Chapter 9 Women Sages in Male Epistemic Spaces – an Analysis of Patriarchal Forces in Female Knowledge Production

In: Knowing - Unknowing
Authors:
Anthony Okeregbe
Search for other papers by Anthony Okeregbe in
Current site
Google Scholar
PubMed
Close
and
Muyiwa Falaiye
Search for other papers by Muyiwa Falaiye in
Current site
Google Scholar
PubMed
Close

1 Introduction

Ever since the late African philosopher, Odera Oruka, put forward his concept of philosophic sagacity as an authentic African philosophy (Oruka 1983, 1990), widespread discussion on this position has given it such authority that it is proposed as one of the most reliable sources of African knowledges (Mosima 2016). Perhaps owing to the influence of Paul Radin (1927) and his gender-restrictive reference to “man” in the discovery of African knowledges, Oruka and his followers, save for one female sage, Peris Njuhi Muthoni, seem to have excluded women from the category of sages (Presbey 2021: 2).

Thus, despite the possible existence of many female powerhouses of wisdom in Africa, and despite the global push for equal opportunities and recognition for women, the sage philosophy project is still predominantly chauvinistic. Though some recent works in African philosophy are interrogating the marginalization of women in African intellectual history (Chimakonam 2018; Matolino 2018) and the possibility of feminizing epistemologies in African gender studies (Amadiume 2005; Marcano 2010; Oyewùmí 2011), the generation, documentation and analysis of a corpus on female sages has yet to gain serious academic attention. A few works have expressed the possibility of an inclusive sagacity project that involves female sages in knowledge production and ideation (Mosima 2018; Presbey 2000, 2012, 2018, 2021). However, a fundamental shortcoming in these works is the lack of empirical data on the life and times, influences and reflective corpus of ideas and wisdom creditable to such female sages. Thus, the female sage is still significantly marginalized in a predominantly male-dominated space of indigenous knowledges.

The project on which this paper is based sets out to explore the nature and value of feminine wisdom in an agenda-setting manner, seeking to investigate the possibility of women sages, the nature and content of the form of knowledge they produce and the value of such knowledges to contemporary Africa and the world at large. The research also unpacks the multiple ways of knowledge production, characterization, transmission and recognition through heuristic investigation of the epistemic agency of female sages, until now ignored in the documentation of indigenous knowledges. Since ideas, knowledges and wisdom are purveyors of civilization and societal development, reconfiguring the scales of indigenous knowledges and wisdom through female agency is pivotal in holistically deploying indigenous knowledges, practices and wisdom to expand Africa’s epistemic space.

The research is significant because, by investigating women’s epistemic powers and feminine wisdom, it counterbalances the privileged masculinity accorded to the epistemic enterprise and promises to provide another perspective to the male-dominated production, management and dissemination system of indigenous knowledges in Africa. In this way, this chapter contributes to the literature on feminism, gender studies and related fields. Drawing insight from Pius Mosima’s (2016–2018) critical postmodernist analysis of philosophic sagacity, this chapter maintains that Oruka’s sage philosophy project is founded on a hegemonic Western ratio socially situated in a patriarchal cultural setting. As a result, it does not accommodate female epistemic agents as candidates for philosophic sagacity.

Oruka’s Sage Philosophy Project leaves open gaps in the articulation of what wisdom entails and who is wise. Although he insisted that being a philosopher and being wise were mutually exclusive, he made ratiocination (as abstract reasoning) a condition for philosophic sagacity. Furthermore, notwithstanding his submission on candidates for philosophic sagacity, there seems to have been a deliberate exclusion of female agency in the entire project as Presbey rightly observed (Presbey 2012: 117). A gender-sensitive reading of the mechanics of the project reveals that “all named student assistants are male (Oruka 1991: Acknowledgements). Of 12 sages whose interviews are quoted at length in the book Sage Philosophy (1991), only one is a woman. In an earlier part of the book, where Odera Oruka gives brief excerpts of interviews with eight sages, all these are also men (Oruka 1991: 37–40). Nine sages asked about equality of the sexes were all men (Presbey 2012: 117). We wonder if this seemingly embarrassing oversights are not premeditated or rooted in the masculinist mindset to pave way for a position that both panders to the philosophical tradition of a colonial knowledge system and entrenches a patriarchal epistemic order.

In spite of the oversights, we agree with Oruka not only that philosophy should be sought in sagacity but also that what sagacity entails should not be dictated in advance. We hold that the concept of women as sages is rooted in the idea that women have a unique and valuable perspective on the world that has been historically overlooked and undervalued, albeit by agencies of patriarchy and colonial heritage. What informs this position is our assumption that since wisdom pertains to practical understanding of quotidian dealings, sagacious knowledge “is not esoteric, for it is within everyone’s reach; nor does it require a special skill or talent (Kekes 1983: 280). Furthermore, in view of the fact that phronesis, a Greek term which translates as “practical understanding” or “prudence in everyday dealings”, is a veritable correlate of wisdom, this paper argues that female sages indeed exist in contemporary African societies.

In furthering the reflection for this chapter, two assumptions foreground our conceptualization of knowledge. One is the philosophy of difference, a fundamental principle of which is the engagement with marginal issues in mainstream philosophical traditions, examination of constitutive exclusions and appraisal of deviations from the hegemonic norm in philosophical scholarship (Imafidon 2020). The other assumption contemplates the ontogenesis of knowledge from the postmodern theorizing in Deleuze and Guattari’s rhizome epistemological model, which envisions theories and research works that allow for multiple, non-hierarchical entry and exit points in data representation and interpretation (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 6–10). It also adopts the neo-African epistemic temperament of insurgent and resurgent decolonization (Ndlovu-Gatsheni 2018, 2021). Methodologically, it adopts an African phenomenological approach (Olivier, Lamola and Sands 2023), which studies the phenomena of African lived experiences by letting the expressions of these women’s lived experiences be “seen” in the way they are.

In light of these assumptions, knowledges cannot be conceptualized in advance because knowledge can take any form in so far as it is an individual’s description of a reality experienced or witnessed, a proposition of an idea emanating from one’s interiority, or an expression of an embedded feeling or culturally transmitted mentality. By decentring the canons of philosophic knowledge that arise from colonial intellectual heritage, namely the thinking that knowledge could be acquired only through rational inquiry from the colonial library, this chapter calls for unthinking the ways in which Africa has been constructed and represented in the past, and creating new ways of knowing Africa from the inside out (Okeregbe 2018; Hountondji 2009). In this way, it not only “shows that studying knowledge and forms of knowing implies exploring forms of unknowing and ignorance” (Hoeyer and Winthereik 2022: 217) but also that thinking shifts with new experiences, new encounters and new awakenings. Thus, this chapter resonates with the theme “thinking as moving”, by translocating the context of female epistemic agency from the imperial citadel of the colonial academe to the self-created sphere of ownness of the African woman.

This work contributes to feminism, gender studies and related fields by challenging female epistemic marginalization, creating a space for women’s voices to be heard and valued in the creation of knowledge. By centring the experiences and perspectives of women, and by availing space for women to express their thoughts about their experiences in all their rawness and modest authenticity, this chapter aims to create a more inclusive and just epistemic regime.

2 Field Trip Findings

Adopting a similar (not necessarily identical) research approach to the one used by Oruka in carrying out his Sage Philosophy Project, we purposively made the six geopolitical zones of Nigeria our research area. These zones are the North West, North Central, North East, South West, South South and South East. We thereafter randomly selected communities in each of these six geopolitical zones from which female sages could be identified. We further built on this mapping process by carrying out surveys and interviews in these locations with the aim of identifying female sages across certain age brackets. Importantly, the choice of the six geopolitical zones in modern day Nigeria was to discover and advance the multiplicity and relationality of knowledges among female sages, knowing that these zones may not be culturally homogenous. We restricted the age bracket (to 50 and 80) to ensure that respondents had not been influenced by formal school education, among other influences. This transethnic cultural survey, which formed the primary method of data gathering, was necessary to provide content to the research, even as it expressed the multiple nature of knowledge.

For even distribution, nine to 12 randomly selected respondents from each of the six geopolitical zones were interviewed. A provincial state was also randomly selected from a geopolitical zone, and three communities were isolated in that provincial state for the study. In each of these three communities, three to four respondents were interviewed. In all, 66 potential female sages were interviewed individually, using open ended questions for critical conversation. They reflected multiplicity and diversity in terms of the sampled local government areas (LGA s), religious orientation, age grade, educational status, professions and roles in the community. Although the respondents were chosen based on community recommendations, their availability and their interest in participating in the project, the team experienced serious resistance from some members of the communities and some of the identified potential female sages, who expressed concerns about exploitation.1 Since knowledge production presupposes some relationship between the researcher and the researched, the notion of positionality (namely, indicators of contexts and relational locations such as nationality, race, class, education, epistemological perspectives and philosophical orientations) is a consideration in the value accorded the knowledge produced (Anyidoho 2008: 28). Often, there is the misunderstanding (emanating from past anthropological research works) that field research borders on extractivism, and thus researchers are seen as harvesters of encrypted knowledge of some cults or secret societies. Because our research project interviewed mainly elderly women, there was the tendency to think that way too. However, when we explained our motivations for the project, the respondents became favourably disposed towards it.

Given the political situation in certain parts of the country, the women had to be constantly reassured that this project was purely academic in nature and would not be used for political purposes. In one provincial state, the political tension in some communities was so intense that we were asked to remove our facemasks while moving around, to avoid drawing attention. This was shortly after the Covid-19 pandemic lockdown, and the ban had been lifted in some states on the wearing of facemasks. Apparently, like other areas far from the state capital, this town paid little heed to wearing a mask. Thus, our masked appearance gave us away as “outsiders”.

The administration of the consent procedures before the interview sessions, difficult as it was in some instances, allayed concerns and fears over exploitation, and the prima facie lack of trust in “strangers” seeking indigenous knowledge from the “natives”. Besides, when they realized that we were seeking women’s perspectives on being and existence for academic and educational purposes, some connection was established. For the fieldwork, the principal investigator worked with a female research assistant, and both were accompanied by two pre-established field assistants (one of whom had to be female) who also acted as translators in some cases. The gender balance created an auspicious environment for interviews of this nature to run smoothly. Largely, the respondents spoke in their native language, but in communities where language posed a barrier in communication, the researchers relied on the translators. After a series of focus group discussions, the number of sages was pruned to nine.

3 Criteria for Sagacity

Odera Oruka, who made the ambitious project of Sage Philosophy Project his life-long contribution to the global philosophical enterprise, set out to show that the problem of the traditional African was not that of abstraction, logic and scientific inquiry and that written literature was not a condition for authentic African philosophy. He premised his justification for authentic African philosophy by arguing that within the ambit of communal philosophizing, there was the possibility of individual reflection. He argued:

Some sages go beyond mere sagacity and attain philosophic capacity. As sages they are versed in the beliefs and wisdoms of their people. But as thinkers, they are rationally critical and they opt for or recommend only those aspects of their beliefs and wisdoms which satisfy their rational scrutiny. In this respect they are potentially or contemporarily in clash with the diehard adherents of prevailing common belief.

ORUKA 1991: 51

By referring to “some sages” Oruka meant sages whose intellectual activities did not qualify as philosophic sagacity. Sages in this category appear in the works of Sodipo and Barry Hallen (Hallen and Sodipo 1986), and include Ogotemmeli, Marcel Griaule’s interlocutor (Griaule 1975). According to Oruka, their activities qualified as culture philosophy at best (Oruka 1991: 52). Culture philosophy, according to Oruka, indicates the underlying ideas and beliefs of a culture seen in one totalizing repertoire as its mythos or folk wisdom. Familiarity with a culture philosophy or folk wisdom presupposes allegiance to that culture. On the other hand, philosophic sagacity is the outcome of the re-evaluation of culture philosophy, a critical assessment of communal beliefs. In the words of Oruka, “using the power of reason rather than celebrated beliefs of the communal consensus and explanation, the sage philosopher produces a system within a system, an order within an order” (Oruka 1991: 52). In other words, whereas culture philosophy, which is philosophy of the first order, absolutizes and glorifies the truth claims of a culture, philosophic sagacity is a second-order scion sprouted from the first order, through the rigours of ratiocinative scrutiny or open-minded, rational scepticism. In carrying out his epistemic quest, the sage philosopher acts as an individual, for it seems that only as an individual would the sage be able to transcend communal philosophizing.

Pius Mosima, who has extensively and productively engaged with Oruka and his philosophic sagacity, explains why Oruka was fascinated with the individual as the quintessential philosopher. He asserts that this rests on Oruka’s thinking that “in a modern context, the individual is the subject, the author. He is the one who produces books, articles, and pamphlets” (Mosima 2016: 115). Moreover, being a specialist, the individual as a philosopher “has a superior position to educate, instil moral values or enlighten the reader, who is not held in high regard”. All this is because the individual philosopher is supposed to have “privileged access to truth, reason, and scientific knowledge” (ibid.).

4 The Reality of Women as Sages

Given the criteria put forward by Oruka, are there female philosophic sages in Nigeria? To ascertain whether or not our respondents were candidates for philosophic sagacity, we posed some ontological questions to them, such as whether God existed, and considered their responses.

Gladys Okpoagu was a 77-year-old widow who was educated up to Standard Five. A Christian and trader by profession, Madam Gladys, at the time of this interview, had just relinquished her position as Woman Chairlady of the Umuduru Akwakuma/Okporo community in Orlu, Imo State. Barring the infelicities associated with conducting interviews with an interpreter, these were her responses.

4.1 On the Origin of the World

Interviewer:
What does existence of the world mean to you? How do you think the world came to be? You know, what’s your view about the world? Is it possible for things to exist at all? What’s your view?
Sage Gladys:
What I am thinking in my mind is that God created the world. After creating the world he discovered that was good. He then created human beings and allowed human beings to be in the world. So, God wanted human beings to be. I am thinking this world is exactly how God wanted it to be. It is good the way it is and I like it like that.

Okay. That means you believe in God.

Yes. There is God. There is God.

Where does this your belief in God stem from? How? From where did you believe God?

I believe there is God with my faith. From my faith, I know there is God because anybody who doesn’t have faith won’t believe there is God. But if you have faith, you will believe there’s God. It’s just faith! Then you will hope in God and your faith will be strong in him, and then you will know there’s God. When you don’t faith, you won’t believe there’s God. But with faith, you will use your spirit man and know that there’s God. You and the spirit of God will be working hand in hand.

How I believe there is God is this: One, something may happen. Like, as I am a woman, I might get pregnant. If that woman is pregnant, you won’t know how the child formed in the stomach and she will carry it for nine months and deliver it. It is God that made it possible. Do you understand? God made it possible. So everything is all about faith. If you believe in God, anytime you have challenges, God will fight for you. Help you and you will be strong again. Take me for instance; I once had Stroke nine years ago. It’s my faith in God that saved me. That is why I believe strongly that there’s God and he does things for me.

What it means is that the ability for her to carry a pregnancy for nine months shows that there’s something that is responsible for it and that’s God?

Yes.

Yes! That’s why I strongly believe that there’s God. Do you understand? There’s God and that God we are serving. Anyone who doesn’t believe in God, one, doesn’t understand what he’s doing. My faith is God, that there’s God, he created everything in this world. He’s God that can do all things. No one can do all things except God.

We interviewed another female sage, a 77-year-old who called herself Mother Angelina Oguaju. Madam Angelina, who died two days after this interview, was educated up to Standard Six. She was Christian, a housewife and community leader. Her response to the same question on being and the cause of existence seems quite similar to the above.

Interviewer:
The universe, how did it come to be?
Sage Oguaju:
The way I understand this world?

Yes.

There is no other way I understand it. It is created by God.

It is God that brought this world into existence; no one will claim that he knows how this world came into existence except God. It is God that brought the world into existence and also made us (human) to be in the world and behold the things in the world.

It’s alright! Ok. So the world didn’t just originate by chance?

Yes.

Ok. Let me take it to the other one. If God made it to be, it means you believe God exists?

Yes, I believe there is God.

What informs your view? Hope it’s not

Why I believe that there is God is that it is not easy. It is God that made humans. Something without form in the womb all of a sudden, turns to human being. From there it grew and came out as human. In the womb, it is alive and it is eating food. Without God, it won’t be possible. Again, sometimes you might be alone calling on God, telling him some stories, asking him for something, when you are done, by mistake, God will do it for you but there was no one there when you were making your supplication and no one heard it. It is God that will bring those things to pass. No one else can do it.

4.2 On the Question of Leadership

On the question of leadership, sage Gladys Okpoagu submitted the following:

Interviewer:
What do you understand by being a leader having been a chairlady before? What do you understand by leadership? Is a leader born or made?
Sage Okpoagu:
To start with, a leader is born. It’s also made. From my family, from my father’s family, my father led his village people for 13 years. Then, my brother is preparing to be king. My eldest brother is the chairman of his kindred (ụmụduru). The other male in Owerri as a civil servant was the youth leader before he left and my humble self was a chairlady. My first daughter staying in Aba is the chairlady there. So, what’s in leadership as a leader is truth. If you see evil, you call it evil, don’t be partial. When someone does evil even if it’s your mother, father, husband or your kinsman, tell him that what he did is bad. Next time, the person won’t repeat such, but if you keep silent, the evil will continue. So, when it comes to leadership, you must be truthful, you must be upright, you must be advising your subjects. If any one does evil or when you come to the public, I used to advise my subjects. Don’t allow your children to steal, or become promiscuous. The house belongs to the woman. I will be telling them, don’t allow your children to impregnate a lady, if they do, they will marry the person. If there’s anyone that’s doing evil, call the person privately and advise her. If someone that’s having marital challenges, call her and advise her and let her know that marriage is patience. Those are the reasons I personally ran away from leadership even when they were begging me, but I told them I was okay.

What system do you think should be used in the selection of leaders? That is, we want to select leader now, what system do you think should be used to select leaders?

The best method? As we are in this our kindred, that is, Ụmụduru, everybody knows each other. If there’s a need for selection of men or women leaders, we in this kindred know each other. For instance, before I handed over, I had looked round and know who will be strong enough to condemn evil. Some were like, “look at this person. She is qualified for the position”, but I said no. I selected the right person and she’s there now. What’s there is that if you want to select a leader either in the village or in anything. It’s expected that the people who know each other, they know who to select as a good individual. Do you understand?

Having explained the relationship between power and leadership, and power as an instrument of control, the interview continued:

How do you see power and human nature?

How I see it? Like the power of leadership is truth. If the leader is truthful who doesn’t condone evil, just to ensure that you tell your subjects the truth. Don’t lie to them. For instance, it may be said, this land belongs to an individual but another person takes it. If this type of matter is brought and you are given a bribe, don’t take the bribe. Say the truth. If you say the truth and do it repeatedly, next time nobody will bother giving you bribe because they have known you to be truthful. Leadership is all about truthfulness. Always say the truth. Stand on your ground and say the truth no matter the pressure, be firm. You may even be threatened with money so that you will pervert justice, reject it if you know yourself because if you accept it, your leadership is messed up already. It’s truth, truth is leadership.

Another sage, Rhoda Benjamin, a farmer, Christian from Gonin/Gora Federal Housing Layout, Ungwan Waziri Southern Kaduna in northern Nigeria made this submission.

Interviewer:
Let us discuss leadership.
Sage Benjamin:
Every human being created is a leader of himself or herself. So long you are not able to take care of yourself; you are not a good leader. Much less, give you two or three people to lead. If you cannot take care of yourself, how can you take care of the people under you? Leadership is very good. It can be good for some people and some will not find it funny. To be a leader, one needs to be patient, tolerant and carry people along. He should be a person that gives listening ears to his people, not a leader that dictates to them; person who gives his people a listening ears.

Are leaders born or made?

I think leaders are born. Most times, if you are training children, and you found out that one or two are outstanding. From there, you will be able to identify good leaders among them. Most of our children are stubborn, but one or two always obey your instruction. It means they are leaders from the womb. Those who get leadership through struggle don’t normally succeed.

4.3 On the Issue of Gender Relations/Equality of the Sexes

Martina Samuel Brown was a 58-year-old leader in Afaha Atai village, in Uyo, Akwa Ibom State. She was a Christian and educated up to sixth grade in primary school.

Interviewer:
Can a woman be wiser than a man? If so, why then should a woman be submissive to the man?
Sage Brown:
A woman can be wiser than a man in certain aspects, for example in situations where the woman knows that certain decisions can be fatal and destructive. But if the man refuses to listen at that point, he is foolish if he refuses the counsel of a woman because she is a woman, the man is foolish then.

Why then should women be submissive?

Because God created it to be so; that women should be submissive to the men.

On the same issue as above, here is the conversation with Comfort Akinkúnmi from Ilé-Ogbó village in Ìlọrin West Local Government Area of Kwara State in North Central Nigeria. She put her age at between 75 and 80. She was illiterate and a petty trader.

Interviewer:
What is your view about male and female responsibilities? Is it the same?
Sage Akinkunmi:
There was no such life in the days of our mothers. We have not seen such. Females these days are stronger than men.

Do you think such a thing is proper or is it right to be like that?

Ha! It is not right. The female should contest, the male should contest, the male will always win. But the reverse is the case now. Men are no longer succeeding. Females are stronger than the male gender these days.

Do you prefer how it was when we only saw males leading and we barely heard the females, and females must follow the command the males give? Do you prefer it?

There is no such command our husbands give to us that we must obey in our time again. It is bad. That is why the world is not settled. Now, the male talks and the female disobeys. It is really bad.

5 Female Sages as Non-candidates for Orukan Philosophic Sagacity

From the Orukan standpoint, given that these women fulfilled other conditions for being sages, the question remains whether the postulations they made or the sage views expressed were philosophic in the sense of being critical. Did these female sages think or know that they were sages? Were they deliberate, conscious philosophic sages? As Oruka and his team asserted that to be critical as a philosophic sage demands that the sage in question subjects communal consensus, prevalent worldviews and established positions to ratiocinative scrutiny. Oruka also seemed to suggest, by his emphasis on this demonstration of critical individuality, that the operative virtue of the philosopher sage is the ability to be continually critical.

If the above is the case, since the women who responded to the questions seemed devoid of perceptible criticality by Oruka’s standards it follows that they do not qualify as philosophic sages in the Orukan sense. Many of them neither problematized their treatment of questions raised nor engaged the interlocutors in the polemical manner popularized by the analytic tradition, for which many anglophone philosophical traditions are known. This position should not go unquestioned because it calls for critical engagement with the Orukan criteria for sagacity in their axiological underpinning and methodological stance.

6 Analysis: Patriarchal Forces in Female Knowledge Production

Generally, female sages within the age brackets interviewed tended to adhere to the dictates of their traditional cultures when expressing views about self, nature and society, notwithstanding their religious affiliations as Christians, Muslims and Orisa adherents. Though such views may be critical of folk wisdom, they expressed them with a subtlety and caution that would not upset the epistemic balance of their respective Indigenous cultures. However, it is worth considering that this ability to maintain such epistemic integrity, though suggestive of the level of practical wisdom that these sages possessed, subsists on patriarchy.

The prevalence of patriarchy reveals certain modes of relationality between the activities of these sages and the cultural environment from which their philosophic or sagacious postulations emanate. As used here, modes of relationality refers to the various forms, qualities and outcomes of relating. It entails both the presence and absence of relating (Spies and Seesemann 2016: 136) as well as the overall philosophical underpinning of relationality (Powell 2013). The epistemic modes of relationality, among other things, concern the axiology and politics of knowledge production as well as the structures, historicities and the social networks associated with it. In analyzing the statements of the female sages, we identify the following modes of relationality: control, suppression and acquiescence.

6.1 Control

Deliberate control through customary practices, domination of spaces of influence and familial contestations are some of the most veritable expressions of patriarchy (Familusi 2012; Olabode 2009; Adebayo and Kolawole 2012). Recent studies tend to support the view that epistemic spaces also are the privileged arena of masculine domination. Apart from the home, the marketplaces and certain agricultural spaces (Pérez-Terán 2017: 7), contemporary African communities still exist in epistemic spaces controlled by male actors and agencies. Following the relational setting of philosophic sagacity, it is likely that Oruka operated within a patriarchal epistemic space bequeathed to African scholarship by an intellectual tradition that undermined the role of women in philosophical knowledge production.

At the time that Oruka flourished as a philosopher, from 1970 until his death in 1995 (Ochieng’-Odhiambo 1995: 12), there were very few prominent female African philosophers, if any. It was as if the social code of masculinity prevalent in many traditional African societies operated in the academic philosophical circles as well: women were to be seen and not heard. This is not surprising, because Oruka, like many African men of his time, thrived in a social setting that strongly discriminated against women. As studies have shown, Kenya, like many African countries, has exercised its own share of domination and subjugation of women through negative cultural practices promoted by oral literature and folklores (Wa-Gachanja 2002). Even among Oruka’s Luo community, the concept and practice of Lako or Ter, officially construed as “widow guardianship” (Abuya 2002), has been so controversial among wide-ranging interest groups and stakeholders that it has been demonized as a negative cultural practice (Nyarwath 2012: 103).

It is even alleged that Peris Njuhi Muthoni, the only female philosophic sage featured in Oruka’s sagacity project, was allegedly unfairly treated by Oruka in his conversation with her (Presbey 2021: 2; Mosima 2018: 31). Mosima is said to have noted the difference in the questioning of Muthoni and the male sages and Oruka’s unfair dismissal of Muthoni’s ideas because “she engaged in cultural critique to an extent equal to or better than the other men” (Presbey 2021: 2). While it is not too clear what the allegation of unfair treatment entailed, what is obvious is that Oruka, in his authoritative book on sage philosophy, dedicated only two pages (Oruka 1991: 104–106) to Muthoni’s submissions compared to the generous space given to the diversity of questions directed at the men (ibid.). How this could escape the scrutiny of female African philosophers for so long was suggestive of the extent of male domination in the epistemic space of philosophic sagacity.

Besides the interventions of Gail Presbey (Presbey 1997, 2012, 2018, 2021), Anke Graness (1997) and Sophie Oluwole (1997a), whose interrogation of the methodology, agency and epistemic content of Oruka’s treatment of philosophic sagacity has opened up new insights into sagacious reasoning, there seem to be no other African female academic philosophers and very few non-African academic philosophers who have contributed to the sagacity discourse regarding female agents. How can epistemic justice be served when the major contributors are male?

6.2 Suppression

Suppression as a category of patriarchal epistemology is revealed through proverbs and narratives of dominance. Proverbs are one of the most potent ways by which perceptions of women may be ascertained from members of the community. Just as they are vehicles for the expression of a people’s belief systems, transmission of values and articulation of worldviews, they are also instrumental in reflecting gender relations in a given society. Usman (2014, 2018) focuses on the Hausa society of northern Nigeria, where women have been suppressed through the use of proverbs. Proverbs such as the following express negativity and undermine women in social relations (ibid.).

  1. Mata Dangin Shaidan (Women are close relatives to the devil).

  2. Bin shawaran mata ita ke sa da na sani (Taking women’s advice brings much regret).

In a society or epistemic community where such toxic narratives are rife, it is very unlikely that a female sage would rank high in the eyes of the community. Conversely, in communities where women tend to be highly regarded, roles of sagacity are created for them by their societies even if such societies operate regimes of benign sexism (Mazrui 1993), recognizing gender segregation without bestowing sexual advantage or inflicting gender cost. In such societies, Okyerefo informs us, wisdom is “personified as a female virtue to endow the elders with the prowess to adjudicate in intractable cases” (Okyerefo 2019: 14), thereby predicating male decision-making on female acumen.

However, there have been arguments that such a relational mode might have been imagined, because some traditional Yoruba oral traditions accord certain epistemic privileges to women, especially mothers. One of the strongest allusions to this position has come from Oyewùmí, who, in her influential but controversial work, The Invention of Women: Making an African Sense of Western Gender Discourses (1997), argues that because biologization of the gender is not a conferrer of status, privilege and power in the Yoruba social system, Yoruba women are not perceived as “powerless, disadvantaged, and controlled and defined by men” (Oyewùmí 1997: XII). Although this essentialism and idealization of gender equality among the Yoruba would seem to advance women’s empowerment, studies (as cited above) have shown that patriarchal domination and suppression were and are still prevalent in many African societies (Adebayo and Kolawole 2012; Familusi 2012; Balogun 2010).

6.3 Acquiescence

In common parlance, acquiescence refers to the act of non-objection, compliance with or giving tacit agreement to a view, policy and the like. But as a category of patriarchal epistemology, it refers to the epistemic agency of women “whose desires and values are patriarchal excrescence not attributable to [them] women as real free agents” (Narayan 2006: 418). Narayan alluded to acquiescence as compliance with cultural practices that bargain with patriarchy and an epistemic prison where choices are made within constraints.

In epistemic conditions where suppression was not observed, during our interviews there were cases of acquiescence on the part of the respondents. One observable recurrence during the interviews was the deliberate surrender to faith and religious beliefs through an appeal to banal “theologism” in articulating metaphysical issues. This “theologism” was also evident in the responses to gender relations. With the exception of one or two respondents who were adherents of some Indigenous religions, others imposed or rather took recourse in their Christian or Islamic positions on the issues raised. Even in philosophical questions that required logical articulation, there was quick surrender and tacit assent to religious beliefs. We see this infrarational appeal as an indication of the centuries of cultural and cognitive restructuring that has been systematically orchestrated by religious interlopers. It is not surprising that religion operates as an instrument of patriarchy. As Amadiume (1987) explains about her Igbo ethnic group, Christian missionaries, in an unholy fraternity with colonial rule, abhorred customary practices and outlawed them. The consequence of this epistemic violence was the eventual disempowerment, domestication and relegation of women (Amadiume 1987: 119–134). What all this tells us is that the reality of female sages is predicated on the dominance of a patriarchal knowledge production scheme, since patriarchy is the norm when it comes to gender relations (Amadiume 1987).

7 Deviation from the Orukan Sense

One of the fallouts of the Orukan conception of philosophic sagacity is the ascription of critical and rational investigation to sagacity. In this regard, sagacity consists in the ability of the sage to pursue the exploration of an idea through the agency of ratio. Ratio, as the kernel of the Orukan thesis on sagacity, entails the epistemic ability to analyze, dissect and scrutinize an object of inquiry. But, is this all there is to philosophic sagacity or to being sagely philosophic? The notion of sagacity as a Western hegemonic ratio that can be extracted from the mind through interview has been criticized by Mosima:

Wisdom is not just theoretical or abstract thought (sophia) as Oruka makes us understand when he interviews his sages. Wisdom is also practical (phronesis), as in sangoma wisdom … It constitutes a way of self-knowledge of our own existential and practical situation.

MOSIMA 2016: 121

In her reaction to this criticism, Presbey (2017), who suggests that Oruka intended by action and later works that sage philosophy be a future-oriented and continuous self-evaluating project, agrees that it was misleading of Mosima to review Oruka’s sagacious philosophy in this light. According to her, Oruka, in a continuous evaluation of his project, engaged in interviews with “sages on a variety of topics like natural family planning”, while paying careful attention to “concepts of home, family relations, burial practices, and religious beliefs and practices” (Presbey 2017: 89). The point is that Oruka himself, in expanding his idea of sagacity, did not restrict the activity of the sages to the scrutiny of abstract thought, he also accommodated postulations on existential conditions and practical mundane living as subjects for sage philosophy. Wisdom, therefore, entails not only the capacity for critical evaluation of concepts or ratiocinative inquiry but also profound articulation of living experiences. If this is the case, then it deviates from Oruka’s original position that merely tends to create an alter Socrates out of the philosophic sages.

8 Towards “Feminine Wisdom”

In the light of this revised Orukan position, we can speak of another kind of sagacity, one that need not be entrapped by pre-established male-dominated canons. Although the responses of our sages might seem pedestrian in the original Orukan sense or to any essentialist philosophical tendency, on careful and discerning analysis they express a peculiar kind of sagaciousness about being and nature. They are open to some sense of sagacity that may be “feminine” on the basis of being different. This difference is evident in the knowledge production universe, where women are subjected to both testimonial and hermeneutical injustice on the basis of their ontological relegation as intellectually weak and inscrutable on account of their gender (Eyo and Obioha 2022: 145; Fricker 2007: 1). These experiences of epistemic injustice tend to engender a broader outlook on existence which appears different, if not strange, to a male-dominated order, thus opening up new insights into sagacious reasoning. Indeed, women have the capacity to contemplate some mystery about their being in a way that eludes masculine rationality.

Furthermore, in a postmodernist world characterized by multiform narratives and multiperspectival existential standpoints, it is scholarly inelegant to impose non-negotiated standards and methodologies as canons of what philosophy is and how to go about African philosophy following the form of philosophic sagacity. Whereas for the older generation, sagacity is contemplated in the context of suppression, acquiescence and control of female epistemic agency, knowledge production for the educated, Westernized younger generation includes protests and counternarratives through forceful constructive dialogue and negotiated management of epistemic spaces. This is why Oluwole’s submission on the extrarational nature of African philosophy is instructive in appreciating feminine wisdom. In one of her proverbial submissions, Oluwole avers: “Bi a ba non gongo ogbon si nkan, ti ko ba to o, ki a fi were die ti ese” (If reason is stretched to its limit, then folly becomes inevitable) (Oluwole 1997b: 39).

The “little madness” implied by the proverb is suggestive of the manifold nature of sagacious activities. Feminine wisdom, or the epistemic activity of female sages, may come in any form in so far as the agencies deployed lead to new ways of knowing or viewing African experiences. For instance, while the sages’ submissions on the origin and cause of being lack the rigorous explication of concepts found in textbooks, their recourse to self-affirmation is noteworthy. By providing grounds for the existence of God based on their expression of interior experiences as mothers or child-bearers, their position complements other forms of the cosmological argument for the existence of God. Furthermore, the reality of consensual knowledge production in this age of globalization abhors any purist or totalizing conception of an African philosophical position.

9 Conclusion

By using sage philosophy as an example to highlight the dominance of patriarchal forces in female knowledge production, this paper encourages a movement towards female sagacious philosophizing. It is a call for female academic philosophers to interrogate whatever toxic masculinities hamper female epistemic agencies. However, we are aware of, and hamstrung by, the fact that there is a gender imbalance in the discourse on philosophic sagacity. Considering Presbey’s review of the work on marginalization of African women in philosophical discourse, which questions the preponderance of male contributors who decry the absence of African women in academic philosophy, it seems highly disturbing that projects like this have not been taken over by female academic philosophers. That women have not been the ones responding to the Oruka challenge is as baffling as it is discomforting to us male researchers. Doesn’t this salvaging mission also suggest the prevalence of patriarchal regimes in academics?

References

  • Abuya, Pamela. 2002. “Women’s Voices on the Practice of Ter among the Luo of Kenya: A Philosophical Perspective”. Fabula: Journal of Folktale Studies (1–2): 94101. https://doi.org/10.1515/fabl.2002.028.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Adebayo, Anthony A. and Taiwo O. Kolawole. 2012. “Domestic Violence and Death: Women as Endangered Gender in Nigeria”. American Journal of Sociological Research 3 (3): 5360. https://doi:10.5923/j.sociology.20130303.01.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Amadiume, Ifi. 1987. Male Daughters, Female Husbands: Gender and Sex in an African Society. London: Zed Books.

  • Amadiume, Ifi. 2005. “Theorizing Matriarchy in Africa: Kinship Ideologies and Systems in Africa and Europe”. In African Gender Studies: A Reader, edited by Oyèrónké Oyewùmí, 8398. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Anyidoho, Nana Akua. 2008. “Identity and Knowledge Production in the Fourth Generation”. African Development, XXXIII (1): 2539. https://www.jstor.org/stable/24484663.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Azenabor, Godwin. 2009. “Odera Oruka’s Philosophic Sagacity: Problems and Challenges of Conversation Method in African Philosophy”. Thought and Practice 1: 6986.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Balogun, Oladele Abiodun. 2010. “Proverbial Oppression of Women in Yoruba African Culture: A Philosophical Overview”. Thought and Practice 2 (1): 2136.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Chimakonam, Jonathan O. 2018. “Addressing the Epistemic Marginalization of Women in African Philosophy and Building a Culture of Conversations”. In African Philosophy and the Epistemic Marginalization of Women, edited by Jonathan O. Chimakonam and Louise du Toit, 120. New York: Routledge.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Deleuze, Gilles and Guattari, Felix. 1987. A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Translation and foreword by Brian Massumi. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Eyo, Evaristus Matthias and Precious Uwaezeoke Obioha. 2022. “African Epistemology and Epistemic Injustice Against Women: Complementary Epistemology to the Rescue”. Sapientia Journal of Philosophy, 16: 14454.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Falaiye, Muyiwa, 1997. “Popular Wisdom vs. Didactic Wisdom: Some Comments on Oruka’s Philosophic Sagacity”. In Sagacious Reasoning: Odera Oruka in Memoriam, edited by Anke Grannes and Kai Kresse, 16370. Frankfurt: Peter Lang Publishers.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Falaiye, Muyiwa. 2006. “Philosophic Sagacity and the Problem of Transmitting Knowledge Without Writing: The Ekiti Yoruba Experience”. Hekmat Falsafeh (Wisdom and Philosophy) 2 (1): 6984.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Familusi, Olumuyiwa O. 2012. “African Culture and the Status of Women: Yoruba Example”. Journal of Pan African Studies, 5 (1) 299313.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Fricker, Miranda. 2007. Epistemic Injustice: Power and Ethics of Knowing. Oxford: University of Oxford Press.

  • Griaule, Marcel. 1975. Conversations with Ogotemmeli: An Introduction to Dogon Religious Ideas. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Hallen, Barry and John O. Sodipo. [1986] 1997. Knowledge, Belief, and Witchcraft: Analytic Experiments in African Philosophy. Redwood City, CA: Stanford University Press.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Hoeyer, Klaus and Brit R. Winthereik, 2022. “Knowing, Unknowing, and Re-knowing”. In The Palgrave Handbook of the Anthropology of Technology, edited by Bruun, M.H., et al.Singapore: Palgrave Macmillan.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Hountondji, Paulin J. 2009. “Knowledge of Africa, Knowledge by Africans: Two Perspectives on African Studies”. RCCS Annual Review [Online], Issue 1. http://rccsar.revues.org/174. DOI: .

    • Crossref
    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Imafidon, Elvis. 2020. “Exploring African Philosophy of Difference”. In Handbook of African Philosophy of Difference, edited by Elvis Imafidon. Handbooks in Philosophy. Cham: Springer.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Kekes, John. 1983. “Wisdom”. American Philosophical Quarterly 20 (3): 27786. http://www.jstor.org/stable/20014008. Accessed October 9, 2023.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Marcano, Donna-Dale. 2010. “The Difference That Difference Makes Black Feminism and Philosophy”. In Convergences: Black Feminism and Continental Philosophy, edited by Maria del Guadalupe Davidson, Kathryn T. Gines and Donna-Dale L. Marcano, 5366. New York: SUNY Press.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Matolino, Bernard. 2018. “African philosophy’s injustice against women”. In African Philosophy and the Epistemic Marginalization of Women, edited by Jonathan O. Chimakonam and Louise du Toit, 12641. New York: Routledge.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Mazrui, Ali A. 1993. “The Black Woman and the Problem of Gender: An African Perspective”. Research in African Literatures, 24 (1): 87104. https://www.jstor.org/stable/3820201.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Mosima, Pius, 2016. Philosophic Sagacity and Intercultural Philosophy: Beyond Henry Odera Oruka. Leiden: African Studies Centre.

  • Mosima, Pius. 2018. “Henry Odera Oruka and the Female Sage”. In African Philosophy and the Epistemic Marginalization of Women, edited by Jonathan O. Chimakonam and Louise du Toit, 2241. New York: Routledge.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Narayan, Uma. 2002. “Minds of Their Own: Choices, Autonomy, Cultural Practices, and Other Women”. In A Mind Of One’s Own: Feminist Essays On Reason And Objectivity, edited by Louise Antony and Charlotte Witt, 418431. New York: Routledge.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Ndlovu-Gatsheni, Sabelo. J. 2018. Epistemic Freedom in Africa: Deprovincialization and Decolonization. London: Routledge.

  • Ndlovu-Gatsheni, Sabelo. J. 2021. “The Cognitive Empire, Politics of Knowledge and African Intellectual Productions: Reflections on Struggles for Epistemic Freedom and Resurgence of Decolonization in the Twenty-First Century”. Third World Quarterly, 42 (5): 882901. https://doi.org/10.1080/01436597.2020.1775487.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Ndlovu-Gatsheni, Sabelo. J. 2022. “Unthinking Thinking and Rethinking African Future(s)”. African Studies Review 65 (1): 267278. doi:.

  • Nyarwath, Oriare. 2012. “The Luo Care for Widows (Lako) and Contemporary Challenges”. Thought and Practice: A Journal of the Philosophical Association of Kenya (PAK) New Series, 4 (1) June: 91110.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Ochieng’-Odhiambo, Frederick. 1995. “An African Savant: Henry Odera Oruka”. In Quest: An African Journal of Philosophy 9 (2): 1221.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Okeregbe, Anthony. 2018. “De-globalizing African ‘Truths’: Some Insights from Frantz Fanon et al”. Philosophia: e-Journal for Philosophy and Culture 21: 4866.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Okyerefo, Michael Perry Kweku. 2019. “Curiosity Transcends Boundaries and Foments African Epistemologies”. Keynote address at the annual conference of the Canadian Association of African Studies (CAAS).

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Olabode, Babatunde O. 2009. African Gender Myth in Proverbs and Verbal Discourses: A Case Study of the Yoruba of South-Western Nigeria. Ibadan: Hope Publications.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Olivier, Abraham, M. John Lamola and Justin Sands, eds. 2023. Phenomenology in an African Context: Contributions and Challenges. New York: SUNY Press.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Oluwole, Sophie B. 1997a. “Oruka’s Mission in African Philosophy”. In Sagacious Reasoning: Henry Odera Oruka in Memoriam, edited by Anke Graness and Kai Kresse, 14962. Frankfurt: Peter Lang.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Oluwole, Sophie B. 1997b. “Culture, Nationalism and Philosophy.” In Philosophy and Democracy in Intercultural Perspective: Studies in Intercultural Philosophy, 3, edited by Heinz Kimmerle and Franz M. Wimmer, 2342. New York: Brill. https://doi.org/10.1163/9789004457997_003.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Oruka, Henry Odera. 1983. “Sagacity in African Philosophy”. International Philosophical Quarterly 23 (4): 38393.

  • Oruka, Henry Odera. 1990. Trends in Contemporary African Philosophy. Nairobi: Shirikon Publishers. https://doi.org/10.5840/ipq198323448.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Oruka, Henry Odera. 1991. Sage Philosophy: Indigenous Thinkers and the Modern Debate on African Philosophy. Nairobi: ACTS Press.

  • Oyewùmí, Oyèrónké. 1997. The Invention of Women: Making an African Sense of Western Gender Discourses. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Oyewùmí, Oyèrónké. 2011. “Decolonizing the Intellectual and the Quotidian: Yorùbá Scholars(hip) and Male Dominance”. In Gender Epistemologies in Africa: Gendering Traditions, Spaces, Social Institutions, and Identities, edited by Oyèrónké Oyewùmí, 934. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Pérez-Terán, Alba Saray. 2017. Male Fields, Female Agencies: An Analysis of Women’s Strategies in the Demasculinization of Cocoa Plantations in Cameroon. Master’s thesis: Utrecht University.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Powell, Christopher. 2013. “Radical Relationalism: A Proposal”. In Conceptualizing Relational Sociology, edited by C. Powell and F. Dépelteau, 187207. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Presbey, Gail, 1997. “Who Counts as a Sage? Problems in the Further Implementation of Sage Philosophy”. Quest 10: 5265.

  • Presbey, Gail. 2000. “Contemporary African Sages and Queen Mothers: Their Leadership Roles in Conflict Resolution”. In Peacemaking: Lessons from the Past, Visions for the Future, edited by Judith Presler and Sally Scholz, 23145. Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Presbey, Gail. 2012. “Kenyan Sages on Equality of the Sexes”. Thought and Practice: A Journal of the Philosophical Association of Kenya (PAK) (New Series) 4 (2): 11145.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Presbey, Gail. 2017. “Oruka and Sage Philosophy: New Insights in Sagacious Reasoning”. In The Palgrave Handbook of African Philosophy, edited by A. Afolayan and Toyin Falola, 7596. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Presbey, Gail. 2018. “Odera Oruka on Culture Philosophy and Its Role in the S.M. Otieno Burial Trial”. In Odera Oruka in the Twenty-first Century Kenyan Philosophical Studies II, edited by Reginald M.J. Oduor, Oriare Nyarwath and Francis E.A. Owakah, 99118. Washington DC: Council for Research in Values and Philosophy.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Presbey, Gail. 2021. “Book Review: African Philosophy and the Epistemic Marginalization of Women. Jonathan O. Chimakonam and Louise du Toit (Eds.). London and New York: Routledge/ Taylor and Francis, 2018. ISBN 780815359647”. Hypatia 4 (2): 11145. E4. doi:.

    • Crossref
    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Radin, Paul. 1927. Primitive Man as Philosopher. New York: D. Appleton and Company.

  • Spies, Eva and Rudiger Seesemann. 2016. “Pluralicity and Relationality: New Directions in African Studies”. Africa Today 63 (2): 13239. https://doi.org/10.2979/africatoday.63.2.19

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Usman, Asabe. 2014. “An Annotation of Selected Hausa Parallel Proverbs”. Journal of Modern Education Review, 4 (11): 89299. http://dx.doi.org/10.15341/jmer(2155-7993)/11.04.2014/003.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Usman, Asabe. 2018. “The Politics of Attack Through Gendered Hausa Proverbs”. Cross Currents 4 (5): 11017. https://doi.10.36344/ccijhss.2018.v04i05.003.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Wa-Gachanja, Muigai. 2002. “Images of Women in Kenyan Oral Narratives”. Fabula: Journal of Folktale Studies (1–2): 7584. https://doi.org/10.1515/fabl.2002.026.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
1

As city-dwelling male researchers educated in the philosophical traditions of the global North, embarking on a research project that has elderly women from a provincial setting as subjects of research was fraught with unease and agonizing awakening. The motivation for this project stems from a criticism directed at the pervasive currents of patriarchal hegemonic epistemology that underlie Oruka’s sage philosophy project, assumptions of which we took for granted. When the question was asked, during one of our presentations on Oruka’s philosophic sagacity, if the project admitted only male epistemic agencies, it dawned on us that the wave of the twenty-first century insurgent and resurgent decolonization (Ndlovu-Gatsheni 2018, 2021) had not caught up with us; that there was a need to expurgate the known African mentality from the thralldom of colonial epistemic heritage and disciplinary captivity. Thus, we set out to let women – as suppressed voices and marginalized epistemic agents – tell us things we did not know. Being non-feminists, we do not explore any feminist theory in framing our submission but rather let the expressions of these women’s lived experiences be “seen” in the way they are while we examined them from a “purified” positionality.

Citation Info

  • Collapse
  • Expand

Knowing - Unknowing

African Studies at the Crossroads

Series:  Africa Multiple, Volume: 4
  • Abuya, Pamela. 2002. “Women’s Voices on the Practice of Ter among the Luo of Kenya: A Philosophical Perspective”. Fabula: Journal of Folktale Studies (1–2): 94101. https://doi.org/10.1515/fabl.2002.028.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Adebayo, Anthony A. and Taiwo O. Kolawole. 2012. “Domestic Violence and Death: Women as Endangered Gender in Nigeria”. American Journal of Sociological Research 3 (3): 5360. https://doi:10.5923/j.sociology.20130303.01.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Amadiume, Ifi. 1987. Male Daughters, Female Husbands: Gender and Sex in an African Society. London: Zed Books.

  • Amadiume, Ifi. 2005. “Theorizing Matriarchy in Africa: Kinship Ideologies and Systems in Africa and Europe”. In African Gender Studies: A Reader, edited by Oyèrónké Oyewùmí, 8398. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Anyidoho, Nana Akua. 2008. “Identity and Knowledge Production in the Fourth Generation”. African Development, XXXIII (1): 2539. https://www.jstor.org/stable/24484663.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Azenabor, Godwin. 2009. “Odera Oruka’s Philosophic Sagacity: Problems and Challenges of Conversation Method in African Philosophy”. Thought and Practice 1: 6986.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Balogun, Oladele Abiodun. 2010. “Proverbial Oppression of Women in Yoruba African Culture: A Philosophical Overview”. Thought and Practice 2 (1): 2136.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Chimakonam, Jonathan O. 2018. “Addressing the Epistemic Marginalization of Women in African Philosophy and Building a Culture of Conversations”. In African Philosophy and the Epistemic Marginalization of Women, edited by Jonathan O. Chimakonam and Louise du Toit, 120. New York: Routledge.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Deleuze, Gilles and Guattari, Felix. 1987. A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Translation and foreword by Brian Massumi. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Eyo, Evaristus Matthias and Precious Uwaezeoke Obioha. 2022. “African Epistemology and Epistemic Injustice Against Women: Complementary Epistemology to the Rescue”. Sapientia Journal of Philosophy, 16: 14454.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Falaiye, Muyiwa, 1997. “Popular Wisdom vs. Didactic Wisdom: Some Comments on Oruka’s Philosophic Sagacity”. In Sagacious Reasoning: Odera Oruka in Memoriam, edited by Anke Grannes and Kai Kresse, 16370. Frankfurt: Peter Lang Publishers.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Falaiye, Muyiwa. 2006. “Philosophic Sagacity and the Problem of Transmitting Knowledge Without Writing: The Ekiti Yoruba Experience”. Hekmat Falsafeh (Wisdom and Philosophy) 2 (1): 6984.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Familusi, Olumuyiwa O. 2012. “African Culture and the Status of Women: Yoruba Example”. Journal of Pan African Studies, 5 (1) 299313.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Fricker, Miranda. 2007. Epistemic Injustice: Power and Ethics of Knowing. Oxford: University of Oxford Press.

  • Griaule, Marcel. 1975. Conversations with Ogotemmeli: An Introduction to Dogon Religious Ideas. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Hallen, Barry and John O. Sodipo. [1986] 1997. Knowledge, Belief, and Witchcraft: Analytic Experiments in African Philosophy. Redwood City, CA: Stanford University Press.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Hoeyer, Klaus and Brit R. Winthereik, 2022. “Knowing, Unknowing, and Re-knowing”. In The Palgrave Handbook of the Anthropology of Technology, edited by Bruun, M.H., et al.Singapore: Palgrave Macmillan.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Hountondji, Paulin J. 2009. “Knowledge of Africa, Knowledge by Africans: Two Perspectives on African Studies”. RCCS Annual Review [Online], Issue 1. http://rccsar.revues.org/174. DOI: .

    • Crossref
    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Imafidon, Elvis. 2020. “Exploring African Philosophy of Difference”. In Handbook of African Philosophy of Difference, edited by Elvis Imafidon. Handbooks in Philosophy. Cham: Springer.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Kekes, John. 1983. “Wisdom”. American Philosophical Quarterly 20 (3): 27786. http://www.jstor.org/stable/20014008. Accessed October 9, 2023.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Marcano, Donna-Dale. 2010. “The Difference That Difference Makes Black Feminism and Philosophy”. In Convergences: Black Feminism and Continental Philosophy, edited by Maria del Guadalupe Davidson, Kathryn T. Gines and Donna-Dale L. Marcano, 5366. New York: SUNY Press.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Matolino, Bernard. 2018. “African philosophy’s injustice against women”. In African Philosophy and the Epistemic Marginalization of Women, edited by Jonathan O. Chimakonam and Louise du Toit, 12641. New York: Routledge.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Mazrui, Ali A. 1993. “The Black Woman and the Problem of Gender: An African Perspective”. Research in African Literatures, 24 (1): 87104. https://www.jstor.org/stable/3820201.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Mosima, Pius, 2016. Philosophic Sagacity and Intercultural Philosophy: Beyond Henry Odera Oruka. Leiden: African Studies Centre.

  • Mosima, Pius. 2018. “Henry Odera Oruka and the Female Sage”. In African Philosophy and the Epistemic Marginalization of Women, edited by Jonathan O. Chimakonam and Louise du Toit, 2241. New York: Routledge.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Narayan, Uma. 2002. “Minds of Their Own: Choices, Autonomy, Cultural Practices, and Other Women”. In A Mind Of One’s Own: Feminist Essays On Reason And Objectivity, edited by Louise Antony and Charlotte Witt, 418431. New York: Routledge.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Ndlovu-Gatsheni, Sabelo. J. 2018. Epistemic Freedom in Africa: Deprovincialization and Decolonization. London: Routledge.

  • Ndlovu-Gatsheni, Sabelo. J. 2021. “The Cognitive Empire, Politics of Knowledge and African Intellectual Productions: Reflections on Struggles for Epistemic Freedom and Resurgence of Decolonization in the Twenty-First Century”. Third World Quarterly, 42 (5): 882901. https://doi.org/10.1080/01436597.2020.1775487.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Ndlovu-Gatsheni, Sabelo. J. 2022. “Unthinking Thinking and Rethinking African Future(s)”. African Studies Review 65 (1): 267278. doi:.

  • Nyarwath, Oriare. 2012. “The Luo Care for Widows (Lako) and Contemporary Challenges”. Thought and Practice: A Journal of the Philosophical Association of Kenya (PAK) New Series, 4 (1) June: 91110.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Ochieng’-Odhiambo, Frederick. 1995. “An African Savant: Henry Odera Oruka”. In Quest: An African Journal of Philosophy 9 (2): 1221.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Okeregbe, Anthony. 2018. “De-globalizing African ‘Truths’: Some Insights from Frantz Fanon et al”. Philosophia: e-Journal for Philosophy and Culture 21: 4866.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Okyerefo, Michael Perry Kweku. 2019. “Curiosity Transcends Boundaries and Foments African Epistemologies”. Keynote address at the annual conference of the Canadian Association of African Studies (CAAS).

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Olabode, Babatunde O. 2009. African Gender Myth in Proverbs and Verbal Discourses: A Case Study of the Yoruba of South-Western Nigeria. Ibadan: Hope Publications.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Olivier, Abraham, M. John Lamola and Justin Sands, eds. 2023. Phenomenology in an African Context: Contributions and Challenges. New York: SUNY Press.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Oluwole, Sophie B. 1997a. “Oruka’s Mission in African Philosophy”. In Sagacious Reasoning: Henry Odera Oruka in Memoriam, edited by Anke Graness and Kai Kresse, 14962. Frankfurt: Peter Lang.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Oluwole, Sophie B. 1997b. “Culture, Nationalism and Philosophy.” In Philosophy and Democracy in Intercultural Perspective: Studies in Intercultural Philosophy, 3, edited by Heinz Kimmerle and Franz M. Wimmer, 2342. New York: Brill. https://doi.org/10.1163/9789004457997_003.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Oruka, Henry Odera. 1983. “Sagacity in African Philosophy”. International Philosophical Quarterly 23 (4): 38393.

  • Oruka, Henry Odera. 1990. Trends in Contemporary African Philosophy. Nairobi: Shirikon Publishers. https://doi.org/10.5840/ipq198323448.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Oruka, Henry Odera. 1991. Sage Philosophy: Indigenous Thinkers and the Modern Debate on African Philosophy. Nairobi: ACTS Press.

  • Oyewùmí, Oyèrónké. 1997. The Invention of Women: Making an African Sense of Western Gender Discourses. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Oyewùmí, Oyèrónké. 2011. “Decolonizing the Intellectual and the Quotidian: Yorùbá Scholars(hip) and Male Dominance”. In Gender Epistemologies in Africa: Gendering Traditions, Spaces, Social Institutions, and Identities, edited by Oyèrónké Oyewùmí, 934. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Pérez-Terán, Alba Saray. 2017. Male Fields, Female Agencies: An Analysis of Women’s Strategies in the Demasculinization of Cocoa Plantations in Cameroon. Master’s thesis: Utrecht University.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Powell, Christopher. 2013. “Radical Relationalism: A Proposal”. In Conceptualizing Relational Sociology, edited by C. Powell and F. Dépelteau, 187207. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Presbey, Gail, 1997. “Who Counts as a Sage? Problems in the Further Implementation of Sage Philosophy”. Quest 10: 5265.

  • Presbey, Gail. 2000. “Contemporary African Sages and Queen Mothers: Their Leadership Roles in Conflict Resolution”. In Peacemaking: Lessons from the Past, Visions for the Future, edited by Judith Presler and Sally Scholz, 23145. Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Presbey, Gail. 2012. “Kenyan Sages on Equality of the Sexes”. Thought and Practice: A Journal of the Philosophical Association of Kenya (PAK) (New Series) 4 (2): 11145.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Presbey, Gail. 2017. “Oruka and Sage Philosophy: New Insights in Sagacious Reasoning”. In The Palgrave Handbook of African Philosophy, edited by A. Afolayan and Toyin Falola, 7596. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Presbey, Gail. 2018. “Odera Oruka on Culture Philosophy and Its Role in the S.M. Otieno Burial Trial”. In Odera Oruka in the Twenty-first Century Kenyan Philosophical Studies II, edited by Reginald M.J. Oduor, Oriare Nyarwath and Francis E.A. Owakah, 99118. Washington DC: Council for Research in Values and Philosophy.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Presbey, Gail. 2021. “Book Review: African Philosophy and the Epistemic Marginalization of Women. Jonathan O. Chimakonam and Louise du Toit (Eds.). London and New York: Routledge/ Taylor and Francis, 2018. ISBN 780815359647”. Hypatia 4 (2): 11145. E4. doi:.

    • Crossref
    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Radin, Paul. 1927. Primitive Man as Philosopher. New York: D. Appleton and Company.

  • Spies, Eva and Rudiger Seesemann. 2016. “Pluralicity and Relationality: New Directions in African Studies”. Africa Today 63 (2): 13239. https://doi.org/10.2979/africatoday.63.2.19

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Usman, Asabe. 2014. “An Annotation of Selected Hausa Parallel Proverbs”. Journal of Modern Education Review, 4 (11): 89299. http://dx.doi.org/10.15341/jmer(2155-7993)/11.04.2014/003.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Usman, Asabe. 2018. “The Politics of Attack Through Gendered Hausa Proverbs”. Cross Currents 4 (5): 11017. https://doi.10.36344/ccijhss.2018.v04i05.003.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Wa-Gachanja, Muigai. 2002. “Images of Women in Kenyan Oral Narratives”. Fabula: Journal of Folktale Studies (1–2): 7584. https://doi.org/10.1515/fabl.2002.026.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation

Metrics

All Time Past 365 days Past 30 Days
Abstract Views 0 0 0
Full Text Views 238 238 43
PDF Views & Downloads 97 97 11