2005 article, originally published in Marx’s theory of money: modern appraisals, edited by Fred Moseley, London/New York: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 78–92.
(For its abstract see the Abstracts of all chapters, p. 4.)
Contents
Introduction
1 The monetary dimension
1.1 Form, prevalence, systemic existence
1.2 Extroversion
1.3 The introversive and the extroversive constituent of value
1.4 From a simple to an enriched notion of value
2 Very abstract labour
2.1 False analogies – abstract labour and abstract timber – and the disappearance of the simplified notion of abstract labour
2.2 Immanent substance and immanent measure – abstract labour and method
3 Money’s measuring: ideal transubstantiation
3.1 Idealities
3.2 Marx’s notion of ‘measurement’: ‘verwandlen’ and standardised measurement
3.3 Imaginary measurement by imaginary money
3.4 Extroversive hypostasisation
4 An introversive regress: bullion
Summary and Conclusions
References
Introduction1
In the first volume of Capital Marx introduces ‘money’ in Chapter 1 (section 3) and then reintroduces it in Chapter 3. At first sight the second introduction seems merely a superfluous excursion at this point since in the remainder of the book Marx apparently does not ‘do’ anything with it. He returns to money only in Capital II (Part Two) and then again in Capital III (Parts Four and Five). This may be one reason why the Chapter 3 introduction has for a long time been much neglected.
Over the last 15 years commentators of Marx have tended to focus on the aspect of the ‘commodity money’ basis in Marx’s theory. This is relevant for the current Marxian theory of capitalism, but it is irrelevant for the historical assessment of an author writing in the second half of the nineteenth century.2 Yet another issue is the methodological question of why Marx – given that commodity money basis – postpones a full account of credit money till later in the work. Here I ally myself with Campbell who argues that this issue should be assessed from within Marx’s method and systematic, especially the gradual movement from relatively simple to complex concepts and accounts.3
In this essay I provide a novel interpretation of the relation between the two introductions of money referred to (Chapter 1 and Chapter 3 of Capital I). In particular I will argue that Chapter 3 sheds indispensable light on what happens in Chapter 1; Chapter 1 is a one-sided account that gets complemented in Chapter 3. A neglect of the core aspect that I will emphasise about Chapter 3 must have consequences for all further interpretations of the book; however, I cannot deal with that issue here.4
This essay is historiographic and hence I abstain from presenting my own (value-form theoretical) views. Thus there is no question of agreement or disagreement with Marx involved other than internal critique.
I refer to the German Das Kapital I by (1867G – quoted from the 4th edition of 1890) and to the English Fowkes translation by (1867F – as translated from the 4th edition). Unspecified page references (e.g. 180) are always to the latter. Note that Chapters 1–3 together constitute Part One of the book.
1 The monetary dimension
1.1 Form, prevalence, systemic existence
The standpoint of Chapter 1 of Capital I is ‘the commodity’. The relatively brief Chapter 2, on the process of exchange, introduces social actors of exchange and the action of society to turn a particular commodity into the general equivalent ‘money’ (180) within a society of generalised commodity production (187). Thus Chapter 2 posits the prevalence (Dasein) of money in practice. Whereas Chapter 1 already posits the form of money, money itself (i.e., its systemic existence) is derived in Chapter 3. Notably it is systematically derived from exchange, just as the commodity and value were derived from exchange. Behind it is a notion of dissociate production, but this is implicit.5 It is only later that the role of value, that is money’s role in production and the full circuit of capital, will become explicit (that is in all the rest of Capital). But in order to comprehend this role, Chapter 3 is absolutely crucial.
1.2 Extroversion
Throughout Chapter 3 Marx frequently uses the term veräußerlichen for ‘to sell’, which literally means ‘to outer’ or ‘outering’. Nevertheless, the normal German term would be verkaufen (a term that he also uses; the difference is lost in the English translation). He also uses entäußeren for the same, as well as other terms with the same root of außer, especially Außdruck (expression; compare the roots außer, outer, utter). This homology is also lost in the translation.
The term ‘outer’ prepares one, of course, for an ‘inner’ or ‘immanent’. Moreover, against the background of Marx’s familiarity with Hegel’s philosophy, the terms are rather heavy; they point at ‘moments’ that can be distinguished but that inseparably belong together.
At the end of the first section of Chapter 3 of Das Kapital I Marx writes (1867G: 118; italics added): “Die Preisform schließt die Veräußerlichkeit der Waren gegen Geld und die Notwendigkeit dieser Veräußerung ein.” Fowkes translates (198) as: “The price-form therefore [?] implies both the exchangeability of commodities for money and the necessity of exchanges.” Apart from the ‘therefore’ this translation is defendable, but it completely loses the connection pointed out above. A more literal translation would be: “The price-form implies/entails the ‘extroversibility’ of commodities for money as well as the necessity of this ‘extroversion’.” But without explication this would not make sufficient sense in English.6
1.3 The introversive and the extroversive constituent of value
In Marx’s view money is one constituent of value (he does not use exactly this formulation). The immanent or introversive constituent of value is undifferentiated ‘abstract labour’ (Chapter 1), its extroversive (außer) constituent is money (Chapter 3); but these two inseparably belong together. Money is the necessary form of expression of value (Außdruck). That is, value has no existence without money.7 This is the end-result of Part One.
Another way of saying that value has no existence without money is to say that value is without exception of monetary dimension.8 In fact this is already the outcome of Chapter 1. Its Section 3 presents the formation of the form of money; or one could say it posits the form of extroversion (Veräußerlichung) which is the starting point for Chapter 3.9
Marx introduces the concept of ‘value-form’ in Chapter 1. After that the term moves to the background in the sense that it is only sporadically used. The reason is that in Chapter 3 the concept is concretised into its monetary expression. Key to this concretisation is money’s role as measure of value as well as the meaning of ‘measure’ (see §3 below).
1.4 From a simple to an enriched notion of value
Section 1 of Chapter 3 sets out the ‘function’ of money as ‘measure of values’. This may give the (false) impression of there ‘being’ value entities independently of the ‘measure’, that is independently of money. If Marx had started here from scratch and considered the measurement of a use-value in terms of money, the problem would not have arisen. In fact he considers commodities.
If my interpretation as set out in §1.3 is accepted we move from a simplified notion of value (Chapter 1) to an enriched one (that of the full Part One), each indicated with one term ‘value’ (§2.2 below). Evidently, we cannot but start Chapter 3 with the simple notion of value inherited from the previous chapters. Therefore, there might at first sight appear to be two lines of reasoning in Chapter 3: labour-time and money. Near to the opening of Chapter 3 Marx writes (188): “Money as a measure of value is the necessary form of appearance of the measure of value which is immanent in commodities, namely labour-time.” The first line of reasoning is an obvious reference back to the Chapter 1, what I call, simple–abstract ‘immanent’ or introversive notion of value with its immanent measure, namely labour-time. The other line posits that money is ‘the necessary form of appearance’ of that immanency. The commodity, and hence value, has no existence without money: “products of labour … taking the form of commodities implies their differentiation into commodities and the money commodity” (188n).
The monistic focus on the introversive notion of value in much of the Marxian economics after Marx is certainly also due to Marx’s presentation of the matter, especially his particular way of moving from simplified determinations to complex ones.10 However, because of the inseparability of the introversive and the extroversive constituents of value, monistic phrases such as ‘labour-values’, or conversely, ‘value-prices’ do not fit Marx’s theory and hence are never used in Capital.
2 Very abstract labour
2.1 False analogies – abstract labour and abstract timber – and the disappearance of the simplified notion of abstract labour
The (false) impression of there being value entities independently of the ‘money measure’ is reinforced by (false) analogies with other types of measurement. When we measure the length of a table with a metre stick, the table’s length exists independently of the stick.11 The analogy is false because the table is fully constituted as material/substance (introversive) and form (extroversive). There is no obvious unique way to measure the length of the material of the table (i.e., the length of the timber and nails, say). Surely we can in principle measure the length of two odd pieces of freshly cut timber – in this sense we have measurables – but we cannot add those up in a unique sensible way because of their unequal shapes.
To redress the analogy: there is no obvious unique way to measure the ‘introversive substance’ of value. You cannot add up nails and timber to measure the length of a table, or at least these would be awkwardly related. The same goes for concrete labour in connection to value.
In Chapter 1, therefore, Marx takes recourse to the notion of ‘abstract labour’ as a simplified constituent of value (it would be misleading to call this even an abstract substitute measure).12 It is most telling that after this chapter the term ‘abstract labour’ disappears, with four exceptions. In face of the Marxian discourse of the last 20 years this cannot be stressed enough.13
When in Chapter 1 Marx presents the commodity, he posits their being and prevalence (Dasein). In fact their existence is only grounded when he gets to their production in Parts Three to Five (though even this grounding is still a simplified one). In a different jargon: their production is presupposed (the presupposition being grounded later). Similarly, when presenting the commodity in Chapter 1 Marx presupposes the money measure that is only grounded (still simple) in Chapter 3. Abstract labour foreshadows the money measure.
Column 2 of Table 1 (p. 143) provides a schematic outline of the determinations of value. Column 1 sets out a hypothetical analogy with another realm. Several entries in the Table will be expanded upon later.
Table 1
A hypothetical analogy for the measurement of material ‘tables’ and of social ideal ‘value’†
TIMBER AND TABLES |
LABOUR AND VALUE |
---|---|
We begin by a simplifying abstraction and reduce (e.g.) ‘tables’ to a material substance that they have in common, timber; we consider this as a ‘moment’ of tables. |
We begin by a simplifying abstraction and reduce ‘value’ to a social substance that entities of value have in common, labour; we consider this as a ‘moment’ of value. |
‘Timber’: substance of tables. Introversive moment for the constitution of tables. |
‘Labour’: substance of value. Introversive moment for the constitution of value. |
Tables are not timber as such. (Further: considering timber under the aspect of length does not imply that ‘length of timber’ is the measure for tables.) |
Value is not labour as such. (Further: considering labour under the aspect of time (labour-time) does not imply that ‘labour-time’ is the measure of value.) |
The length of timber is a quality necessary for the being of tables – at least provisionally.* |
The time of labour is a quality necessary for the being of value – at least provisionally.* |
‘Tables’ (at the level of abstraction reached so far): tables are constituted by an introversive moment of substance (timber) and an extroversive moment of form (actually: the creative material act of making). |
‘Value’ (at the level of abstraction reached so far): value is constituted by an introversive moment of substance (labour) and an extroversive moment of form (actually: ideal commensuration by money). |
All tables have timber in common – at least provisionally (i.e., at the current level of abstraction*); but they are not fully constituted by timber. |
All value has labour in common, at least provisionally (i.e., at the current level of abstraction*); but it is not fully constituted by labour. |
‘Tables’ are material realities. (In principle tables can be trans-historical material realities.) |
‘Value’ is an ideal reality. (Moreover, it is a social-historical ideal reality.) |
* Provisionally: we can have plastic tables. |
* Provisionally: the form allows for an extroversive hypostasisation – value without labour substance (see §3.4 below). |
Once we have reached beyond the early simplification it makes no sense to measure conceptually enriched tables by measuring length of timber: length of tables ≠ length of timber |
Once we have reached beyond the early simplification it makes no sense to measure conceptually enriched value by measuring time of labour: quantity of value ≠ time of labour (value ≠ abstract labour-time) |
† |
I do not want to suggest that Column 1 sets out the appropriate way for knowing what tables are, and how they should be measured; the message is that inasmuch as it makes no sense to measure the length of fully constituted tables by the timber, it makes no sense to measure value by labour-time. |
2.2 Immanent substance and immanent measure: abstract labour and method
We saw that money is the necessary expression of value: only with money do we arrive at the extroversive form of immanent substance: that is, the determinate ‘being’ of commodities. There cannot be a privileging of the one over the other (analogously: when we consider a specific table there is no point in privileging the ‘introversive’ timber and nails over the ‘extroversive’ creative act of formation of that table or vice versa; the one without the other is not-table – see Table 1 on p. 143). In other words, ‘value’ and the ‘commodity’ are not fully constituted in Chapter 1: they are merely as an initiating simplification.
Marx’s method is one of conceptual progression from simple to complex determinations. In the case at hand Chapter 1 establishes introversive notions of the commodity; at that level of the presentation the commodity has no determinate existence, but rather ‘prevalence’ (Dasein). The commodity of simple circulation is fully posited only with its extroversive notions in Chapter 3 (completing Part One).
Marx’s immanent measure of value in Chapter 1 – time of ‘abstract labour’ – is very abstract. It does not provide a measure of value in the sense that we (nowadays) usually use the term measure. Many commentators have brushed away this problem by identifying value and ‘abstract labour time’!14 ‘Abstract labour’ cannot be measured (in terms of time) with more sense than a table’s timber as abstracted from, for example, anything but its length. But for the latter this does not provide the full constitution of a table (merely substance); for the former this does not constitute value (merely substance).
I use the term ‘very abstract labour’ because in the literature on Marx, or developments from his work, the term ‘abstract labour’ has become somewhat worn out: it seems often identified with a quantitative part of concrete(!) labour: (1) producing at average conditions of production (hence, it is said, ‘necessary’); (2) for the product of which there is demand (hence, it is said, ‘necessary’); (3) that contributes to production in a particular sense, or ‘productive’ labour (hence, it is said, ‘necessary’). These issues can be announced; however, there is no way of knowing them or measuring them prior to the market. Thus abstract labour has no determinate existence. Abstract labour has a dimension of time but, paradoxically, it cannot be measured unless we assume that abstract labour equals concrete labour (thus abstract from abstract labour).
Rather, value is fully constituted only when we have money; money in the market measures ‘abstract labour’ and so determines ‘abstract labour’ so to speak; however (!), at this point the term ‘abstract labour’ is superfluous: we have value. (Of course, it may be added, ‘value’ itself is an abstraction in practice.)
The notion of very abstract labour implies that Chapter 1 does not present a ‘labour theory of value’ (a term not used by Marx) in any quantifiable sense. From this again derives the conclusion that abstract labour, a fortiori, cannot be quantitatively implanted into lower levels of abstraction (and – to repeat – Marx does not do this).
The warning regarding the Chapter 1 notions of value and labour also applies to ‘money’ within Chapter 3. It seems that for Marx a thing’s ‘being’ the measure of value (Section 1) and its being the means of circulation (Section 2), constitutes it as being money. The heading of Section 3 is: ‘Money’. It means that only in that section money becomes constituted (though simple). This gives rise to a considerable language problem (as always in systematic dialectics) of how to talk about the entity prior to it (i.e., without running into artificial language). In the first two sections of Chapter 3 Marx often uses the term ‘gold’, but frequently also ‘money’ even if money has not yet been fully constituted – merely a simplified constituent.
Of course, this problem applies to ‘capital’ in all of Capital. Each time (section, chapter, part, volume) we are further introduced into it. It is misleading to think of any early presentation as ‘truth’; it is also misleading to cite it in that way. Until the completion it is always partial (“the whole is the truth”, wrote Hegel).
3 Money’s measuring: ideal transubstantiation
3.1 Idealities
In this section I expand on the core of Chapter 3: ‘money’s measuring’. I begin with a fairly long quotation from early on in the chapter, which I take to be programmatic. It shows, first, that the value of an entity is a purely ideal form of its existence (this denies ontologically real ‘embodiment’); second, the measurement in terms of money (gold) is an ideal act: it is performed through an imaginary equalisation with money (gold); third, as a result the second performance can be established by imaginary money. I amplify on the first two issues in §3.2 and on the third in §3.3.
The price or money-form of commodities is, like their form of value generally [wie ihre Wertform überhaupt] quite distinct from their palpable and real bodily form; it is therefore a purely ideal or notional form [nur ideelle oder vorgestellte Form – ‘vorgestellte’, i.e., ‘imagined’]. Although invisible, the value of iron, linen and corn exists in these very articles [Dingen]: it is signified [vorgestellt, i.e., ‘imagined’] through their equality with gold, even though this relation with gold exists only in their heads, so to speak [ihre Gleichheit mit Gold, eine Beziehung zum Gold, die sozusagen nur in ihren Köpfen spukt, i.e., their equality with gold, a relation to gold, even though this only haunts their heads, so to speak]. The guardian of the commodities must therefore lend them his tongue, or hang a ticket on them, in order to communicate their prices to the outside world. Since the expression of the value of commodities in gold is a purely ideal act [ideelles], we may use purely imaginary [nur vorgestelltes] or ideal gold to perform this operation … In its function as measure of value, money therefore serves only in an imaginary or ideal capacity [als nur vorgestelltes oder ideelles Geld, i.e., as merely imaginary or ideal money]. (1867F: 189–90; 1867G: 110–11; emphasis added)15
3.2 Marx’s notion of ‘measurement’: ‘verwandlen’ and standardised measurement
When Marx refers to money’s measurement, he refers to an abstract genus. This is a problem for us. In everyday language and practice money is so much an (‘imagined’) concrete entity, that we tend to immediately give it the content of our particular money – the North Americans think of their dollars, many Europeans of euros, and so on. ‘Money’, however, is the abstract general of these. This is a main difficulty of Chapter 3. If this is not grasped then Marx’s distinction between measure of value and standard of price becomes a superficial one.16 Marx points this out, but not clearly enough. It is important to stress this because it underlines the conceptual progress made in Chapter 3.
Usually when we think of a measure we think of a standard. However, when Marx says ‘money measures value’ he means that it establishes the commensuration (i.e., homogenisation).17 That is to say, the value-form determination is concretised as money measure. On the other hand, the ‘taking measure’ (and ticketing) of the value of a commodity is established in terms of a standard of price. The distinction between this ‘measurement in general’ and the specific ‘taking measure’ by way of a particular standard is most important. (Marx’s terminology might seem idiosyncratic in current language. However, in Hegel’s Logic (both its versions) we have a similar usage of the term ‘measure’. In hindsight this also sheds light on Marx’s usage of ‘immanent measure’ for the Chapter 1 moment of value.)
As the measure of value it [money] serves to convert [verwandeln, transform] the values of all the manifold commodities into prices, into imaginary quantities of gold {that is, money in general}; as the standard of price it [money] … measures, on the contrary, quantities of gold by a unit quantity of gold [Goldquantum]. (1867F: 192; 1867G: 113; emphasis added)18
The second phrase, about the standard, specifies a unit (quantum) for the measurement of the quantity in the first phrase. For the second phrase we can use the analogy of (say) length measurement: as a standard of length a particular rod (named metre or yard) measures ‘entities of length’ by a unit of length (one metre or one yard). As the standard of price, some particular money (named dollar or euro) measures quantities of money (a pile of notes or coins) by a unit of price (one dollar or one euro).
For the first phrase, as already indicated (§2.1), the analogy would be false. Prior to the measurement we have ‘entities of length’ (such as tables). For the commodities, prior to the measurement, we merely have the ‘introversive substance’, which is a purely ideal or imagined introversive substance (cf. the quote in §3.1).19
The act of measurement by money (i.e., prior to the actual exchange) ideally ‘transubstantiates’ commodities into form-determined entities and hence commensurate or homogeneous (cf. the quotation from 1867F: 192 given above). This is like a miracle. But just as most Catholics that go to church every week or perhaps every day may not be very attentive any more to the miraculousness of the (ideal) transformation of bread and wine into the body of Christ, we are, when we mundanely buy our daily bread, usually not very attentive to the miraculous ideal transubstantiation as performed by the lady in the baker’s shop.
This transubstantiation in reference to the Catholic celebration is one connotation of the German term Verwandlung (and its verb verwandeln). Transformation and to transform is perhaps the preferable translation (unfortunately, it is not consistently adopted). Thus money’s measurement per-forms the value-homogeneity of commodities. Or we could also say: money turns the hopelessly abstract immanent notion of ‘abstract labour’ into extroversive form, and therewith into a potential concretum (concretum, that is when the salto mortale is completed into the metamorphosis C–M). Without this ‘measurement überhaupt’, standards of price (or standards of value) make no sense.
Thus value is, in both its constituents (introversive and extroversive), imaginary or ideality. Although it is beyond the subject of this chapter, I should add that ideality can have real effect. In this case this is – as far as I am concerned – the point. (See Murray 2000b and 2004 on subsumption.)
3.3 Imaginary measurement by imaginary money
I now turn to the third aspect of the ‘programmatic’ quotation (§3.1). If we restrict the discussion (as I have done so far) to money as measure of value, Marx goes as far as one could go in the commodity-money based monetary regime of his day (though see §4) that is, within the restriction – much emphasised by Campbell 1997 – of simple commodity circulation, namely, prior to the introduction of capital into the presentation, and hence prior to the introduction of money as finance. In hindsight it is easy (but a-historical) to criticise almost all of monetary theory prior to, say, 1973 for allotting a major role to metal in the top of the money pyramid.
If we compare the current ‘pure credit-money’ regime with a ‘pure commodity money’ regime the crucial step is not the demise of the Bretton Woods regime (the controlled international gold–dollar standard); the latter is the tail. Crucial is the (national) irredeemability of banknotes and the prevalence of ‘money of account’ at all: imaginary money (cf. Marx’s treatment of money of account in Section 3 of Chapter 3).20 Thus the ideal or imaginary Verwandlung is accomplished by ideal or imaginary money (or – from a perspective of pure credit-money – by nominal money).
3.4 Extroversive hypostasisation
One culmination of Marx’s treatment of money as measure is the ‘imaginary measurement by imaginary money’ mentioned above. A second one is the hypostasisation of money as extroversive measure, whence entities (as including insensuous ones) can take the price-form without having value (196).
The possibility … of a quantitative incongruity between price and magnitude of value … is inherent in the price-form itself. This is not a defect, but, on the contrary, it makes this form the adequate one for a mode of production whose laws can only assert themselves as blindly operating averages between constant irregularities. (196)
However, the possibility of incongruity may go further than these irregularities. Marieken, Faust or a modern business manager can sell their souls. With the money they can buy indulgences or ‘goodwill’:
Things which in and for themselves are not commodities, things such as conscience, honour, etc., can formally speaking, have a price without having a value. (197)
Whereas in their simplicity the introversive determinations of Chapter 1 are necessary – as Marx frequently repeats – the extroversive determinations are equally necessary. However, because it is inherent to the latter that these do not stick to the former, the extroversive measure hypostases.
The upshot is a shift in the connection between the Chapter 1 ‘simple value’ and the Chapter 3 price constituting ‘value’. Whilst money necessarily measures value, it can also measure nullities.
4 An introversive regress: bullion
The weakness of Marx’s presentation dated 1867 (18904) is not at all, in my view, that he starts his account of money as measure with commodity money: the development of money of account from it is fine. The weakness is rather that when he gets to the final subsection of the chapter, ‘World Money’, he makes the impression of presenting the empirical prevalence of ‘world money’ in the shape of gold/silver (especially for settling international payments) as an argument for his starting point in commodity money. And instead of theorising that prevalence, he just describes it: money “falls back into its original form as precious metal in the shape of bullion” (240). What is more, he explicitly presents a regression to Chapter 1:
In the world market … money functions to its full extent as the commodity whose natural form is also the directly [unmittelbar, i.e., immediate] social form of realisation [Verwirklichungsform, i.e., form of actualisation] of human labour in the abstract. (1867F: 240–1; 1867G: 156 – underlining added)
Quite aside from my methodological critique above, this quotation provides a textual confirmation of the main thesis of this chapter about the relation between Chapters 1 and 3, including the ex ante immeasurability of abstract labour (in the usual sense of measurement). By itself abstract labour is not actual. Note first that we have here one of the two occurrences of ‘abstract labour’ in this chapter (and in all of the 2,000 pages to come there is just one recurrence). Note also that the two corrections in the translation above are crucial. ‘Immediateness’ refers to an abstract, yet underdeveloped or defective account. ‘Realisation’ in this context is most confusing, as in some Marxian accounts the term refers to ‘sale’. Instead, Marx says, bullion is being the immediate form of human labour in the abstract. Directly following the text just quoted Marx writes: “Its mode of existence [seine Daseinsweise] becomes adequate to its concept.” Mere Dasein is another reference to defectiveness. Thus bullion is the immediate form of abstract labour. I add: bullion itself.
Thus the Chapter 1 ‘abstract labour’ is only mediately measurable – we necessarily require money: money measures abstract labour. The one exception to this necessary mediation (in 1867) is the labour producing the commodity ‘bullion’; because bullion as world money functions as general means of payment and general means of purchase, we have an immediate social form of actualisation of abstract labour. (Today, of course, there is no exception.)
Summary and Conclusions
Value constitutes the historically specific social form of production in capitalist societies. Part One of Capital I introduces the concept of value by way of an analysis and synthesis of simple commodity circulation: that is, commodity circulation in abstraction from capital, the production of capital and the development of the circuit of capital (the subject – briefly – of the remainder of the work).
Although this social form has real (ontological) effect in shaping the material production in capitalist societies, it is an ideal form in the sense that it is insensuously permutated to entities and processes. It has sensuous existence only in money and artefacts of accounting, themselves physically separate from those entities and processes, although utterly meaningless without the latter.
In the interpretation of Part One of Capital I set out here, the ideal immanent (or introversive) substance of the value of commodities is ‘abstract labour’ (sic). Its qualitative measure (i.e., the immanent measure of value) is ‘time’ of abstract labour. This is what I called the simple-abstract notion of value (of Chapter 1). It is defective and it has no real ideal existence (no ideal existence in practice).
This simple notion is complemented in Chapter 3 by the ideal extroversive form of the value of commodities: money. It is only henceforth that ‘value’ has been fully constituted. Money establishes the actual homogeneity of commodities and is the only one actual ideal measure of value (adopting a particular standard).
The introversive substance and the extroversive form of value are inseparable. Value cannot be concretely measured without money; any effort to do so comes down to a Ricardian ‘timber-nail tale’ of measurement. However, we have seen that this inseparability is not symmetrical: money can measure, and purchase, nullities.
Once we are past Chapter 3, any talk in terms of abstract-labour(-time) is a regress to a simplification – i.e., simple or underdetermined value. Marx, though, does not make this mistake.
The first version of this chapter was presented at the 2003 conference of the International Symposium on Marxian Theory. I am grateful for the comments by its participants (Christopher Arthur, Riccardo Bellofiore, Suzanne de Brunhoff, Martha Campbell, Duncan Foley, Claus Germer, Makoto Itoh, Costas Lapavitsas, Pichit Likitkijsomboon, Fred Moseley, Patrick Murray, Anitra Nelson, and Tony Smith).
It is obvious that a Marxian theory of pure credit-money can be constructed. See Williams (2000), Realfonzo and Bellofiore (1996), Bellofiore and Realfonzo (1997), Bellofiore (2004); see also Reuten and Williams (1989: Chapter 2 and Chapter 8, §4). However, pure credit-money cannot be introduced early on in Capital: an implantation of the stuff of Capital III, Parts Four and Five early on in Capital I would demolish the complete systematic structure of the work, and hence it would require a complete reconstruction (although there is also a class of reconstruction that does not affect the systematic structure of the work). Even if Marx had introduced money as finance early on in Capital I (say after Part Two) he still would have had to present a general account of money earlier, and it is this general account of Part I that I am concerned with in the rest of this chapter.
Campbell (1997, 1998, 2002). See also Williams (2000).
In previous work (esp. Reuten 1989, 1993 and 2000) I suggested that whereas Marx made a fundamental ‘break’ from Classical Political Economy there are (inevitably) Classical/Ricardian remnants in his work. (See Murray’s 2000a critique of my 1993 paper, my reply (2000), and Murray’s rejoinder in 2002). A restudy of a number of German texts of Capital (together with insights from Hegel’s work) makes me conclude that there are fewer such remnants than I thought before. See Reuten (2004), which, next to the current chapter, is a key to this. [For the 2004 article see Chapter 8 of the current book.]
Chapter 2 – prior to the introduction of capital in Chapter 4 – nevertheless posits an anticipation of dissociated production.
Translation necessarily involves interpretation. Translators are confined to rely on the common interpretation of their day, and therefore a novel interpretation must have consequences for the translation.
My thoughts are intuitive without expressing them. My face is that due to its expression; when my skin has been injured by fire, my face is still my face, and yet not. It seems to me that the innere-äußere opposition is in between:
internal – external (inadequate because of its ‘exogenous’ connotation)
impressive – expressive
introversive – extroversive
implosive – explosive (if we could cut their connotations of destruction).
For Hegel especially, inward–outward would have to be added. Marx evades innere in the current context (he uses it in Capital I, Part Seven), and adopts instead ‘immanent’ (immanent). Henceforth I adopt the terms of immanent/introversive and extroversive.
Value’s monetary dimension does not imply that it only exists in monetary shape. Entities in capitalism (e.g. machines) may have a value of monetary dimension without being money. Equally things may be of monetary dimension (e.g. machines as functioning means of production) without having a price: things have a price only when they are offered for sale. Within the circuit of capital M–Ci…P…Cj’–M’ the Ci…P…Cj’ is ideally accounted in monetary dimension. This ideality may be exciting (as it should be) but it is not surprising. Every businessman, accountant or auditor knows that most of the balance sheet of an enterprise is made up in terms of an ideal monetary dimension (the balance sheet is a static version of the circuit of capital).
See also Arthur’s excellent study (2004, pp. 36–8). He writes: “to be a commodity involves all the determinations of chapter 1, including those of Section 3 on its form, in which it is shown that an adequate expression of the value of commodities requires the existence of money”. See also Arthur 2005. The notion that value has no existence without money is also key to Murray 2005 although he arrives at this from a different angle from the one proposed in the current chapter. Elson 1979 is an inspiration for the research reported in the current chapter. “Marx’s examples”, she wrote, “are always couched in money terms, never in terms of hours” (p. 139). In fact the same applies for Marx’s equations (Reuten 2004). Elson notes that “values cannot be calculated or observed independently of prices” but she also thought that “in Capital Marx does not highlight the conceptual distinction which he makes between an ‘immanent’ or ‘intrinsic’ measure, and an ‘external’ measure, which is the mode of appearance of the ‘immanent’ measure” (1979, p. 136). In fact the German text is rather explicit. With her “Marx does not highlight the conceptual distinction which he makes”, she showed great intuition.
Without helping us by saying what he is doing.
Its length in metres does not exist independently of the stick (or rather the metric system), but that is not my point here.
I still think that it is to the point to conceive of ‘abstract labour’ as a foreshadow of money (as I did in previous work). But this notion has proved to be confusing in debates with those labour-embodied proponents who think in terms of ‘abstract-labour-embodied’ and from which I distance myself (see Reuten 1993 [chapter 6 of the current book]). In previous work I adopted for abstract labour the composite mL (where m is the monetary expression of labour; and L in fact added-up concrete labour). As an interpretation of Marx this is wrong. (At least it is wrong to use Marx’s term abstract labour for mL; mL is value-added which is a more concrete notion.) After the initiating Chapter 1 this notion (and the term) ‘abstract labour’ is superseded and should not be used any more.
In my view many, if not most, of the problems for the interpretation of Chapter 1 have to do with the difference between abstract and concrete labour. Capital was not written (Marx thought) for philosophically educated readers. The meaning of ‘abstract labour’ is not easy. In the course of explaining it, Marx, I think, felt constrained to take recourse to all kinds of non-rigorous approximations, analogies and examples. However, these are overcome section-wise. Once the later section is comprehended it makes no sense to phrase that non-rigorously. (Didactics may require one to explain the mathematical notion of fraction by example of a cake. It is expected that when we get to fractional exponential growth, the thinking in terms of cakes is past.)
To my knowledge ‘abstract labour’ is further used: once in Chapter 2, twice in Chapter 3 (1867F: 209, 240) and once in Chapter 8 (1867F: 308) (German edition Chapter 6), all in Volume I. There are no occurrences in Volumes II or III. There is also an occurrence in the Results (1867F: 992–3).
Relatedly the term labour as ‘substance’ disappears after Chapter 3. There are two exceptions for Volume I: 18 (672), 23 (715); one exception for Volume II: 19 (462); four exceptions for Volume III: 8 (248), 48 (961, 964, 968) (references are by chapter and page number of the English texts in the Fowkes/Fernbach translation).
The term ‘homogeneous labour’ equally disappears after Chapter 3 (without exception to my knowledge).
See also Reuten (1999).
Fowkes misses the qualification of ‘equality’ into ‘relation’. His suppression of the ‘haunting’ (spukt) is an obvious intervention in the text. It is also not clear why Fowkes is not consistent about ‘imaginary’/‘imagined’ where Marx is consistent about it (vorgestellt).
The ‘standard of price’ may be some (nominal) quantum of gold when a commodity money regime prevails, or a specific nominal accounting unit (dollar, euro) when a regime of pure credit-money prevails (as after the Bretton Woods demise of the mid-1970s). Standards of price are linked in their exchange rates.
A homogenisation that is foreshadowed in the term ‘abstract labour’. But this is not a homogenisation: it is a (very) abstract notion.
My interpolations in square brackets derive directly from the (German) text; interpolations in curly brackets are interpretative.
Note again that Marx, of course, departs from the Chapter 1 ‘immanent value’ – a notion that is now, with the extroversion, transformed into a more concrete concept of value.
I use this term ‘substance’ because Marx uses it. But even when prefixed by ‘purely ideal’ the term risks giving rise to notions of ‘embodiment’ (expanded upon in Reuten 1993) [Chapter 6 of the current book].
In this context Marx’s ‘inverse quantity theory of money’ is important (the quantity of money is determined by the price level).
References
Superscripts indicate first and other relevant editions; the last mentioned year in the bibliography is the edition cited.
Arthur, Christopher J. 2004, ‘Money and the form of value’, in Bellofiore and Taylor (eds 2004), pp. 35–62.
Arthur, Christopher J. 2005, ‘Value and money’, in Moseley (ed.) 2005, pp. 111–23.
Arthur, Christopher J., and Geert Reuten (eds) 1998, The circulation of capital: essays on volume II of Marx’s ‘Capital’, London: Macmillan.
Bellofiore, Riccardo 2004, ‘Marx and the macro-monetary foundation of microeconomics’, in Bellofiore and Taylor (eds) 2004, pp. 170–210.
Bellofiore, Riccardo 2005, ‘The monetary aspects of the capitalist process in the Marxian system: an investigation from the point of view of the theory of the monetary circuit’, in Moseley (ed.) 2005, pp. 124–42.
Bellofiore, Riccardo, and Riccardo Realfonzo 1997, ‘Finance and the labour theory of value: toward a macroeconomic theory of distribution from a monetary perspective’, International Journal of Political Economy, 27/2.
Bellofiore, Riccardo, and Nicola Taylor (eds) 2004, The constitution of capital: essays on volume I of Marx’s ‘Capital’, London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Campbell, Martha 1997, ‘Marx’s theory of money: a defense’, in Moseley and Campbell (eds) 1997, pp. 89–120.
Campbell, Martha 1998, ‘Money in the circulation of capital’, in Arthur and Reuten (eds) 1998, pp. 129–58.
Campbell, Martha 2002, ‘The credit system’, in Campbell and Reuten (eds) 2002, pp. 212–27.
Campbell, Martha, and Geert Reuten (eds) 2002, The culmination of capital: essays on volume III of Marx’s ‘Capital’, London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Elson, Diane 1979, ‘The value theory of labour’, in Value: the representation of labour in capitalism, edited by Diane Elson, London: CSE Books.
Marx, Karl 18671G/18904, Das Kapital, Kritik der politischen Ökonomie, Band I, Der Produktionsprozeß des Kapitals, MEW 23, Berlin: Dietz Verlag, 1973.
Marx, Karl 18671F/18904, Capital, a critique of political economy, volume I, trans. of the 4th German ed. by Ben Fowkes, Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1976.
Moseley, Fred, and Martha Campbell (eds) 1997, New investigations of Marx’s method, Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press.
Moseley, Fred (ed.) 2005, Marx’s theory of money: modern appraisals, London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Murray, Patrick 2000a, ‘Marx’s “truly social” labour theory of value: abstract labour in Marxian value theory (part one)’, Historical Materialism 6: 27–66.
Murray, Patrick 2000b, ‘Marx’s “truly social” labour theory of value: abstract labour in Marxian value theory (part two)’, Historical Materialism 7: 99–136.
Murray, Patrick 2002, ‘Reply to Geert Reuten’, Historical Materialism 10.1: 155–76.
Murray, Patrick 2004, ‘The social and material transformation of production by capital: formal and real subsumption in “Capital volume I”’, in Bellofiore and Taylor (eds) 2004, pp. 243–73.
Murray, Patrick 2005, ‘Money as displaced social form: why value cannot be independent of price’, in Moseley (ed.) 2005, pp. 50–64.
Realfonzo, Riccardo, and Riccardo Bellofiore 1996, ‘Marx and money’, Trimestre 29/1–2: 189–212.
Reuten, Geert 1988, ‘Value as social form’, in Value, social form and the state, edited by Michael Williams, London: Macmillan, pp. 42–61.
Reuten, Geert 1993, ‘The difficult labour of a theory of social value: metaphors and systematic dialectics at the beginning of Marx’s Capital’, in Marx’s method in Capital: a re-examination, edited by Fred Moseley, Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, pp. 89–113.
Reuten, Geert 1999, ‘The source versus measure obstacle in value theory’, Rivista di Politica Economica 89/4–5: 87–115.
Reuten, Geert 2000, ‘The interconnection of systematic dialectics and historical materialism’, Historical Materialism 7: 137–66.
Reuten, Geert 2004, ‘Productive force and the degree of intensity of labour’, in Bellofiore and Taylor (eds) 2004, pp. 117–45.
Reuten, Geert, and Michael Williams 1989, Value-form and the state; the tendencies of accumulation and the determination of economic policy in capitalist society, London: Routledge.
Williams, Michael 2000, ‘Why Marx neither has nor needs a commodity theory of money’, Review of Political Economy 12/4: 435–51.