights, opposing the vested political regime. His subsequent writings and editorship of a liberal journal brought him into conflict with Prussian censorship. He sought refuge in Paris (1843–45), Brussels (1845–47), Cologne (1848–49), and finally, in 1849, settled in London.
In the hectic 1842–49 period, Marx studied and wrote on philosophical, political, and economic issues, and developed his materialist conception of history (§3.1). He also made contact with radical socialist groups, and met Friedrich Engels, his lifelong personal, political, and intellectual friend. In 1848, aged 30, he and Engels wrote the Manifest der Kommunistischen Partei.
From 1849 to about 1865 Marx reduced his political activities and concentrated on serious analysis of the capitalist system, combining research with journalistic work to earn his living. Many thousands of pages were drafted for his magnum opus in a creative and highly productive period. At the same time, he and his family lived in poverty. Income from Marx’s journalistic work was scarce; to survive, they relied on gifts from relatives and friends, especially Engels.
Marx’s research plans were extremely ambitious. He aimed to write a complete systematic analysis of society: economic, social, political, and historical. By 1858 he planned to write six books. The first of these came to completely occupy his mind and energies. It grew to the three volumes of Capital that we now have, together with a sequel account of political economic theories (another three volumes). Marx brought to press himself only the first volume of Capital (1867).
After its 1867 publication, Marx continually revised Volume I, especially its key value-theoretical Part One (the volumes are organised into parts). A second German edition dates from 1873 and a French edition, in instalments, from 1872–75. This process of revision should be kept in mind for those who seek consistency between Volume I and the manuscripts for Volume III, composed in 1864–65.
In the years 1865–70 and 1877–78 Marx wrote much of Volume II of Capital, without completing it. He had gotten re-involved in political activities, but his health also seriously deteriorated. As we will see below, Marx’s Capital project employs a demanding systematic methodology. Towards the end of his life, the requirements for the organisation of the work grew beyond his fading energy.
After Marx’s death, the two remaining volumes of Capital were edited from Marx’s drafts and notebooks by Engels (1885, 1894) and the sequel by Kautsky (1905–10). The drafts are in varied states of completion – the second half of both Volumes II and III consists of reorganised notebooks – and the editors inevitably had their impact on the result. In fact, Marx had considered them unfit for publication.
2 The many Marxes, the many Capitals
Developing historiographic views, as well as developing Marx scholarship, have affected the interpretation of Marx’s Capital (§3). This is not different from other authors. However, in the case of Marx especially, an additional factor is important: the time lags between the posthumous publications of his writings – as well as their translations into (for example) English. Table 1 provides examples.
A 27-year lag between the publication of Volumes I and III meant that Capital I had a life of its own. In 1932 (1938 and 1963 in English), two works of Marx were published that shed new light on his views on money and the capitalist labour process. In 1953 (1973 in English) the Grundrisse, an early 800-page draft of Capital in dialectical style, was published, shedding new light on both the method and content of Capital. Even in the 1990s important new manuscripts were published, and others are still forthcoming. The result is that throughout the twentieth century, and continuing to the present day, there have been many Marxes and many Capitals.
Table 1
‘Many Marxes’: dates of publication of some major works
(1) |
(2) |
(3) |
(4) |
(5) |
(6) |
||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
First publication in German |
Years 1–3 |
First English translation |
Date of manuscript |
Years 1–4 Ms–German |
Years 3–4 Ms–English |
||
1867 |
Das Kapital I |
19 |
1886 |
Capital I |
1861, 1863, 1865–67a |
0 |
19 |
1885 |
Das Kapital II |
22 |
1907 |
Capital II |
1865–70, 1877–78 |
7 |
29 |
1894 |
Das Kapital III |
15 |
1909 |
Capital III |
1864–65 |
29 |
44 |
1905–10 |
Theorien über den Mehrwert (3 vols) |
48–61 |
1952–71 |
Theories of Surplus Valueb |
1862–63 |
47 |
108 |
1932 |
Pariser Manuskripte |
31 |
1963 |
Economic-philosophical manuscripts |
1844 |
88 |
119 |
1932 |
Die deutsche Ideologiec |
6 |
1938 |
The German Ideology (Parts I & III) |
1845–46 |
86 |
92 |
1953 |
Grundrissed |
20 |
1973 |
Grundrissee |
1857–58 |
95 |
115 |
1992 |
Ökonomische Manuskripte 1863–67 [including the Capital III manuscripts] |
– |
– |
– |
1863–67 |
125–29 |
– |
-
Work on second German edition, 1867–72; and on French edition 1872–75.
-
First Volume 1952, A history of economic theories; extracts 1951.
-
Extracts 1902–03, 1921 and 1927.
-
Earlier scarcely available edition 1939–41; its Introduction was published in 1903.
-
Extracts 1964 and 1971.
It is illusory to think that new textual ‘evidence’ changes views overnight, especially for path-breaking publications. The 1953/1973 publication of the Grundrisse has only had a major impact since the mid-1980s. Keynes, himself author of the path-breaking publication The General Theory, explained the reason in its Preface: “The difficulty lies, not in the new ideas, but in escaping from the old ones …”.
The early appreciation of the 1894 (English, 1909) Capital Volume III, or even the 1867 (1886) Volume I of Capital, has shaped the interpretation of Marx in all standard histories of thought, in both the first half of the twentieth century and since. As difficult as it is to write a history, it is much harder to revise a history that has become part of the received view. Whatever textual ‘evidence’ arises, a range of interpretations – perhaps a moving range – will likely ensue.
Table 1 requires a general historiographic note. Columns 1–3, ordered according to dates of publication, are its core. The order of publications – impact – is relevant for a general history of thought. A history of the intellectual development of Karl Marx, or of the ‘making’ of Capital, requires an historical ordering by manuscripts dates (column 4). These are very different historiographic perspectives. (For the latter perspective, the making of Capital, Oakley’s succinct 1983 book is very informative, even if at the time he lacked full information about Engels’s editorial work.)
3 Interpretations of Marx’s method in Capital
Interpretations of Marx’s Capital are intimately related to interpretations of his method, of which five major aspects are examined below. Some version of the first, historical materialism (§3.1), was shared by most commentators until around 1970. The interpretation of Marx’s method in the following period is more complex. Subsequent subsections – roughly in historical order – add in these further complications, in each case building on the methodological aspect of the previous subsection.
3.1 Historical Materialism
Marx embraced, and was the originator of, a materialist conception of history (often called ‘historical materialism’ – the label is not Marx’s). Analytically and institutionally, any society can be seen as a number of domains: political and legal, cultural including education, and economic. For Marx, the development of the economic domain (the “relations of production”) is key to the development of a society at large (a ‘social formation’, such as a feudal or a bourgeois/capitalist society). What happens in the “superstructure” – the juridico-political and cultural domains – is understood in terms of the “base structure” – the economic relations and their requirements. Two aspects are fundamental to the economic relations themselves: first, the relationship between (a) the social layer or class that does the actual work, and (b) the layer or class that has the power to live off the surplus produced by the former, and that usually also possesses the means of production that the former works upon; and second, the “forces of production”, the amalgamation of the labour process in relation to technology (the latter understood in grand, epochal terms).
This schema is especially significant in analysing changes in structures and their aspects, particularly their dynamic interaction during uneven development. ‘Grand’ history can be seen in terms of revolutionary transitions – ‘restructuring’ into more fitting aspects. (Note that especially in the first half of the twentieth century this schema has often been interpreted mono-causally, running from the forces of production, instead of as a dialectic between all structures and aspects.)
Marx developed these ideas when he was 25–30 years of age. They can be seen clearly in the Manifesto. One plausible reading of Capital, or one dimension of it, is as an analysis of the economic base structure of capitalism. Note, though, that the work does not contain an explicit analysis of social class (except for a just over one page unfinished ‘chapter’ on classes at the end of Volume III of Capital, the term class is hardly ever used in Capital). Furthermore, even if there are a few – very few – mostly speculative references to transitional elements within capitalism, transition is not what the work is about.
3.2 Critique
Especially important in reading Capital is the methodology Marx developed alongside his materialist conception of history, namely his method of “critique” – largely acquired from Hegel (post Kant – cf. Benhabib 1986). Almost all Marx’s works carry the term “Critique” [Kritik], which is distinguishable from ‘criticism’. The latter adopts a normative external criterion (ethical, aesthetic or methodological) to evaluate society or such social products as artistic and scientific endeavours. The method of critique evaluates society and social products on the basis of the norms and standards of the object of inquiry itself. An object of inquiry is analysed from within itself. Its norms and standards are taken to their logical conclusions, detecting possible inconsistencies and contradictions – as when capitalist business both lauds ‘market competition’ and seeks to eliminate competitors and achieve monopolistic positions.
In Capital Marx addresses both a material ontological constellation and ideas about it. When the original title, Das Kapital; Kritik der politischen Ökonomie, is translated as: Capital; A Critique of Political Economy (Penguin editions), the double meaning of the German is lost. The English translation correctly indicates that the work is a critique of a science but omits that the work is as much – in my view, in the first place – an internal critique of “the political economy”, an ontological constellation.
Marx scholars today accept ‘internal critique’ as a major aspect of Marx’s method in Capital. However, controversies remain over the method and content of Capital, since other aspects are not necessarily ruled out. For example, is ‘Marx’s’ ‘labour theory of value’ (he never used the expression) still an external norm, or is the concept of value adopted from the object of inquiry? (See further §3.4.)
3.3 Naturalistic versus socio-historical concepts
Marx simultaneously historicises social and economic concepts – the critique is an historicised critique. Social self-understanding usually takes the current social constellation and its concepts for granted, as ‘natural’, or as the norm (‘ethnocentrism’). They are then used to evaluate history or other contemporary societies. (For example, some Americans deploy their notions of ‘market’, ‘competition’, ‘economic freedom’, ‘political democracy’ to evaluate other societies.) Marx identified the ‘mainstream’ political economy of his time as that body of self-understanding in Great Britain and France of 1850 set in ahistorical or naturalistic terms (cf. Mattick 1986).
From this perspective, Marx sometimes distinguished a trans-historical, or general-material, denotation of concepts – ‘goods’ and ‘work’ – from their historical, in this case capitalist, counterpart – ‘commodities’ and ‘labour’ (Arthur 1986; Murray 1988). His aim was not to construct a second language, but to show that in the social domain naturalistic entities do not exist. No trans-historical ‘human needs’, ‘utility’, ‘wealth’, ‘goods’, ‘work’, or ‘technology’ exist; they are always ‘defined’ and ‘subsumed’ within a socio-historical constellation (on human needs, see Campbell 1993; and on wealth and on subsumption generally, Murray 2000, 2002). Whereas J.S. Mill historicises ‘the laws of distribution’ – still eternalising/naturalising ‘the laws of production’ – Marx is a complete de-naturaliser. Anything human is set in an historically specific social form.
3.4 Value-form theory
The view that Marx’s critique is an historicised critique, and that everything human takes on an historically specific social form (§3.3), is highlighted in the recent ‘form theoretic’ interpretation for which Capital is an exposition of the capitalist social form ‘value’ [early proponents are Eldred and Hanlon 1981 and Eldred, Hanlon, Kleiber and Roth 1982–85 who build on work by Backhaus 1969; Rubin 1972 [1923] is an important rediscovered precursor].
The general methodological idea of ‘form theory’ (springing from Aristotle and Hegel – cf. Murray 1997) is that ‘content’ and ‘form’ necessarily go together (for both natural-physical objects and anything created by human beings). ‘Form’ is of the essence of content, just as much as form cannot exist without content. Any actual social formation requires an historically specific form of production and distribution (e.g. tradition, power, democratic decision-making), the capitalist form being value as expressed in monetary dimension. But isn’t it the case that things – sugar, cigar or car – already have a content and form? True. In fact, it is ‘truer’ than the question purports. They surely have a physical form, but from Marx’s point they necessarily also have a social form that can be distinguished but not separated from their physical being. In capitalist economies things are not merely exchanged in markets in terms of value, but are produced as values, which affects how things are qualitatively.
In a traditional interpretation of Capital, Marx introduces in its first chapters a ‘labour theory of value’ – building on the Classical Political Economy of Smith and especially Ricardo – ‘value’ being a naturalistic concept, reckoned in a labour-time dimension. In this interpretation, Marx presents a ‘positive’ theory of value. Hence the materialist internal critique aspect of Marx’s method must, for this part of Capital at least, be de-emphasised (note that the ‘labour-time theory’ interpretation antedates the critique interpretation). For this traditional interpretation, later parts of Capital set out how concrete market phenomena can be ‘reconciled’ with this ‘positive’ theory.
For value-form theory, this first part of Capital is a key materialist critique text. When commodities are produced for sale – a specific characteristic of capitalism – the concrete, utility-producing character of labour is completely secondary to the producer; labour matters to the extent that it is value-producing ‘abstract labour’, a mere expenditure of time. This same text also shows how value (the abstract time facet of labour) is necessarily expressed in abstract monetary terms – and in monetary terms only. Later parts of Capital set out even more complex forms, culminating in the profit form of value, in which things are not merely produced as values, but specifically according to the measure and success-norm of capital: profit and the rate of profit.
How can we appraise these two opposing interpretations? To any reader of Capital it will be obvious that for Marx value is not simply determined by labour-time. The discussions of changing productivity and intensity of labour throughout Volume I problematise such a notion. Nevertheless, Marx often uses the simplified notion as an analytic reference point. Thus, whereas Marx’s value-form theory is a fundamental break from Classical Political Economy, he maintains remnants of a Ricardian labour-time theory of value (Backhaus 1969).
I think that the ‘labour-time theory of value’ interpretation cannot be maintained because too many texts are inconsistent with it. The same applies, however, to a comprehensive monetary value-form interpretation. There are two lines of reasoning within Capital. Marx shares the fate of those who made a fundamental break (a césure), or a paradigm shift, from past conceptions. New conceptions must be formulated in the inherited language. Initial breaks must be partial, inconsistent, or flawed, and need to be completed by researchers following up the break. This, however, does not make the partial break less of an accomplishment (Reuten 1993; for a different view, see Murray 2000).
3.5 Systematic Dialectics
Also controversial is a final methodological interpretation, arising in the middle of the 1980s, which views Capital as Systematic Dialectics. Historical Dialectics describes the evolution and succession of distinct social formations; Systematic Dialectics theorises about one particular social formation, such as the capitalist system, setting out the whole of its object of inquiry as a completely endogenous system, or at least its necessary components and processes.
A major impetus for this interpretation was the 1953/1973 publication of Marx’s Grundrisse, a rough draft of Capital that was, as mentioned in §2, more so than Capital written in a dialectical style. As indicated, a publication, such as the Grundrisse in this case, will not change inherited interpretations overnight. A second impetus was the dedication by a number of scholars (some stimulated by the Grundrisse reading) to the study of the Hegel–Marx connection (cf. Burns and Fraser 2000). As the studies of Marx’s Grundrisse and Hegel’s Systematic-Dialectical works converged, the new interpretation of Capital gradually emerged. [For beginnings, see Banaji 1979, Arthur 1986, and Murray 1988. A comprehensive Systematic-Dialectical interpretation is Smith 1990; cf. his 1993a, 1993b. See Mattick 1993 for critique of the interpretation. For general accounts of the methodology of Systematic Dialectics, not necessarily related to Capital, see Reuten and Williams 1989, pp. 3–36, Arthur 1998, and Reuten 2000.]
A Systematic Dialectic operates on several conceptual levels, from abstract and simple to concrete and complex. Its starting point is also an entry into its whole object of inquiry, formulating that whole both abstractly and simply. Gradual concretion and increasing complexity are achieved at subsequent levels of abstraction; at a final level of ‘abstraction’, the complexity of concrete empirical reality should be attained.
An un-theorised, or naive, empirical reality is the beginning of research. From that, after a complex and creative investigation, the initial highest level of abstraction is reached – the starting point of the systematic presentation (indicated in the previous paragraph). Thus, empirical reality (at first naive, in the end systematically theorised) is both the beginning and the end of the research. A rough outline of this process from the empirical to the abstract to the concrete is found in one of Marx’s few methodological texts (Marx 1903).
Marx identifies neither these levels of abstraction in Capital nor how to get from one level to the next. So this must all be inferred in this interpretation of Capital.
The grand systematic of Capital is in terms of its three volumes: (I) ‘The production of capital’ (from the commodity to money to capital, and from the production of capital through surplus-value to the accumulation of capital); (II) ‘The circulation, or, the organic interconnections of capital’; and (III) ‘The destination and concrete shapes of capital’ (profit and the rate of profit, and competition and the distribution of the fruits of capital into profits of enterprise, interest and rent). The three volumes are each made up of parts, which provide more detailed levels of abstraction.
Levels of abstraction are conceptual terrains. In dialectics, concepts are not fixed – as in conventional ‘linear logic’ (cf. Arthur 1997) – but manifest ongoing conceptual progress from one level of abstraction to another. An axiomatic translation of one level into another is inconsistent with the methodology. In general, when a level of abstraction insufficiently captures the whole, the process is driven forward. Capturing the whole means formulating ‘a system’ that can, in principle, reproduce itself endogenously. At each operating level of abstraction, the ‘discovery’ of its endogeneity limits pushes the process to a new, richer, more complex level. Such a level is institutionally more complex and requires new categories and concepts. With it come both a reconceptualisation and the concretion of the conclusions of earlier levels of abstraction.
To some extent the method may be envisioned as one of successive approximation (Sweezy 1968 [1942]) – but only with the major proviso precluding fixed definitions (they only apply at their own level of abstraction). Indeed, a recurrent reconceptualisation occurs. A succinct example comes from Marx’s Results (1933, p. 969), when he contemplates Volume I of Capital:
Originally, we considered the individual commodity in isolation, as the direct product of a specific quantity of labour. Now, as the result, the product of capital, the commodity changes in form (and later on, in the price of production, it will be changed in substance too).
Earlier he had written (p. 954):
The commodity may now be further defined as follows: … The labour expended on each commodity can no longer be calculated except as an average, i.e., an ideal estimate. … When determining the price of an individual article it appears as a merely ideal fraction of the total product in which the capital reproduces itself.
The manuscripts for the final versions of the three volumes of Capital that we have are dated in ‘odd’ order (Table 1). Inasmuch as Marx reworked and reconceptualised his manuscripts for Volume I, this would have affected the re-study of the levels of abstraction in Volumes II and III. The three volumes of Capital are not only in different states of draft (ranging from mere notes to final versions), but, more important for a Systematic Dialectic, in different states of conception. It is thus especially important to remember, for a Systematic-Dialectical interpretation of Capital, that its last two volumes cannot be seen as conceptually final.
3.6 Conclusions
By 2000 Marx scholars have largely agreed that Capital analyses its object of enquiry from within, aiming to drive the object’s (capital’s) own standards and processes to their logical conclusions. Marx’s method of critique is largely an historicised critique. Whether it is a totally historicised critique – as highlighted in the value-form interpretation – is disputed. While most Marx scholars also agree that some type of conceptual development, or at least ‘successive approximation’, exists in Capital, whether it is as rigorous as the Systematic-Dialectical interpretation claims is disputed.
All of these different overall interpretations of Capital can find confirmations in Marx’s texts. However, there is increasing evidence, from §3.1 to §3.5, falsifying each successive position. We might thus say that Capital is a rich heuristic source of a variety of different reconstructive theoretical approaches.
4 A synopsis of the systematic structure of Capital
A synopsis of the general structure of Marx’s Capital must be informed by some methodological interpretation. The present synopsis relies on the most recent Systematic-Dialectical interpretation, not pushed too far, and with dialectical jargon avoided. Most Marx scholars will recognise the general outline of this structure – if perhaps not all details. The general scheme of the structure – see Table 2 on p. 26 – has some affinity with a sophisticated schema of Arthur (2002a).
Table 2
The systematic of Capital
Capital |
A |
B |
C |
---|---|---|---|
What it is |
How it works |
The resulting process |
|
Volume I Its production How it arises |
Parts 1 and 2 From commodity to money; from money to capital |
Parts 3–6 Production process of capital |
Part 7 Accumulation of capital (Annex, Part 8) |
Volume II Its circulation How it operates |
Part 1 Capital as circuit |
Part 2 Turnover of capital |
Part 3 Extended social reproduction of capital |
Volume III Its destination How it culminates |
Part 1 Measure of capital – profit-form and profit rate |
Part 2 Competition and movement of capital; formation of general profit rate |
Part 3 Cyclical evolution of the profit rate Parts 4–6 Industry, commerce, finance, landed property (Reflection, Part 7) |
The Table 2 scheme implies that, for example, the answer to the question ‘What is it?’ at the first level (I-A) is insufficient. Subsequent levels (II-A, III-A) provide reconceptualisation and concretion. The same applies to the question of ‘How it works’ (I-B to III-B) and ‘The resulting process’ (I-C to III-C). This involves a ‘vertical’ conceptual progress; we also have a ‘horizontal’ conceptual progress (from I-A to I-B etc.). Below, each entry is considered in turn, with extra space devoted to the first (I-A).
References to Capital are by volume number and page number. References to the secondary literature are provided for the most controversial issues only. For various methodological aspects of Capital see Moseley (ed.) 1993 and Moseley and Campbell (eds) 1997; recent articles with further references on the three volumes can be found in Bellofiore and Taylor (eds) 2003, Arthur and Reuten (eds) 1998, Campbell and Reuten (eds) 2002, and Bellofiore (ed.) 1998.
DIV-1-4-1
I-A What is capital? – How it arises
‘Capital’ might be a sum of money, a quantity of means of production, or an investment in commodities. All such ‘shapes’ of capital have in common that they are value forms. For Marx ‘the commodity’ is the elementary shape of the value-form. Therefore he starts with its analysis (Capital I, Part One), turning in succession to money and capital.
There are two aspects to Part One. First, Marx seeks in ‘value’ a reference point for all his Volume I analysis. The problem of a suitable reference point has troubled all great economists, from Petty through Smith, Ricardo and onward to Keynes and later. A main problem in understanding Marx’s text is that he seeks (cf., §3.2) an endogenous reference point, one internal to his object of enquiry. (In contradistinction to external constructs, such as – later on in history – index numbers, or Sraffa’s standard commodity.)
Secondly, Marx seeks not a naturalistic, but an historically specific social reference point (cf., §3.3); one that applies to a society in which commodities are systematically produced with a view to sale (I, pp. 138–9, 153–4, 174). The two aspects appear to combine into one problematic, posing an even greater difficulty for the text.
The reference point for value is “abstract labour” measured by labour-time (I, p. 129). (Therefore Marx’s theory has often been interpreted as a ‘labour theory of value’.) Simultaneously, Marx posits, first, that value exists only in a “value-relation or an exchange relation” and, secondly, that it is manifested in the value form par excellence, the money form (I, 138–9, 152, cf., 255). Indeed, throughout Capital, Marx always expresses value and value entities in monetary terms (£’s). (Thus it seems that Marx adopts a monetary measure of value.) I think, then, that we must accept that there is an ambiguity here, which can only be resolved in a reconstructive way (see, e.g., Backhaus 1969; Bellofiore 1989; Reuten 1993; Smith 1998; Bellofiore and Finelli 1998; Arthur 2002b).
Note that, like the concept of capital, the concept of money – as introduced in Part One, is developed throughout Volumes II–III. Marx starts from a notion of commodity money; this is procedural within a ‘successive approximation’ approach (cf. Campbell 1997, 1998, 2002; Williams 2000).
Marx develops the (level I) concept of capital in sequence from an analysis of the commodity and money. Part Two of Capital I introduces capital proper. Marx’s answer to the question ‘What is capital?’, towards the end of this Part, is abstract and formal: it is inherent to capital that it expands ‘in movement’: “The movement of capital is … the unceasing movement of profit-making” (I, pp. 253–4). It is a movement from money (M) into more money: M … M +
the subject of a process in which, while constantly assuming the form in turn of money and commodities, it changes its own magnitude, throws off surplus-value from itself considered as original value, and thus valorises itself independently. For the movement in the course of which it adds surplus-value is its own movement, its valorisation is therefore self-valorisation. (I, p. 255)
So capital is a movement of self-valorisation, of throwing off surplus-value. (Note that Marx has ‘bracketed’ the notion of ‘profit’ and replaced it by the more abstract notion of ‘surplus-value’. Later on (III-A) we will see “surplus-value” transformed into “profit” and the latter again in the sum of “profit of enterprise”, interest and rent. Before examining the processes of that distribution – in Volume III – Marx’s concern is to explain the abstract total. In Volume I (and II) he proceeds from the temporary assumption that each capitalist owns means of production and requires no hiring or borrowing of land, dwellings, or external finance (I, p. 710).)
Part Two closes by formally introducing a particular commodity and commodity market, that of labour-power, the existence of which is predicated on workers’ lack of means of production. It includes a brief introduction to the value of labour-power; that is, the wage that in principle should be sufficient to reproduce the labour-power – ‘sufficient’ depending on physical, historical, and moral elements (I, pp. 272–5).
I-B How capital works – how it arises
Capital, we saw, is a movement of self-valorisation, of throwing off surplus-value. The middle part of Volume I considers “not only how capital produces, but how capital is itself produced” (I, p. 280). How can surplus-value be explained? Recall M – C – M´. “The change in value of the money … cannot take place in the money itself … The change must therefore take place in the commodity …” (I, p. 270). Hence the key to M – C – M´ lies in C. Marx next shows that the production process is the site where the value of C is turned into C´.
In the exchange M – C, capital in money-form is turned into capital in commodity form: means of production and labour-power. Labour-power is exchanged against the wage, and labourers sell their labour potential. During production, labour is ‘subordinated’ to capital: “the worker works under the control of the capitalist … the product is the property of the capitalist and not that of the worker” (I, pp. 291–2). Because the means of production are static elements, a change in C can only be engendered by the active living element: labour. Labour alone can generate a surplus-value beyond the wage. In labour resides the potential to produce a surplus-product, or, in value-terms, surplus-value. Marx calls the ratio between the amount of surplus-value and the capital laid out in wages the “rate of surplus-value” or the “degree of exploitation of labour-power by capital” (I, pp. 320–7).
The body of the middle part of Capital I, which is more than 400 pages long, consists of a detailed analysis of methods and (organisational) techniques for increasing the rate of exploitation. Throughout, Marx uses the labour-time reference point. Nevertheless, as previously indicated, all of his value entities are expressed in monetary terms (£’s); the same applies to all his numerical examples (cf. Elson 1979a).
I-C Capital’s resulting process – how it arises
“Earlier we considered how surplus-value arises from capital; now we have to see how capital arises from surplus-value. The employment of surplus-value as capital, or its reconversion into capital, is called accumulation of capital” (I, p. 725). In Part Seven, Marx shows how capital’s growth results in three simultaneous dynamic processes: (1) the propagation of a reserve army of unemployed labour, especially by way of the introduction of labour-expelling techniques of production pressing down the wage rate; (2) cyclical growth of capital; and (3) centralisation of capital.
The final Part Eight provides an historical account of the conditions of the buying and sale of labour-power: ownership of the means of production by capitalists. This is the precondition for the I-A starting point, and so rounds off this level of analysis as a circle.
DIV-1-4-2
II-A What is capital? – How it operates
In I-A, Marx treats capital as ‘movement’. Indeed, all of Volume I describes movement, resulting in expanded movement (valorisation and accumulation). In Part One of Volume II this is made explicit. Capital is shown to be a continuous movement through four manifestations/shapes, together constituting the circuit of capital:
→ M —E— C [MP; LP] ..... P ..... C´ —E— M´ →
Capital in the shape of “money capital” (M) is transformed in the exchange process (–E–) into the shape of “production capital” (C); specifically, means of production (MP) and labour-power (LP). The latter work up the former in the process of production (···) where we have the shape of “capital in process” (P); this constitutes a metamorphosis into valorised “commodity capital” (C´), with C´ different qualitatively from C, as well as quantitatively in value terms (C´> C). Finally, another exchange transforms the expanded commodity value C´ into a monetary value equivalent M´, the shape of expanded “money capital”. The process can now resume on an expanded scale – wherein capital is accumulated.
II-B How capital works – How it operates
Until Part Two, capital has been implicitly treated as an expanding flow (fixed capital as introduced in Volume I was set to zero). Now Marx explicitly distinguishes circulating from fixed capital. It is shown how capital as movement works in production in terms of length of production periods and turnover-times of capital. ‘Time’ is key to capital. Speeding up any of the phases of the circuit means that a given quantity of capital can turn around more production.
II-C Capital’s resulting process – how it operates
Part Three presents the circulation of capital in the context of the economy as a whole. Using a two-sector ‘model’, Marx specifies dynamic interconnections pertinent to economic growth and conditions for balanced growth. These conditions are very severe and the implication is that balanced growth is possible, though unlikely.
DIV-1-4-3
III-A What is capital? – How it culminates
Part One of Volume III considers surplus-value (flow) in relation to total capital invested (stock) and introduces the key capitalist profit form: “A sum of value is … capital if it is invested in order to produce a profit …” (III, p. 126). This involves a conceptual transformation of both “surplus-value” and “capital” such that the rate of profit measures the valorisation of capital. Profit and the rate of profit are capital’s continuity measures.
III-B How capital works – how it culminates
The profit-form brings a new dynamic (III, pp. 263, 267, 275); Part Two shows how the profit rate measure works. Since for capital its particular physical content does not matter (bread, spirits or bibles), another aspect of capital’s movement is its flow to branches where it attains the highest profit rate. Thus competition between capitals produces an averaging of the profit rate. Concomitantly we have a further commodification of workers who must move “from one sphere to another and from one local point of production to another” (III, p. 298).
With the profit-form, the concept of price developed in Volume I is modified. After this, however, Marx surprisingly tries to make quantitative translations between the conceptual levels, comparing the transformed profit-form entities with a calculation prior to the profit form. In this Marx underscores the dynamic introduced at this level. The literature on the interpretation and reconstruction of this ‘transformation’ is enormous; for references, see Moseley 1993, Mohun 1994, Foley 2000, Bellofiore 2002, Laibman 2002, and various articles in Bellofiore (ed.) 1998, Vol. 1.
III-C Capital’s resulting process – how it culminates
Part Three presents the resulting dynamic of diachronic change in the average rate of profit through the profit-enforced introduction of cost-reducing techniques of production. These generate cyclical rate-of-profit increases to the initiating capital and a simultaneous cyclical average rate-of-profit decrease, as reversed in cyclical restructuring of capital (for this interpretation, see Reuten 2002a, 2004 – cf. Lebowitz 1976; Fine and Harris 1979; Groll and Orzech 1987).
No longer restricted to undifferentiated “industrial capital”, Parts Four to Six show capital separated into functionally different and conflicting factions: industrial, commercial, financial, and real estate. Profit now separates and is distributed as profit of enterprise, interest and rent (Moseley 2002). The final Part Seven is a draft for further concrete manifestations of the whole. It also emphasises Marx’s fundamental point that capitalism is an historically specific and mutable mode of production that conceals its class structure (Mattick 2002; Murray 2002).
Summary
In Capital the one-dimensionality of the capitalist social form – the value-form as expressed monetary terms – is the basis for capital as a “movement of self-valorisation”. Volume I treats the aspect of self-valorisation as movement and Volume II movement in macrosocial context. In Volume III these aspects are articulated in the working of the profit-form and the ‘concrete abstraction’ of a dimensionless rate of profit – money over money. That non-dimensionality, indifferent to content, drives the base structure of a capitalist society.
5 Marx’s theory and Marxian theory as a strand
The main interpretations of Marx’s work should be distinguished from the twentieth century growth of ‘Marxian theory’ as one strand alongside, in economics, the institutionalist, neoclassical, post-Keynesian, and others (for a historiography, see Howard and King 1989; 1992). Marxian theory and institutionalism share an interdisciplinary emphasis, although Marxian theory is a multidisciplinary project conducted by philosophers, economists, political scientists, sociologists, social geographers, and historians.
Current Marxian theory includes three types of research. A first type, nearest to Marx’s work, is empirical research based on Marx’s theory (such as the long run development of the macroeconomic profit rate – e.g., Moseley 1991; Duménil and Lévy 1993; Wolff 2001). Even more complicated than in mainstream economics, the concepts behind the statistical data differ from the theoretical concepts. Of course, such empirical studies involve interpretation of Marx’s theory.
If one finds Marx’s work to be inconsistent or unsatisfactory, a second type is theory reconstruction. Reconstructive work ranges across all fields of Marx’s writings (particularly all components of Table 2). Methodological work is a facet of this type (see, e.g., the contributions in Albritton and Simoulidis (ed.) 2002).
A third type is non-reconstructive theory development. For example, elements of business cycle theory – corresponding to their level of analysis (column 3 of Table 2) – are found in all three volumes of Capital. Building on those elements, contemporary Marxian business cycle researchers may seek for an empirically testable theory of the cycle; this has requirements other than those intended, or at least reached, by Marx (for references, see Reuten 2002b). Other examples are economic policy research (not reached in Capital) or, more generally, the study of the institutional conditions surrounding the accumulation of capital in different historical periods of capitalism (‘phases’, or ‘social structures’, or ‘regimes’ of accumulation; see the contributions in Albritton et al. 2001).
Although much of this work has drifted away from Capital, or at least beyond it, we nevertheless see in the former considerable reference to the latter (critically or complimentarily). This is an interesting aspect of Marx’s status within the history of thought. It is also a fascinating aspect of the study of the history of thought generally, namely that it can serve as a rich heuristic source of inspiration for current ideas.
I am grateful for comments by Chris Arthur, Mark Blaug, Gerald Levy, Paul Mattick, Patrick Murray, Tony Smith, Nicola Taylor and the editors of this book, especially Warren Samuels and John Davis.
References
Albritton, Robert, and John Simoulidis (eds) 2002, New dialectics and political economy, Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Albritton, Robert, Makato Itoh, Richard Westra, and Alan Zuege (eds) 2001, Phases of capitalist development: booms, crises and globalizations, Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Arthur, Christopher J. 1986, Dialectics of labour: Marx and his relation to Hegel, New York: Blackwell.
Arthur, Christopher J. 1997, ‘Against the logical-historical method: dialectical derivation versus linear logic’, in Moseley and Campbell (eds) 1997, pp. 9–37.
Arthur, Christopher J. 1998, ‘Systematic dialectic’, Science & Society, 62(3): 447–59.
Arthur, Christopher J. 2002a, ‘Capital in general and Marx’s Capital’, in Campbell and Reuten (eds) 2002, pp. 42–64.
Arthur, Christopher J. 2002b, ‘The spectral ontology of value’, in Andrew Brown, Steve Fleetwood, and J.M. Roberts (eds), Critical realism and Marxism, London: Routledge, pp. 215–33.
Arthur, Christopher J., and Geert Reuten (eds) 1998, The circulation of capital: essays on volume II of Marx’s ‘Capital’, London/New York: Macmillan/St. Martin’s Press.
Backhaus, Hans-Georg 1969, ‘Zur Dialektik der Wertform’, in A. Schmidt (ed.), Beiträge zur Marxistischen Erkenntnistheorie, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. English translation: M. Eldred and M. Roth 1980, ‘On the dialectics of the value-form’, Thesis Eleven, 1: 99–120.
Banaji, Jairus 1979, ‘From the commodity to capital: Hegel’s dialectic in Marx’s Capital’, in Elson (ed.) 1979, pp. 14–45.
Bellofiore, Riccardo 1989, ‘A monetary labor theory of value’, Review of Radical Political Economics, 21(1–2): 1–25.
Bellofiore, Riccardo (ed.) 1998, Marxian economics: a reappraisal, 2 vols., London: Macmillan.
Bellofiore, Riccardo 2002, ‘“Transformation” and the monetary circuit: Marx as a monetary theorist of production’, in Campbell and Reuten (eds) 2002, pp. 102–27.
Bellofiore, Riccardo, and Roberto Finelli 1998, ‘Capital, labour and time: the Marxian monetary labour theory of value as a theory of exploitation’, in Bellofiore (ed.) 1998, pp. 48–74.
Bellofiore, Riccardo, and Nicola Taylor (eds) 2003, The constitution of capital: essays on volume I of Marx’s ‘Capital’, Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Benhabib, Seyla 1986, Critique, norm, and utopia, New York: Columbia University Press.
Burns, Tony, and Ian Fraser (eds) 2000, The Hegel–Marx connection, London: Macmillan.
Campbell, Martha 1993, ‘The commodity as necessary form of product’, in R. Blackwell, J. Chatha, and E.J. Nell (eds), Economics as worldly philosophy; essays in political and historical economics in honour of Robert L. Heilbroner, New York: St. Martin’s Press, pp. 269–302.
Campbell, Martha 1997, ‘Marx’s theory of money: a defense’, in Moseley and Campbell (eds) 1997, pp. 89–120.
Campbell, Martha 1998, ‘Money in the circulation of capital’, in Arthur and Reuten (eds) 1998, pp. 129–58.
Campbell, Martha 2002, ‘The credit system’, in Campbell and Reuten (eds) 2002, pp. 212–27.
Campbell, Martha, and Geert Reuten (eds) 2002, The culmination of capital: essays on volume III of Marx’s ‘Capital’, London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Duménil, Gérard, and Dominique Lévy 1993, The economics of the profit rate: competition, crises and historical tendencies in capitalism, Aldershot: Edward Elgar.
Eldred, Michael, and Marnie Hanlon 1981, ‘Reconstructing value-form analysis’, Capital & Class, 13: 24–60.
Eldred, Michael, Marnie Hanlon, Lucia Kleiber, and Mike Roth 1982–85, ‘Reconstructing value-form analysis 1–4’, Thesis Eleven, 1982/4, 1983/7, 1984/9, 1985/11. Modified as ‘A Value-form Analytic Reconstruction of Capital’, in appendix to M. Eldred, Critique of competitive freedom and the bourgeois-democratic state, København: Kurasje, pp. 350–487.
Elson, Diane 1979a, ‘The value theory of labour’, in Elson (ed.) 1979b, pp. 115–80.
Elson, Diane (ed.) 1979b, Value: the representation of labour in capitalism, London: CSE Books.
Fine, Ben, and Laurence Harris 1979, Rereading Capital, London: Macmillan.
Foley, Duncan 2000, ‘Recent developments in the labor theory of value’, Review of Radical Political Economics, 32(1): 1–39.
Groll, Shalom, and Ze’ev B. Orzech 1987, ‘Technical progress and values in Marx’s theory of the decline in the rate of profit: an exegetical approach’, History of Political Economy, 19(4): 591–613.
Howard, Michael C., and Jesse E. King 1989/1992, A history of Marxian economics: volume I, 1883–1929; volume II 1929–1990, London: Macmillan.
Laibman, David 2002, ‘Value and the quest for the core of capitalism’, Review of Radical Political Economics, 34(2): 159–78.
Lebowitz, Michael A. 1976, ‘Marx’s falling rate of profit: a dialectical view’, Canadian Journal of Economics, 9(2): 232–54.
Marx, Karl 1867, 4th edn. 1890, Das Kapital, Kritik der Politischen Ökonomie, Band I, Der Produktionsprozeß des Kapitals, MEW 23 [cited English translation by Ben Fowkes, Capital, a critique of political economy, volume I, 1976, Harmondsworth: Penguin].
Marx, Karl 1885; 2nd edn. 1893, ed. F. Engels, Das Kapital, Kritik der Politischen Ökonomie, Band II, Der Zirkulationsprozeß des Kapitals, MEW 24 [cited English translation by David Fernbach, Capital: a critique of political economy, volume II, 1978, Harmondsworth: Penguin].
Marx, Karl 1894, ed. F. Engels, Das Kapital, Kritik der Politischen Ökonomie, Band III, Der Gesamtprozesz der kapitalistischen Produktion, MEW 25 [cited English translation by David Fernbach, Capital: a critique of political economy, volume III, 1981, Harmondsworth: Penguin].
Marx, Karl 1903, ‘Einleitung’ (zu Grundrisse der Kritik der Politischen Ökonomie), ed. Karl Kautsky, Die Neue Zeit [cited English translation by M. Nicolaus, 1973, see Marx 1953, pp. 81–111].
Marx, Karl 1933, Resultate des Unmittelbaren Produktionsprozeßes, Frankfurt: Verlag Neue Kritik. First English translation by R. Livingstone 1976, ‘Results of the immediate process of production’, in Capital: a critique of political economy, volume I, trans. B. Fowkes, Harmondsworth: Penguin, pp. 948–1084.
Marx, Karl 1953 [1939–41], Grundrisse der Kritik der Politischen Ökonomie (Rohentwurf), first English edition 1973, Grundrisse, trans. M. Nicolaus, Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Marx, Karl n.d. Capital, volumes I–III [disc version of Lawrence & Wishart/International Publishers edition], Marx and Engels, Classics in Politics, London: The Electronic Book Company (ElecBook).
Marx, Karl, and Friedrich Engels, Collected works (CW), London/New York/Moscow: Lawrence & Wishart/International Publishers/Progress Publishers.
Marx, Karl, and Friedrich Engels, Gesamtausgabe (MEGA), Berlin and Amsterdam: Akademie Verlag/Dietz Verlag/Internationales Institut für Sozialgeschichte Amsterdam.
Marx, Karl, and Friedrich Engels, Marx Engels Werke, Berlin: Dietz Verlag.
Mattick Jr., Paul 1986, Social knowledge: an essay on the nature and limits of social science, London: Hutchinson.
Mattick Jr., Paul 1993, ‘Marx’s dialectic’, in Moseley (ed.) 1993, pp. 115–34.
Mattick Jr., Paul 2002, ‘Class, capital, and crisis’, in Campbell and Reuten (eds) 2002, pp. 16–41.
Mohun, Simon 1994, ‘A re(in)statement of the labour theory of value’, Cambridge Journal of Economics, 18: 391–412.
Moseley, Fred 1991, The falling rate of profit in the postwar United States economy, London: Macmillan.
Moseley, Fred (ed.) 1993, Marx’s method in ‘Capital’: a re-examination, Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press.
Moseley, Fred 1993, ‘Marx’s logical method and the “transformation problem”’, in Moseley (ed.) 1993, pp. 157–84.
Moseley, Fred 2002, ‘Hostile brothers: Marx’s theory of the distribution of surplus-value in volume III of Capital’, in Campbell and Reuten (eds) 2002, pp. 65–101.
Moseley, Fred, and Martha Campbell (eds) 1997, New investigations of Marx’s method, Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press.
Murray, Patrick 1988/1990, Marx’s theory of scientific knowledge, Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press.
Murray, Patrick 1997, ‘Redoubled empiricism: the place of social form and formal causality in Marxian theory’, in Moseley and Campbell (eds) 1997, pp. 38–65.
Murray, Patrick 2000, ‘Marx’s “truly social” labour theory of value: abstract labour in Marxian value theory’, Historical Materialism, 6: 27–66 (Part 1) and 7: 99–136 (Part 2).
Murray, Patrick 2002, ‘The illusion of the economic: the trinity formula and “the religion of everyday life”’, in Campbell and Reuten (eds) 2002, pp. 246–73.
Oakley, Allen 1983, The making of Marx’s critical theory: a bibliographical analysis, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Reuten, Geert 1993, ‘The difficult labour of a theory of social value: metaphors and systematic dialectics at the beginning of Marx’s Capital’, in Moseley (ed.) 1993, pp. 89–113.
Reuten, Geert 2000, ‘The interconnection of systematic dialectics and historical materialism’, Historical Materialism, 7: 137–66.
Reuten, Geert 2002a, ‘The rate of profit cycle and the opposition between managerial and finance capital: a discussion of Capital III parts 3–5’, in Campbell and Reuten (eds) 2002, pp. 174–211.
Reuten, Geert 2002b, ‘Business cycles: Marxian approach’, in Brian Snowdon and Howard Vane (eds), Encyclopedia of macroeconomics, Aldershot: Edward Elgar, pp. 73–80.
Reuten, Geert 2004, ‘“Zirkel vicieux” or trend fall? – the course of the profit rate in Marx’s Capital III’, History of Political Economy, 36(1): 163–86.
Reuten, Geert, and Michael Williams 1989, Value-form and the state; the tendencies of accumulation and the determination of economic policy in capitalist society, London: Routledge.
Rubin, Isaak Illich 1972 [1923], Ocherki po teorii stoimosti Marksa, 3rd edn, Moscow 1928, Engl. transl. Miloš Samardžija and Fredy Perlman, Essays on Marx’s theory of value, Detroit: Black & Red.
Smith, Tony 1990, The logic of Marx’s Capital: replies to Hegelian criticisms, Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
Smith, Tony 1993a, ‘Marx’s Capital and Hegelian dialectical logic’, in Moseley (ed.) 1993, pp. 15–36.
Smith, Tony 1993b, Dialectical social theory and its critics, Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
Smith, Tony 1998, ‘Value theory and dialectics’, Science & Society, 62(3): 460–70.
Sweezy, Paul M. 1942/1968, The theory of capitalist development, New York: Modern Reader Paperbacks.
Williams, Michael 2000, ‘Why Marx neither has nor needs a commodity theory of money’, Review of Political Economy, 12(4): 435–51.
Wolff, Edward 2001, ‘The recent rise of profits in the United States’, Review of Radical Political Economics, 33: 315–24.