1 Introduction
Religious hatred may cause great harm to individuals and communities, by creating or exacerbating social divisions, causing conflict, and even promoting physical violence. Hence the rationale and impetus for writing a chapter on protection against religious hatred. As well as addressing the issue, in legal terms, of what such protection against religious hatred looks like, we need to think more carefully about some questions: are we clear what ‘religion’ connotes; what may or may not be implied by ‘protection’; and, what may be meant by the phrase ‘religious hatred’ itself? We will address these as we proceed, helping to give some theoretical clarity and frame to what is being discussed, while remaining focused upon the practical implications.
Protection against religious hatred can be understood either narrowly as the legal regulation of the manifestations of religious hatred, usually focused on prohibiting speech inciting discrimination, hostility, or violence; or understood broadly as the full range of practices, legal and non-legal, that can be employed to protect against both the development of religiously hateful attitudes as well as the manifestation of those attitudes. Here, we will focus predominantly on the narrower interpretation, which is nevertheless a rather complicated picture, but will note how this fits within a wider socio-political and conceptual context.
To outline this chapter, after briefly considering the different possible meanings of religious hatred, we will focus on the international legal, or quasi-legal,1 rights to religious freedom and protections against religious hatred, including Article 20 of the United Nations (UN) International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR).2 We will illustrate that the efficacy of these international
2 What is ‘Religious Hatred’?
We will go on to scrutinise the meaning of ‘religion’ and what we mean by ‘protection’ in more depth as the chapter progresses, but let us begin by briefly considering the different ways ‘religious hatred’ can be understood.3 Perhaps the most obvious interpretation is the hatred of an individual or group on the basis of that individual or group’s religious identity. Another interpretation of religious hatred is hatred somehow arising out of, or fuelled by, an individual or group’s religious identity. So, for example, a group of Christians might locate within their Christian doctrine or practice a motivation to hate undocumented immigrants, Jews, Muslims, atheists, or even another group of Christians. There is obviously overlap between these two interpretations where the hatred emanates from an individual or group’s religious identity and is directed at another person or persons on the basis of the latter’s religious identity. Therefore, in practice, the distinction between these various forms of religious hatred may blur, but it is helpful to discuss them here so that we fully appreciate the wide range of phenomena possibly encompassed by ‘religious hatred’. A point to bear in mind is that, within this frame, non-religious individuals and groups may be targeted by religious hatred, if hatred is directed at them on the very basis of their non-religious identity. Implicit in what has been said above is that, of course, non-religious individuals and groups can also be the religious
Another point worth noting here concerns the word ‘hatred’ itself. Hatred, as commonly understood, is initially merely a feeling or emotional state. To the extent it remains as such, without somehow outwardly manifesting, it is not something that legal protections typically can or seek to address, and thus will not be the focus of the chapter. From a legal perspective, protections against religious hatred are more commonly focused on acts of discrimination or violence inspired by religious hatred, or to speech which would stir up religious hatred in or towards others. Of course, governments or civil society actors may use a range of other legislative and non-legislative measures, such as promotion of interreligious dialogue, to seek to protect against the development of religiously hateful attitudes within a society, which we will briefly note at the end of the chapter.
3 The Legal and Quasi-Legal Protections
Protecting a person against hatred on the basis of their religion can be understood as necessary in ensuring that person’s right to freedom of religion or belief (FoRB), including the right to manifest their religion or belief. After all, legal or quasi-legal provisions purporting to provide a person with FoRB may be undermined if a prevailing climate of hatred and discrimination means that the person is too intimidated to practise their religion freely. While, as noted above, hatred directed toward a person on the basis of that person’s religion is not the only possible manifestation of ‘religious hatred’, it is a common form and helps to provide context to legal protections against religious hatred by illustrating the connection between religious hatred and FoRB. Given this nexus, it will be useful to begin this section with a short introduction on FoRB. The right to FoRB is a feature of many international, regional, and national human rights regimes, indeed much more commonly so than are specific protections against religious hatred. FoRB rights aim to ensure the full flourishing of religious life, including such things as the right to worship, celebrate holidays, follow prescribed diets, wear specified clothing, carry out life cycle rituals, build seminaries, have schools, and distribute texts and publications for proselytisation.4 While, as a concept, FoRB is often traced back to European Enlightenment thinkers such as John Locke, who were inspired by what they
The right to FoRB is set out in Article 18 of the UDHR:
Everyone has the right to freedom of thought, conscience and religion; this right includes freedom to change his religion or belief, and freedom, either alone or in community with others and in public or private, to manifest his religion or belief in teaching, practice, worship and observance.
Article 18 of the UDHR has been highly influential globally, though it should be noted that, as an article of a UN declaration, it does not automatically place a legally binding obligation on states.7 A similarly worded right to FoRB is also found in Article 18 of the ICCPR, which, as a UN convention, is legally binding on signatory states that have ratified it, and which we will come on to discuss in more depth below. It is worth noting that Article 18 of the UDHR inspired similar FoRB provisions in regional human rights conventions, including Article 9 of the European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR),8 Article 12 of
While Article 18 of the UDHR (or a regional equivalent) is often cited on its own with regard to FoRB, it exists within a wider framework of rights pertaining to the treatment of religious groups and of relevance to protecting individuals against religious hatred. In the UDHR, this includes Article 2, which establishes that all people are entitled to the rights described in the UDHR, regardless of their race, religion or location, Article 3, which provides that everyone has the right to life, liberty, and the security of the person, and Article 7, which states that everyone is entitled, without any discrimination, to equal protection of the law and against any discrimination in violation of the UDHR.
It is worth mentioning two important themes of human rights protection that will be relevant when we come to discuss protection against religious hatred in more depth. Firstly, that those human rights which are not ‘absolute rights’ are subject to limitations,12 which may be set out in the same article as the right itself, or in a separate article of general applicability to the relevant human rights document overall. For an example of the latter, Article 29(2) of the UDHR states:
In the exercise of his rights and freedoms, everyone shall be subject only to such limitations as are determined by law solely for the purpose of securing due recognition and respect for the rights and freedoms of others and of meeting the just requirements of morality, public order and the general welfare in a democratic society.
Having set out the international human rights context, let us now turn to the more specific rights protecting against religious hatred. Prominent among these is Article 20(2) of the ICCPR, which states:
Any advocacy of national, racial or religious hatred that constitutes incitement to discrimination, hostility or violence shall be prohibited by law.
The target of Article 20 then is advocacy of one or more of three forms of hatred: national, racial, and religious. These could, of course, be covered by a single statement as national, racial and religious identities may overlap a great deal.14 The advocacy covered by Article 20 is that which incites discrimination, hostility, or violence. For convenience, we will sometimes refer to such advocacy in this chapter by the shorthand ‘hate speech’, and it is a phrase often used in legal instruments and scholarship dealing with protection against religious hatred, but it is important to note that outside of this context ‘hate speech’ is used variously and has a contested meaning. Definitions are not provided in the ICCPR, but according to the Office of the UN High Commissioner for Human Rights (OHCHR), ‘hatred’ and ‘hostility’ refer to “intense and irrational emotions of opprobrium, enmity and detestation towards the target group”; ‘advocacy’ requires “an intention to promote hatred publicly towards the target group”; and ‘incitement’ “refers to statements about national, racial or religious groups, which create an imminent risk of discrimination, hostility or violence
The rationale for ICCPR Article 20 was not to protect ‘religion’ itself, but to protect people from discrimination, hostility, or violence on the basis of religion. It was not intended, therefore, to protect religions themselves from criticism, even ridicule, nor indeed to prohibit blasphemy,16 though such expressions could be caught by Article 20 to the extent that they also constitute prohibited incitement. The UN Human Rights Committee (HRC) has gone as far as to say:
Prohibitions of displays of lack of respect for a religion or other belief system, including blasphemy laws, are incompatible with the Covenant, except in the specific circumstances envisaged in article 20, paragraph 2, of the Covenant… Nor would it be permissible for such prohibitions to be used to prevent or punish criticism of religious leaders or commentary on religious doctrine and tenets of faith.17
ICCPR Article 20 provides a positive obligation on signatory states to ensure that their legal regimes include provisions prohibiting such advocacy of hatred, and if they do not, to legislate to introduce such provisions. The obligation to provide domestic legal protections is of paramount importance because, for a plethora of reasons, not least among them viability of enforcement and the expense of conducting legal proceedings, it is generally much more practicable for a person to avail themselves of domestic legal rights than rights that exist only at the international level. As noted above, unlike the UDHR, the ICCPR is binding on signatory states that have ratified it, and thus carries some legal
The Government of the United Kingdom interpret article 20 consistently with the rights conferred by articles 19 and 21 of the Covenant and having legislated in matters of practical concern in the interests of public order (ordre public) reserve the right not to introduce any further legislation…19
We will come on to discuss the significance of the United Kingdom’s reference to ICCPR Article 19 below, but here we simply note that the ability of the United Kingdom to enter a reservation limiting its obligations under ICCPR Article 20 demonstrates a limitation of the effectiveness of the international legal regime. Indeed, the HRC, established by ICCPR Article 28 to monitor states parties’ implementation of the convention, has commented that “The number of reservations, their content and their scope may undermine the effective implementation of the Covenant and tend to weaken respect for the obligations of States parties”.20
Though it is the most prominent, the ICCPR is not the only significant UN document relevant to protection against religious hatred. The UNGA declared in the 1981 Declaration on the Elimination of All Forms of Intolerance and Discrimination Based on Religion or Belief that it was concerned by “manifestations of intolerance and by the existence of discrimination in matters of religion or belief still in evidence in some areas of the world”. It resolved to adopt all necessary measures to eliminate such intolerance and discrimination.21 Unfortunately, unlike the 1963 Declaration on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination,22 which was followed by the 1965 International Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination (ICERD),23 the 1981 Declaration has not yet been followed up by any convention.
There have been various other UNGA resolutions seeking to strengthen the norm against advocacy of religious hatred. Human Rights Council (distinct from the HRC) Resolution 16/18, adopted on 24 March 2011, expressed concern that:
incidents of religious intolerance, discrimination and related violence, as well as of negative stereotyping of individuals on the basis of religion or belief, continue to rise around the world, and condemns, in this context, any advocacy of religious hatred against individuals that constitutes incitement to discrimination, hostility or violence, and urges states to take effective measures…to address and combat such incidents.25
UNGA Resolution 66/168, adopted on 19 December 2011, specifically noted deep concern about “the overall rise in instances of intolerance and violence,
Deeply concerned about the prevalence of impunity in some instances, and the lack of accountability in some cases, in addressing violence against persons on the basis of religion or belief in public and private spheres, and stressing the importance of making the necessary efforts to raise awareness to address the spread of hate speech against persons on the basis of religion or belief.27
4 The ‘Conflict’ between Prohibitions on Hate Speech and Freedom of Expression
As foreshadowed by the reference to Article 19 of the ICCPR in the United Kingdom’s Article 20 reservation discussed above, the perceived conflict between the Article 19 right to freedom of expression and the Article 20 mandate to prohibit incitement has been a major theme of legal debates surrounding the implementation and enforcement of hate speech laws in states bound by the ICCPR.28 Article 19(2) states:
Everyone shall have the right to freedom of expression; this right shall include freedom to seek, receive and impart information and ideas of all kinds, regardless of frontiers, either orally, in writing or in print, in the form of art, or through any other media of his choice.
The balance between freedom of expression and protections against hate speech has been struck differently in different national jurisdictions. At one end of the spectrum we may place the United States, where, to protect freedom of speech, courts are likely to strike down any restrictions on hate speech unless the hate speech is an incitement to violence that is likely to occur imminently.30 Towards the opposite end of the spectrum are European states such as France and Germany where restrictions on hate speech are relatively stronger. These differing approaches likely reflect the historical contexts of these jurisdictions. Continental Europe witnessed large scale conflict and the Holocaust in the twentieth century. Hate speech, then predominantly towards Jews, was seen as the precursor to horrific physical violence. The lesson that has been learned in much of Europe therefore is to robustly clamp down on hate speech before it progresses to something even worse. As mentioned above, there are regional human rights regimes which echo many of the rights in the UDHR and ICCPR, with one notable example being the ECHR. While the ECHR does not contain an equivalent provision to Article 20 of the ICCPR, the European Court of Human Rights (Strasbourg Court) has on numerous occasions been asked to balance the right to freedom of expression in ECHR Article 10 with the right to religious freedom in ECHR Article 9. It has been argued before the court, with some success, that certain speech hostile to a particular religion has infringed the religious freedom of adherents of that religion.31 Again, it is likely the European historical context that explains the Strasbourg Court’s relative willingness to restrict expression. Indeed, the Strasbourg Court has been criticised for developing notions of ‘respect for religions’ or ‘respect for people’s religious feelings’ as grounds for limiting free expression or even as rights in themselves. These criticisms note that the HRC, in hate speech cases that
Even among the 47 states subject to the ECHR, there are great divergences as to the relative weight given to restrictions on hate speech and freedom of speech. In the United Kingdom, the courts have been less ready to restrict speech than in France or Germany. Among other groups in the United Kingdom, Christian campaigners sought to oppose the introduction of the Racial and Religious Hatred Act 2006, which created a group of criminal offences of stirring up religious hatred, and argued, controversially, that the proposed legislation would make it unlawful to criticise other religions and to evangelise their own faith. Ultimately, a “Protection of freedom of expression” clause was included in the Act, which states:
Nothing in this Part shall be read or given effect in a way which prohibits or restricts discussion, criticism or expressions of antipathy, dislike, ridicule, insult or abuse of particular religions or the beliefs or practices of their adherents, or of any other belief system or the beliefs or practices of its adherents, or proselytising or urging adherents of a different religion or belief system to cease practising their religion or belief system.33
The relatively permissive approach in the United Kingdom contrasts greatly with the approach, for example, in Singapore. Amongst other domestic legislation limiting expression likely to be religiously sensitive, the Singaporean Penal Code makes the following offences:
298: Whoever, with deliberate intention of wounding the religious or racial feelings of any person, utters any word or makes any sound in the hearing of that person…
298A: Whoever — (a) by words, either spoken or written…knowingly promotes or attempts to promote, on grounds of religion or race, disharmony or feelings of enmity, hatred or ill will between different religious or racial groups; or
(b) commits any act which he knows is prejudicial to the maintenance of harmony between different religious or racial groups and which disturbs or is likely to disturb the public tranquillity.34
This restrictive approach reflects a strong desire in Singapore to maintain racial and religious harmony in, arguably, the most religiously diverse state in the world, and to avoid a repeat of the riots that took place there in the middle decades of the twentieth century, including on 21 July 1964, when Chinese and Malay groups clashed during a celebration of the birthday of the Prophet Muhammad.
In 2011 and 2012, the OHCHR organised a series of expert workshops to examine “legislation, jurisprudence, and national policies with regard to the prohibition of national, racial, or religious hatred as reflected in international human rights law”.35 This culminated in the Rabat Plan of Action which suggested that, in order to ensure that restrictions on freedom of expression remain exceptional, a six part threshold test would need to be fulfilled in order for a statement of incitement to amount to a criminal offence. Firstly, context needs to be taken into account; secondly, the speaker’s position in society should be considered; thirdly, intent, rather than mere negligence or recklessness, of the speaker must be shown; fourthly, the content and form of the speech must be analysed; fifthly, the reach of the speech act is relevant; finally, the likelihood, including imminence, of harmful action flowing from the incitement is important. This high threshold supports the arguments of scholars such as Nazila Ghanea, who has argued that for Article 20 of the ICCPR to override Article 19, it will generally require “a pattern, if not long history, of gross human rights violations against a particular minority group.”36
5 A Socio-Political Decolonial Conceptual Frame
As American criminologist Biko Agozino, amongst others, has noted, legal and criminal justice schemes are often embedded in racist and colonial regimes of power that uphold what may be termed epistemic injustice.37 That the law is not a neutral tool and may privilege certain elites has, of course, long been a critique going back to at least the time of Karl Marx. However, our concern here is not to question the legal system itself, but rather the socio-cultural frames in which we think about ‘religious hatred’. Back in the early 1960s, scholar of religion Wilfred Cantwell Smith noted that the English language nomenclature ‘religion’ had no natural equivalence in most languages (outside of modern European ones), and that the term itself had very different meanings even in English before around the eighteenth century.38 Taking on board further scholarship since then, which has importantly thrown light on how a Western Protestant Christian conception of ‘proper’ religion has been spread globally by colonialism,39 the significance of this for our purposes is at least threefold. Firstly, most cultures have not had the language to name and define a discrete and particular aspect of their forms of behaviour and ideology as ‘religion’ as distinct from other areas of life. As such, defining and naming certain aspects of the world as being ‘religion’ enforces a modern, Western, and distinctly Protestant Christian worldview and division onto various traditions which may not fit their own ways of seeing the world. Secondly, and following from the first, the modern, Western, and again Protestant, binary of ‘religion’ and ‘secularism’ is only the way one part of the world makes sense of the boundaries and divisions between these two spheres, rather than being a natural breakage between two distinct realms of culture. Thirdly, those things which we may define as ‘religious’ but which do not, for various reasons, fit closely enough with how modern, Western, Protestant men have typically understood ‘religion’ will typically be defined via other nomenclature, which may include such terms as ‘superstition’, ‘magic’, and ‘cult’. It has certainly been argued that scholars and students of interreligious studies who seek to understand the dynamic encounters of traditions in society need to understand the
The important takeaway is that only certain types of things get to be classified as ‘religion’ and protected against ‘religious hatred’. A good case in point are Native American traditions,41 which were typically framed within the United States as ‘superstition’ and therefore practices such as ritualised dances were not protected, but instead demeaned and even met with hostility. It took until 1978 for the United States courts to widely recognise Native American practices and ideological frames as religion and protected by longstanding FoRB provisions. However, to recognise certain practices as examples of ‘religion’ may be problematic for a different reason. To demarcate an aspect of a people’s culture as being ‘religion’ may do conceptual violence to the indigenous lifeworld of those people because such practices may cross over with their other socio-political practices and areas of life. Placing certain practices within the religion box creates an unnatural fissure within the worldview and understanding of those groups. In truth, there is not simply a natural and universal sphere or realm of ‘religion’ waiting out there to be recognised and located; rather it is only an aspect of a particular form of socio-political discourse.
We must, however, be careful not to overstate this. While some radical deconstructionist framings of the scholarship suggest that the definition of ‘religion’ is merely an ‘arbitrary’ pairing off of certain parts of human culture, making the word inherently unstable, politically suspect, and meaningless (in part because it can be filled with an excess of meaning), we must not forget that all words exist within socio-political contexts. As such, a usage of ‘religion’ as an ‘essentially contested concept’ has been advanced, arguing that various human traditions exist which have interacted as somewhat equivalent spheres over time and space (including outside of Western colonial spheres of influence), and that also relate conceptually in certain ways, including in an orientation to what may broadly be termed ‘transcendence’. Thus, we do not argue
We cannot enter into the background here, but in short in both historical and contemporary context, very often religion (or, rather, ‘protected religion’) is what white bodies do (rather than brown or black bodies) what men do (rather than women), what elites and middle-class people do (rather than working-class or subaltern groups), and, is defined from Western, Protestant centres of power rather than understood from the margins or periphery. We may usefully see the problem encapsulated in what is termed the World Religions Paradigm (WRP), which defines how ‘proper’ religion is often perceived. While variously defined,43 in general the WRP delimits religion as: textual, that is originating from and centred upon a particular text, or texts, that define correct belief and practice; belief-centric, so religion is about what people think, or creedal statements, rather than what they do or how they behave; inward focused, so about personal rather than communal commitment, and may be focused especially on ethics, without straying into matters of the public sphere; bounded, so each religion has clear markers that define the ‘believers’ of one religion against the ‘believers’ of another, which may be through texts, creeds, and so on. In scholarly terms, this is wrong on so many levels that it is difficult to unpack the issues here, but in brief: texts are often not central to religions and their practice, and some do not have texts; in many religions, practice and community belonging matters far more than correct beliefs, while doctrines or concepts may be flexible or varied; religion often focuses on outer manifestations and community rather than the inner, and may regulate many areas of life; every religion is syncretic to its core, and forms of multiple identity or belonging are common or normative in various contexts. All of this is of legal consequence as it affects the determination by legislators and policy makers of what gets protected as religion. Implicit in what has been noted above, and may be drawn out explicitly here is what Silvio Ferrari notes as a distinction between understanding religion as internal form (forum internum) which tends to be favoured
The determination of what counts as religion has been relatively straightforward in some cases, for instance relating to mainstream Christian practice. The case of Judaism and protection against antisemitism has been more complicated. Historically, and still today, representations of Judaism as such things as religion, ethnicity, nationality, and culture give rise to the potential for certain forms of antisemitism to not register as ‘religious hatred’ per se.45 In today’s context, despite being the tradition of around one billion of the world’s population, and the second largest religion after Christianity, it is Islam which most often becomes problematised, especially as it has become increasingly securitised post 9/11. Indeed, what we may term devotional practices such as growing beards, mosque attendance, and Quran reading have been seen as signs of radicalisation in an atmosphere of Islamophobic religious hatred which has threatened the way Muslims may freely practice their faith. Who gets to decide what religion is and what counts as religion is therefore not just a conceptual issue for scholars to debate but a wider socio-political issue with definite legal consequences.
6 The Limits of Law
In 2019, the UN launched its Strategy and Plan of Action on Hate Speech, which aimed to “address root causes and drivers of hate speech” and “enable effective UN responses to the impact of hate speech on societies”. In it, the UN Secretary-General states “the UN supports more speech, not less, as the key means to address hate speech” and also that “tackling hate speech is the responsibility of all – governments, societies, the private sector, starting with individual women and men”.46 This helps us to see the limitations of using legal regulations of hate speech as a means to protect against religious hatred. There are many limitations but we will focus on just a few of them here.
Crucially, apart from the conceptual issues raised as to how to decide on what traditions constitute ‘religions’ and are to be protected, and leaving aside the difficulty for individuals of enforcing their legal rights, we see that legal regulations are inherently limited in a broader sense. Laws can be effective mainly at targeting the significant manifestations of hateful attitudes, often once they are already well entrenched. Laws can of course help to punish and disincentivise people from making statements of incitement but, realistically, they can do little more broadly to prevent the development of exclusivist, intolerant, and hateful attitudes that might be encouraged in families, schools, or in workplaces. The situation is made worse by the fact that certain contemporary political movements and their leaders appear to be working to erode norms of tolerance and indeed to capitalise on hatred towards minority groups for their own gain. Therefore, non-legal means of protecting against religious hatred are of great importance. Education initiatives, interreligious, or inter-worldview, dialogues and, more broadly, efforts to bring people of different backgrounds into regular contact with one another in settings conducive to community building are valuable.48 Arguably, promoting interreligious dialogue has become the default position of secular societies in relation to religious diversity, though how far this may promote social cohesion is a
7 Conclusion
In this chapter, we have endeavoured to show that despite clear and seemingly strong international regulations providing protection against religious hatred, these protections are not as strong as they may seem. Reasons for this include the fact that international legal and quasi-legal protections against hate speech have not been implemented by all nation states and even in those where they have, individuals may be unable to enforce their rights domestically. Furthermore, protections against religious hatred are interpreted differently across jurisdictions according to the priority that is given to protecting freedom of speech. We have also undertaken a deeper conceptual analysis to highlight that the determination of what properly constitutes religion, and thus religious hatred, often rests on problematic assumptions. Finally, we argued that, apart from definitional issues and the difficulty of enforcing rights, legal protections are an inherently limited means of combatting hatred. While enumerated as distinct points, each of these overlaps with the others.
By ‘quasi-legal’ we refer to resolutions, declarations, lists of rights, working definitions, and so on, which, while not imposing legally binding obligations, may nevertheless be said to establish powerful norms potentially constraining a state, an organisation, or an individual’s conduct.
UN General Assembly, International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, 16 December 1966, United Nations, Treaty Series, vol. 999, p. 171, available at: https://www.refworld.org/docid/3ae6b3aa0.html.
For a fuller discussion, see Paul Hedges, Religious Hatred: Prejudice, Islamophobia, and Antisemitism in Global Context (London: Bloomsbury, 2021), 43–48.
See Paul Hedges, Understanding Religion: Theories and Methods for Studying Religiously Diverse Societies (Oakland, CA: University of California Press, 2021), 389–390.
Some may suggest that the concept of freedom of religion was exhibited far earlier in such instantiations as the South Asian emperor Ashoka’s edicts which guaranteed a freedom for practice, belonging, and belief to many traditions. However, it is not the purpose of this chapter to either discuss such historical instances, nor to debate in depth what ‘religion’ might have meant across various socio-historical contexts.
UN General Assembly, Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 10 December 1948, 217 A (III), available at: https://www.refworld.org/docid/3ae6b3712c.html.
UNGA declarations and resolutions are not generally legally binding on member states. Nevertheless, they are sometimes referred to as ‘soft law’ and if all or a majority of member states declare that a UNGA resolution is a legally binding norm, it may become ‘general practice accepted as law’ or opinio juris. The legal impact of a UNGA resolution is likely to be greater where its language is precise and it was adopted by a large majority of states. For a useful overview, see Medicins Sans Frontieres, “The Practical Guide to Humanitarian Law: Soft Law”, available at https://guide-humanitarian-law.org/content/article/3/soft-law/.
Council of Europe, European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms, as amended by Protocols Nos. 11 and 14, 4 November 1950, ETS 5, available at: https://www.refworld.org/docid/3ae6b3b04.html.
Organization of American States, American Convention on Human Rights, “Pact of San Jose”, Costa Rica, 22 November 1969, available at: https://www.refworld.org/docid/3ae6b36510.html.
Organization of African Unity, African Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights, “Banjul Charter”, 27 June 1981, CAB/LEG/67/3 rev. 5, 21 I.L.M. 58 (1982), available at: https://www.refworld.org/docid/3ae6b3630.html.
League of Arab States, Arab Charter on Human Rights, 15 September 1994, available at: https://www.refworld.org/docid/3ae6b38540.html.
Which human rights are absolute differs across human rights documents but generally would include, for example, freedom from slavery and freedom from torture. These rights cannot be properly subject to any limitation.
It is not uncommon to hear assertions that two or more rights, even within the same human rights document, contradict each other, or are incompatible with each other. This might lead to attempts to formulate a hierarchy of human rights in order to establish which right should take precedence. In general, the better view is to see the various human rights as interdependent, sometimes requiring a balancing act in determining the priority of competing rights in a given context.
For a discussion of religious hatred as racial hatred, see Hedges, Religious Hatred, 83–98.
OHCHR, “One-pager on “incitement to hatred”, available at: https://www.ohchr.org/Documents/Issues/Opinion/Articles19-20/ThresholdTestTranslations/Rabat_threshold_test.pdf. These definitions derive from Article XIX, Camden Principles on Freedom of Expression and Equality (London, April 2009), principle 12, available at: https://www.article19.org/data/files/pdfs/standards/the-camden-principles-on-freedom-of-expression-and-equality.pdf.
As blasphemy is the subject of another chapter in the current volume, we will not discuss it in depth in this chapter.
UN Human Rights Committee, General comment no. 34, Article 19, Freedoms of opinion and expression, 12 September 2011, CCPR/C/GC/34, paragraph 48, available at: https://www.refworld.org/docid/4ed34b562.html.
From where the authors write. Though Singapore has not signed up to the ICCPR, this does not reflect a reluctance to implement protections against hate speech. On the contrary, Singapore limits expressions related to race and religion to a greater extent than many ICCPR signatory states. The point being made here is simply the inherent limitation of the ICCPR that it only binds states that have ratified it. On how Singapore manages its interreligious diversity with regards to legislation, see Paul Hedges and Mohamed Imran Mohamed Taib, “Singapore’s Interfaith Movement,” in The Interfaith Movement, eds. John Fahy and Jan-Jonathan Bock (New York: Routledge, 2019): 140–142.
The full list of ICCPR declarations and reservations is available on the United Nations Treaty Collection website: https://treaties.un.org/Pages/ViewDetails.aspx?chapter=4&clang=_en&mtdsg_no=IV-4&src=IND [accessed 21 February 2022].
UN Human Rights Committee, CCPR General Comment No. 24: Issues Relating to Reservations Made upon Ratification or Accession to the Covenant or the Optional Protocols thereto, or in Relation to Declarations under Article 41 of the Covenant, 4 November 1994, CCPR/C/21/Rev.1/Add.6, paragraph 1, available at: https://www.refworld.org/docid/453883fc11.html. The HRC also notes, at paragraph 8, that “provisions in the Covenant that represent customary international law (and a fortiori when they have the character of peremptory norms) may not be the subject of reservations. Accordingly, a State may not reserve the right to… permit the advocacy of national, racial or religious hatred”. But it is not in fact clear that the prohibition of the advocacy of hatred represents customary international law, apart from the obligation in ICCPR 20(2).
UN General Assembly, Declaration on the Elimination of All Forms of Intolerance and of Discrimination Based on Religion or Belief, 25 November 1981, A/RES/36/55, available at: https://www.refworld.org/docid/3b00f02e40.html.
UN General Assembly, United Nations Declaration on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination, 20 November 1963, A/RES/1904, available at: https://www.refworld.org/docid/3b00f06558.html.
UN General Assembly, International Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination, 21 December 1965, A/RES/2106, available at: https://www.refworld.org/docid/3b00f1931c.html.
Natan Lerner, “Freedom of expression and advocacy of group hatred: Incitement to hate crimes and religious hatred,” Conference room paper for the Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights’ expert seminar on the links between Articles 19 and 20 of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights: “Freedom of expression and advocacy of religious hatred that constitutes incitement to discrimination, hostility or violence” (2–3 October 2008): 93, available at: https://www.ohchr.org/Documents/Issues/Expression/ICCPR/Seminar2008/CompilationConferenceRoomPapers.pdf.
UN Human Rights Council, Combating intolerance, negative stereotyping and stigmatization of, and discrimination, incitement to violence, and violence against persons based on religion or belief, 12 April 2011, A/HRC/RES/16/18, available at: https://www.refworld.org/docid/4db960f92.html.
UN General Assembly, Resolution 66/168 Adopted by the UN General Assembly: Elimination of all forms of intolerance and discrimination based on religion or belief, 11 April 2012, A/RES/66/168, available at: https://digitallibrary.un.org/record/724798?ln=en.
UN General Assembly, Resolution 76/250 Adopted by the UN General Assembly: Holocaust denial, 20 January 2022, A/RES/76/250, available at: https://digitallibrary.un.org/record/3956241?ln=en. This follows UNGA Resolutions 60/7 on Holocaust remembrance (UN Doc. A/RES/60/7, 21 November 2005), available at: https://digitallibrary.un.org/record/559922?ln=en, and 61/255 on Holocaust denial (UN Doc. A/RES/61/255, 22 March 2007), available at: https://digitallibrary.un.org/record/591884?ln=en.
The perceived conflict between protecting free expression and prohibiting hate speech has been a major theme of legal and political debates globally, relating to a wide range of laws, even in states not bound by the ICCPR.
See Conference room paper, supra note 24.
The United States entered a reservation to the ICCPR stating “article 20 does not authorize or require legislation or other action by the United States that would restrict the right of free speech and association protected by the Constitution and laws of the United States”.
See, for example, Strasbourg Court, Application no. 13470/87, Otto Preminger-Institute v. Austria, judgment of 20 September 1994.
Jeroen Temperman and Joseph Powderly, “Protection against Religious Hatred under the UN ICCPR and the European Convention System,” Human Rights, 10.2 (2015): 137.
Schedule to Racial and Religious Hatred Act 2006, available at: https://www.legislation.gov.uk/ukpga/2006/1/schedule [accessed 28 February 2022].
Singapore Penal Code 1871, as amended, available at: https://sso.agc.gov.sg/Act/PC1871?WholeDoc=1#pr298- [accessed 28 February 2022].
UN Human Rights Council, Annual report of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights – Addendum – Report of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights on the expert workshops on the prohibition of incitement to national, racial or religious hatred, 11 January 2013, A/HRC/22/17/Add.4, available at: https://www.ohchr.org/Documents/Issues/Opinion/SeminarRabat/Rabat_draft_outcome.pdf.
Nazila Ghanea, “Minorities and Hatred: Protections and Implications,” International Journal on Minority and Group Rights, 17.3 (2010): 435.
See Biko Agozino, Black Women and the Criminal Justice System: Towards the Decolonisation of Victimisation (Aldershot: Ashgate, 1997); see also Biko Agozino, “Theorizing Otherness, the War on Drugs and Incarceration,” Theoretical Criminology 4.3 (2000): 359–376.
Wilfred Cantwell Smith, The Meaning and End of Religion (London: SPCK, 1978 [1962]).
For a survey of debates on the term ‘religion’, see Hedges, Understanding Religion, 19–35.
See Paul Hedges and Yue Liu, “Interreligious Studies, Law, and Freedom of Religion and Belief,” in Georgetown Companion to Interreligious Studies, ed. Lucinda Mosher (Washington D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 2021): 99–107.
For sources on this discussion, see Robert F. Berkhofer, The White Man’s Indian: Images of the American Indian from Columbus to the Present (New York: Random House, 1979), Tzvetan Todorov, The Conquest of America: The Question of the Other (New York: Harper and Row, 1984), and Tink Tinker (wazhazhe udsethe, Osage Nation), “Religious Studies: The Final Colonization of American Indians,” Religious Theory (1 and 9 June 2020), available at: http://jcrt.org/religioustheory/2020/06/01/religious-studies-the-final-colonization-of-american-indians-part-1-tink-tinker-wazhazhe-udsethe. For a brief summary, see Hedges, Understanding Religion, 183, box 7.9.
See, variously, Hedges, Understanding Religion, chapters 1, 3, 7, 10, and 18.
The classic study of these debates on defining the ‘world religion’ in nineteenth century Western scholarship is Tomoko Masuzawa, The Invention of World Religions (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 2005).
Silvio Ferrari, “Law and Religion in a Secular World: A European Perspective,” Ecclesiastical Law Society, 14.3 (2012): 355–370. On this relationship, see also Hedges, Understanding Religion, 380, 391.
On how these become conflated in definitions of Judaism and so relate to antisemitism, see Hedges, Religious Hatred, especially 90–94, 113–117.
United Nations Strategy and Plan of Action on Hate Speech, May 2019, available at: https://www.un.org/en/genocideprevention/documents/advising-and-mobilizing/Action_plan_on_hate_speech_EN.pdf.
Deborah Lipstadt, Denying the Holocaust: The Growing Assault on Truth and Memory (New York: Plume, 1994), 220. For further debate on regulating religious hatred and the pitfalls of legal regulations, see Paul Hedges and Luca Farrow, “Interlude 4: Can We Regulate Religious Hatred”, in Hedges, Religious Hatred, 195–201.
On some initiatives in this context, see Gary Bouma, Rod Ling, and Anna Halafoff, “The Impact of Religious Diversity and Revitalization on Inter-religious Education for Citizenship and Human Rights”, in International Handbook of Inter-religious Education, eds. Kath Engbretson, Marian de Souza, Gloria Durka, and Liam Gearon (New York: Springer): 1053–1070; Anna Halafoff, “Riots, Mass Casualties, and Religious Hatred: Countering Anticosmopolitan Terror through Intercultural and Interreligious Understanding,” in Controversies in Contemporary Religion, vol. 2, ed. Paul Hedges (Santa Barbara, CA: Praeger, 2014): 293–312, and Hedges, Religious Hatred, 205–209.
See, on these various points: Paul Hedges, “The Secular Realm as Interfaith Space: Discourse and Practice in Contemporary Multicultural Nation-States,” Religions (2019), DOI: https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10090498; Paul Hedges, “Can Interreligious Dialogue Provide a New Space for Deliberative Democracy in the Public Sphere?: Philosophical Perspectives from the Examples of the UK and Singapore,” Interreligious Studies and Intercultural Theology, 2.1 (2018): 5–25; Julia Martínez-Ariño, “Governing religious diversity in cities: critical perspectives,” Religion, State & Society, 47:4–5 (2019): 364–373; and, Paul Hedges, “Conceptualising Social Cohesion in Relation to Religious Diversity: Sketching a Pathway in a Globalised World,” Interreligious Relations, 16 (2020), available at: https://www.rsis.edu.sg/wp-content/uploads/2020/07/IRR-Issue-16-May-2020.pdf.
Bibliography
Books
Agozino, Biko. Black Women and the Criminal Justice System: Towards the Decolonisation of Victimisation. Aldershot: Ashgate, 1997.
Berkhofer, Robert F. The White Man’s Indian: Images of the American Indian from Columbus to the Present. New York: Random House, 1979.
Hedges, Paul. Religious Hatred: Prejudice, Islamophobia, and Antisemitism in Global Context. London: Bloomsbury, 2021.
Hedges, Paul. Understanding Religion: Theories and Methods for Studying Religiously Diverse Societies. Oakland, CA: University of California Pres, 2021.
Lipstadt, Deborah. Denying the Holocaust: The Growing Assault on Truth and Memory. New York: Plume, 1994.
Masuzawa, Tomoko. The Invention of World Religions. Chicago: Chicago University Press, 2005.
Smith, Wilfred Cantwell. The Meaning and End of Religion. London: SPCK, 1978 [1962].
Temperman, Jeroen, Religious Hatred and International Law: The Prohibition of Incitement to Violence or Discrimination. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2016.
Todorov, Tzvetan. The Conquest of America: The Question of the Other. New York: Harper and Row, 1984.
Book Chapters
Bouma, Gary, Rod Ling, and Anna Halafoff. “The Impact of Religious Diversity and Revitalization on Inter-religious Education for Citizenship and Human Rights.” In International Handbook of Inter-religious Education, edited by Kath Engbretson, Marian de Souza, Gloria Durka, and Liam Gearon, 1053–1070. New York: Springer.
Halafoff, Anna. “Riots, Mass Casualties, and Religious Hatred: Countering Anticosmopolitan Terror through Intercultural and Interreligious Understanding.” In Controversies in Contemporary Religion, vol. 2, edited by Paul Hedges, 293–312. Santa Barbara, CA: Praeger, 2014.
Hedges, Paul and Yue Liu, “Interreligious Studies, Law, and Freedom of Religion and Belief.” In Georgetown Companion to Interreligious Studies, edited by Lucinda Mosher, 99–107. Washington D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 2021.
Hedges, Paul and Mohamed Imran Mohamed Taib. “Singapore’s Interfaith Movement.” In The Interfaith Movement, edited by John Fahy and Jan-Jonathan Bock, 139–157. New York: Routledge, 2019.
Articles
Agozino, Biko. “Theorizing Otherness, the War on Drugs and Incarceration.” Theoretical Criminology, 4.3 (2000): 359–376.
Ferrari, Silvio. “Law and Religion in a Secular World: A European Perspective.” Ecclesiastical Law Society, 14.3 (2012): 355–370.
Ghanea, Nazila. “Minorities and Hatred: Protections and Implications.” International Journal on Minority and Group Rights, 17.3 (2010): 423–446.
Hedges, Paul. “Can Interreligious Dialogue Provide a New Space for Deliberative Democracy in the Public Sphere?: Philosophical Perspectives from the Examples of the UK and Singapore.” Interreligious Studies and Intercultural Theology, 2.1 (2018): 5–25.
Hedges, Paul. “Conceptualising Social Cohesion in Relation to Religious Diversity: Sketching a Pathway in a Globalised World.” Interreligious Relations, 16 (2020), available at: https://www.rsis.edu.sg/wp-content/uploads/2020/07/IRR-Issue-16-May-2020.pdf.
Hedges, Paul. “The Secular Realm as Interfaith Space: Discourse and Practice in Contemporary Multicultural Nation-States.” Religions (2019), DOI: https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10090498.
Martínez-Ariño, Julia. “Governing religious diversity in cities: critical perspectives.” Religion, State & Society, 47.4–5 (2019): 364–373.
Temperman, Jeroen and Joseph Powderly. “Protection against Religious Hatred under the UN ICCPR and the European Convention System.” Human Rights, 10.2 (2015): 119–138.
Tinker, Tink (wazhazhe udsethe, Osage Nation). “Religious Studies: The Final Colonization of American Indians.” Religious Theory (1 and 9 June 2020), available at: http://jcrt.org/religioustheory/2020/06/01/religious-studies-the-final-colonization-of-american-indians-part-1-tink-tinker-wazhazhe-udsethe.
Cases
European Court of Justice, Application no. 13470/87, Otto Preminger-Institute v. Austria, judgment of 20 September 1994.
National Instruments
Racial and Religious Hatred Act 2006, 2006 Chapter 1, available at: https://www.legislation.gov.uk/ukpga/2006/1/schedule [accessed 28 February 2022].
Singapore Penal Code 1871, as amended, available at: https://sso.agc.gov.sg/Act/PC1871?WholeDoc=1#pr298- [accessed 28 February 2022].
International Instruments
Council of Europe, European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms, as amended by Protocols Nos. 11 and 14, 4 November 1950.
League of Arab States, Arab Charter on Human Rights, 15 September 1994.
Organization for American States, American Convention on Human Rights, “Pact of San Jose”, Costa Rica, 22 November 1969.
Organization of African Unity, African Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights, “Banjul Charter”, 27 June 1981.
UN General Assembly, Declaration on the Elimination of All Forms of Intolerance and of Discrimination Based on Religion or Belief, 25 November 1981.
UN General Assembly, International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, 16 December 1966.
UN General Assembly, International Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination, 21 December 1965.
UN General Assembly, Resolution 66/168 Adopted by the UN General Assembly: Elimination of all forms of intolerance and discrimination based on religion or belief, 11 April 2012, A/RES/66/168, available at: https://digitallibrary.un.org/record/724798?ln=en.
UN General Assembly, Resolution 76/250 Adopted by the UN General Assembly: Holocaust denial, 20 January 2022, A/RES/76/250, available at: https://digitallibrary.un.org/record/3956241?ln=en.
UN General Assembly, Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 10 December 1948.
UN General Assembly, United Nations Declaration on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination, 20 November 1963.
UN Human Rights Committee, CCPR General Comment No. 24: Issues Relating to Reservations Made upon Ratification or Accession to the Covenant or the Optional Protocols thereto, or in Relation to Declarations under Article 41 of the Covenant, 4 November 1994, CCPR/C/21/Rev.1/Add.6, available at: https://www.refworld.org/docid/453883fc11.html.
UN Human Rights Committee, General comment no. 34, Article 19, Freedoms of opinion and expression, 12 September 2011, CCPR/C/GC/34, available at: https://www.refworld.org/docid/4ed34b562.html.
UN Human Rights Council, Annual report of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights – Addendum – Report of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights on the expert workshops on the prohibition of incitement to national, racial or religious hatred, 11 January 2013, A/HRC/22/17/Add.4, available at: https://www.ohchr.org/Documents/Issues/Opinion/SeminarRabat/Rabat_draft_outcome.pdf.
UN Human Rights Council, Combating intolerance, negative stereotyping and stigmatization of, and discrimination, incitement to violence, and violence against persons based on religion or belief, 12 April 2011, A/HRC/RES/16/18, available at: https://www.refworld.org/docid/4db960f92.html.
Others
Article XIX, Camden Principles on Freedom of Expression and Equality (London, April 2009), available at: https://www.article19.org/data/files/pdfs/standards/the-camden-principles-on-freedom-of-expression-and-equality.pdf.
Lerner, Natan, “Freedom of expression and advocacy of group hatred: Incitement to hate crimes and religious hatred,” Conference room paper for the Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights’ expert seminar on the links between Articles 19 and 20 of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights: “Freedom of expression and advocacy of religious hatred that constitutes incitement to discrimination, hostility or violence” (2–3 October 2008): 89–96, available at: https://www.ohchr.org/Documents/Issues/Expression/ICCPR/Seminar2008/CompilationConferenceRoomPapers.pdf.
Medicins Sans Frontieres, “The Practical Guide to Humanitarian Law: Soft Law”, available at https://guide-humanitarian-law.org/content/article/3/soft-law/.
Office of the UN High Commissioner for Human Rights, “One-pager on “incitement to hatred”, available at: https://www.ohchr.org/Documents/Issues/Opinion/Articles19-20/ThresholdTestTranslations/Rabat_threshold_test.pdf.
United Nations Strategy and Plan of Action on Hate Speech, May 2019, available at: https://www.un.org/en/genocideprevention/documents/advising-and-mobilizing/Action_plan_on_hate_speech_EN.pdf.