1 Introduction
Children’s rights theory emanating from childhood studies has dealt extensively with child rights-infused research ethics, exploring questions concerning how to conduct ethically sensitive1 and agency-oriented research in studies with children.2 Such questions concern how to ‘give voice’ to children’s own lived experiences, and how to ensure active participation, influence, and consent in the production of knowledge with children.3 If child rights theory is to add an important layer to earlier philosophical, sociological, and anthropological works on children’s experiences of their rights, this must be achieved by invoking questions regarding the prevailing lack of social justice for children. This lack of social justice can be analysed through the concept of childism, which according to Elisabeth Young-Bruehl refers to prejudice against children that leads to structural discrimination and oppression against children. Analysing childism addresses aspects of power, discrimination, and marginalizing structures concerning children. The aim of this chapter is to explore resistance to the realization of children’s international human rights by arguing that these can be recognized as examples of age-based discrimination against children that disadvantage children, stemming from overlapping childist, racist, sexist, and ableist prejudice against children.
In recent years, childism has become firmly grounded in John Wall’s conceptualization, through which childism finds a parallel in feminism.6 Wall provides several arguments for not defining childism in relation to prejudice studies, as was done in earlier work by Elisabeth Young-Bruehl. While seemingly motivated by ambitions similar to those of this chapter – to challenge theories and research treating children as mere objects of adult agency when discussing their rights – Wall states that childism as conceptualized by Young-Bruehl ‘offers only a negative, deficit-oriented lens for studying childhoods, and not a positive, agentic one’.7 He further states that by defining childism as age-based prejudice and discrimination against children, ‘children are primarily framed as passive objects of adult socialization or harm’.8 Finally, Wall argues that ‘this deficit concept of childism likely deepens their oppression’ as it ‘assumes that only adults can act in child-empowering ways’.9
The aim and intentions of the two uses of childism seem aligned – to contribute to anti-racist and anti-sexist work – but the definitions of the concept differ. Scholars using childism as an equivalent to feminism might argue that childism is the start of a child rights movement. The flaw with that ideal, however, is how (adult) researchers may overlook the need to first address the structures of power and discrimination fed by potentially unreflected adult biases and prejudice against children. Just as critical-race theorists would problematize engaging in work on the Civil Rights Movement without naming racism, white ignorance, or white privilege, childism as an equivalent with sexism, racism, and ableism helps us problematize unaddressed forms of discrimination against children, adult ignorance, and adult privilege.
In parallel with using a critical conceptualization of childism, I need to refrain here from defining a ‘child’ (assigning particular abilities or characteristics to children or denying them certain capacities through such definitions). Additionally, in contrast to adult claims of empowering children’s voices, I employ childism to problematize the structures that risk hindering children from being heard and limiting their subjectivity. This work thus harmonizes with earlier child rights theory that seeks to reconceptualize the legal capacity
What, then, is the relation between the concepts of childism and adultism? Adultism refers to oppressive forms of adults’ power over children, while childism refers to the discursive practices that uphold adult norms and supremacy in society.11 We can see a similar distinction in how sexism supports male supremacy and hegemonic masculinity, as well as in the ways in which racist discourses sustain white supremacy.
If adults are not aware of their own complicity in a discriminatory system of limiting structures and beliefs against children, these structures and beliefs are left unproblematized. For example, not admitting that children face structural discrimination due to age means that adults can ignore the fact that children can be denied the most basic right to healthcare and mental healthcare, while hospitals and health institutions will generally require guardians’ consent – without which a child has no right to receive care.
Childism consists of prejudice, discrimination, or antagonism directed against someone who is between 0–18 years old, based on the belief that adults are superior. Childism defines persons by their lack of adult abilities and as inferior to adults with such abilities. On this basis, children are assigned or denied certain perceived abilities, skills, or character traits. Childist discourses work to keep children subordinate to adults through various forms of violence.12 Conceptualizing childism as a form of discrimination against children is meaningful in human rights theory because it speaks to how earlier critical
The use of the theory of intersectionality, according to Karl Hanson and Noam Peleg, ‘enables us to move beyond thinking about children’s minority status based on their age or assumed lack of or insufficient capacities’, and to include ‘the variations in children’s experiences relating to identity, personality, poverty, ethnicity, race, religion, gender, sexuality and social background, as well as the intersections of these elements’.14
The contribution of childism in this chapter adds to human rights theory and child rights theory in terms of the need to add the additional layer of age-based discrimination against children and children’s subordination to an intersectional lens on children’s rights. Its contribution could be measured by the extent to which childism will disrupt taken-for-granted assumptions in earlier work, where prejudice and negative attitudes towards children have not yet been unveiled.15
The aim of this chapter is to explore identified obstacles to the realization of children’s international human rights by arguing that such obstacles can be recognized as examples of age-based discrimination against children, stemming from overlapping childist, racist, sexist, and ableist prejudice against children. How may we understand the logic behind social obstacles to children’s human rights by naming childism as a system of prejudice and discrimination against children, and how could such understandings inform processes for a strengthened discourse on children’s rights?
2 Resistance against Children’s Rights: The Need for Theory on Childism
Michael Freeman16 argues that in order to take children’s rights seriously, a cultural revolution is needed in terms of adults’ attitudes toward children. Laura Lundy similarly notes the resistance to taking children’s rights seriously, in terms of how children could be rights-holders as ‘indicative of a wider problem: it appears to be perfectly acceptable to deny that children are, should or can be rights-holders when there are very few who would publicly assert that they do not ‘believe’ in human rights’.17
It is not enough merely to acknowledge a poor realization of children’s rights; as Lundy and Peleg note in the introduction to this volume, we need a conceptual framework to analyse why discursive negations of children’s rights persist.18 This chapter will not consider theories justifying the idea of children’s moral and legal rights – which for example have called for shifts in perspective from arguments of children’s capacity to their interests19 – or theories that base justification on the kind of rights that should be given to children.20 A conceptualization of childism is thus not a theory for justification, but rather a critical approach for analysing resistance among adults to the moral and legal rights of children. A theory that addresses systemic inequality and legislation against discrimination could generate a needed change in attitudes and beliefs in relation to children’s rights, for example making the violence against and oppressions of children visible as a form of discrimination. As noted, childism refers to prejudice against children that leads to structural discrimination, and through childist discourse, children are characterized as defined by their lack of adult abilities and, therefore, as inferior to adults.
The human-rights discourse has been informed by adult bias: ideas of the rights-holder have been defined according to adult normativity, human rights violations have been systematically analysed according to adult definitions,
In contrast to the UN Convention on the Elimination of All forms of Discrimination Against Women (cedaw) and the UN Convention on the Elimination of Racial Discrimination (cerd), the crc – at least not explicitly – does not aim towards the elimination of all forms of discrimination against children.22 Inadequacy of addressing age-based discrimination against children in the crc and when implementing human rights for children is a primary weakness in how we have thus far made meaning of children’s rights.
The Committee on the Rights of the Child has regarded children’s rights as a major challenge for all states and actors concerned, and ten years after the adoption of the crc, Paulo David lists six obstacles to its realization: 1) the idea of children’s rights rather than charity towards children challenges existing beliefs and attitudes held about children, 2) there is a lack of cooperation among the stakeholders responsible for realizing the rights of the child, 3) the child’s right to participation challenges traditional adult behaviour and parental values, 4) the right to education has not been adequately addressed in terms of how it encompasses discrimination in school, including protection against corporal punishment and harassment, 5) children’s civil rights are regarded by the adult community as a potential threat to adults’ rights, and 6) Member States have undermined the international acceptance of the crc through major reservations to the Convention.23 These obstacles are discussed further under the following six sub-headings in relation to childism. I give different examples of the reasons listed above and show that these obstacles are still relevant for unveiling possible instances of age-based discrimination against children, and thus illustrate the associated difficulties of realizing the crc.
2.1 Challenging Childist Views about Children
There is a need for a fundamental change of attitudes towards and beliefs about children in order to strengthen the discourse on children’s rights. Childist beliefs consist of ideas that children are inferior to adults and should
Within the human rights discourse, tensions between different minority groups and their rights claims can be further explored by studying the intersections of childism, racism, sexism, and ableism, in terms of how children’s rights are compromised due to these overlapping systems. In a study on sexual abuse and children with neuropsychiatric disorders, Lindblad and Lainpelto
2.2 Child Equity: The Need for Cooperation between Institutions31
The enforcement of children’s rights rests on the need and achievement of cross-sectional cooperation. Children’s rights are relevant to a wide range of professionals working with social services, education, healthcare, police departments, courts, media, housing services, recreational activities, sports, and many more fields. What is actualized in such cooperation are conflicting interpretations of child equality. Thus far overlooked, and something that would constitute a major focus in this cross-sectional realization of children’s
A notion of formal equality for children would presume children to be treated ‘as adults’ where ideas of corresponding duties to rights exist. Age-based discrimination against children cannot be adequately addressed in demands for formal equality, but instead through substantial equality, by which children are not treated ‘as adults’ but their child-specific differences are respected. Adult normative assumptions about who is seen as a rights subject do not work well in discussions concerning children’s rights because childhoods require additional rights related to children’s dependency on adults, and the fact that children cannot be required to act as duty bearers in light of their lack of social, physical, and economic resources. In comparable situations, children are not as ‘free’ as adults to act in a variety of instances where their rights might be actualized. Through childism, we acknowledge that there is widespread discrimination against children, and that they might be treated unfairly and unjustly because they are children – as individuals who are not listened to, not taken into consideration in matters that affect them, and not spoken with but informed of decisions already taken by concerned adults according to adult and parental interests and ideas. Children’s social conditions differ in crucial ways from that of the adult norm, and discussions on formal equality demand that children be treated ‘as adults’, ultimately leading (as we can see in the treatment of children as adults in court systems, and countless other examples) to their increased suffering.33
Courts would need to find ways to become more child equitable (fair and impartial), with the ambition of attaining fairness of treatment for children according to their specific condition. This may include equal or different treatment according to what would be considered equivalent in terms of children’s rights and in refraining from reifying childist stereotypes of children and their needs; it would also require questioning adultist norms of standardized
A conceptual shift from notions of formal equality toward a notion of child equity, I argue, is needed to take into consideration children’s social condition in society. Child equity is defined here as fairness of treatment for children according to their needs. This may include equal or different treatment according to what would be considered equivalent in terms of children’s rights and in avoiding reifying childist stereotypes and adultist norms. Child equity is thus based on ideas about substantive equality for children, which means that their social condition is taken into consideration when determining what is needed in order for their rights to be realized in different instances (conditions that may differ from those of adults – but not all adults – that may demand different treatment to acknowledge a child’s disadvantaged position).
Child equity in cases of child abuse and violence against children could mean involving the family and guardians of a child in preventative and/or rehabilitation measures instead of applying the adult framework of criminal law on children.34 In terms of legal justice, child equity would reflect children’s rights that ensure support for a child in risk environments to seek counselling for abusive communication and violent patterns at home. The dependency of a child, along with the pervasive influence on a child’s reasoning and actions that adults in their environment exercise, risk being overlooked as long as courts apply reasoning for criminal responsibility to children that is similar to the reasoning that applies to adults. In the UK and the US, for example, minors charged with serious crimes can be tried as adults before the law.35 Child equity in terms of the ‘best interests’ of the child could shift the focus in legal reasoning, from an individualistic to a more relational and community-based approach to rehabilitation. Imprisonment or fines are based on adult ideas about corrective justice that may not be as easily applicable when children are affected by the legal system, either in conflict with the law or as victims of crimes. Rehabilitation and supportive structures in society – connecting family counselling, trauma, and crisis management for victims and abusers,
2.3 Right to Participation: Challenging Prejudice against the Youngest Children
Children’s right to participation requires ‘deep social changes in attitudes, behaviour, and values’ of adults.37 When studying obstacles to implementing Article 12 on children’s right to participation, Rebecca Stern looks at ‘traditional attitudes’ when Member States explain inaction, and she comes to the conclusion that a focus on cultural attitudes overshadows ‘the existing attitudes toward children in Western states’.38 I find this problematization interesting, as here Stern addresses the way in which Western states may overlook their own attitudes toward children that hinder children’s realization of their rights in their own states.
Prevailing arguments that Article 12 of the crc applies solely to older children, and which cannot be enforced for younger children and infants, rest on childist attitudes and beliefs connected to children’s abilities at different ages. How are children supposed to be heard in issues affecting them when prejudices about children – that they cannot reason, do not know what is best for them, are not to be trusted, and change their mind constantly – risk being left unchallenged?39
The child according to the UN Committee on the Rights of the Child, is ‘able to form views from the youngest age, even when she or he may be unable to express them verbally’; thus a full implementation of Article 12
The enforcement of Article 12 – on the right for the child to be included and to be heard – requires adults to adjust their communication and attentive listening to individuals who do not excel in oralism. Appreciating diversity in abilities requires changed attitudes and beliefs about children who deviate from the adult norm and about children with disabilities. Interpreting the responsibility of adults to realize Article 12 in the crc by developing knowledge on age-based discrimination could enhance the child’s right to be heard, especially in securing the ability of individuals below the age of 12 to be listened to on their own terms.
The idea that children are not interested in social justice issues may lead adults to neglect to inform children about their rights.41 In what ways do such beliefs prevent adults from engaging children in conversations about discrimination and social injustice? Reflecting on how prejudice challenges the implementation of children’s rights can lead to more ethically sensitive relations between adults and children and to increased instances of using expert groups of children in politics and legislation, which in turn can lead to interventions other than those that adults may have thought of. Reflection on how prejudice against children leads to undue power imbalance in institutions that deal with children’s rights can create venues for more resources in the field of implementing children’s rights and freedoms. This progress could be achieved if children themselves take part in the process.
2.4 The Right to Education as Including Protection against Age-Based Harassment and Assault
Another obstacle to the realization of children’s rights is the way in which rights to something might foreclose the rights of a child in the exercise of that same right. Children’s right to cost-free education is one of their fundamental rights, but while the right to education is stated in the crc, the discrimination and prejudice children face in education is not addressed in the Convention.42
When exploring children’s experiences as rights subjects in education, the existence of corporal punishment, bullying, and inattentiveness to children’s mental health should be reformulated as different forms of discrimination against children in need of more structural and systemic analysis. Age-based violence includes violent acts where children are primarily or exclusively the victims, and violence against children and youths connected to normative understandings of their age.
The right to education encompasses not only access to, but quality of education, and rights in education. Access may be hindered along socio-economic lines, quality may be compromised, and rights in education overlooked. The negative belief that children do not know what they need or what is best for them risks undermining children’s own influence during their time in school.
Protection for children against direct and indirect age discrimination ‘applied in education and children’s services would ensure that the views and experiences of children are taken into account during the development of these’44 and emphasizes the need for ‘reasonable adjustments to enable equal access to public buildings and public transport’.45 Direct age discrimination against children refers to when a child is treated less favourably – differently and worse – due to age, for example by being denied services. Indirect discrimination against children includes instances where a child is treated in the same way as everyone else, but still suffers unequal opportunities due to age, gender,
2.5 Children’s Rights Threatening Adult Rights? An Anti-childist Lens on Adult Power
While there might be general support for the idea of children’s rights, ‘political parties, religious groups, teacher’s organizations, parents associations’ are groups that may feel ‘that recognizing rights of children will infringe on their own rights’.46 As noted by Susan Moller Okin,47 there could be inherent tensions between different rights claims, and she discusses tensions between multiculturalist and feminist rights discourses. An additional layer that requires further discernment is the matter of rights tensions between anti-racist, anti-sexist, and anti-childist efforts to address social injustices.
As sex, race, ethnicity, language, religion, and other areas are mentioned as grounds for discrimination in international conventions on human rights, and as age – usually referring to the elderly – has not included age discrimination against children, these grounds are more likely to be taken into consideration in circumstances that might also affect the rights of the child. Special protection against discrimination for indigenous people, migrants, women, and persons with disabilities are all covered in UN conventions. Due to adultism – that is, adults being in power over children in degrading ways – these discrimination grounds risk being read as applicable only to adults in relation to services and rights. As noted earlier, the crc contains no definition of age discrimination against children.
It is important for childism not to be treated as just another aspect of a feminist or multicultural approach. Issues that may benefit gender equality do not necessarily harmonize with respect for the individual child. Anti-sexist discourses in custody cases, for example, do not necessarily represent the rights of the child. Adult perspective in courts – regarding the rights, interests, and needs of adults primarily – would give precedence to concerned adults’ ideas of what would be in the best interest of the child. Anti-childist lenses on adultist norms – norms that assign adults the status of being powerful and authoritative while disregarding children’s voices, experiences, and different conditions – may question the interests of a parent, even though such an approach
Acknowledging that a minority group may be limited in the exercise of cultural and religious rights calls for special protection, but the flip side of such protection could lead adults to force children who are unable to provide ‘full, free and informed consent’ to undergo traditions harmful to their dignity.48 When examining legislation and policies that may discriminate against children, the heterogeneity of children and their double (and sometimes multiple) marginalization must be acknowledged. Should a girl have the right to be heard and challenge adult women’s expectations on her? Should a boy have the right to do the same against hegemonic masculinity? These are questions that anti-childist lenses on the rights of the child actualize when rights claims are viewed solely through the perspective of the right to culture, religion, or tradition. The attitudes of the adult community, including adult perspectives on marginalized groups, may hinder the full realization of the rights of the child because due to childism, children as a heterogenous group – consisting of all other minority groups – are nonetheless marginalized within every minority group.
Adult authority over children can have violating consequences when serving childist interests and beliefs of children. Anna Kaldal and Pernilla Leviner argue in a study from 2007 that it is important to recognize that parental rights and children’s rights may conflict in both public and civil law, and they emphasize the importance of allowing social services to interview children without the presence or consent of the parents in such procedures.49
2.6 Major Reservations to Children’s Rights: The Need for Intersectional Analysis
Although the crc has received 197 ratifications since its adoption in 1989, major reservations to the crc dilute its international protection for children and lower the intended ambitions of its articles. However, reservations to the crc alone will not provide an overall picture of children’s marginalization in the human rights discourse. Children as a heterogenous group actualize the framework of international rights examined through reservations to the cedaw, cerd, and the UN Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities crpd, as well as the conventions on migrants’ rights and indigenous peoples’ rights.
By drawing on parallels with racism, sexism, and ableism, we may gain knowledge about how discrimination against children encompasses several intersecting systems of oppression. Children and youth, due to the interlocking systems of neo-colonialism, racism, sexism, ableism, and childism, are the first to experience how the subordination of race, class, gender, and abilities intersect. They are among the first to feel the effects of cuts in social services, healthcare, education, and other welfare provisions in a society that is supposed to provide the most vulnerable groups with an economic and social safety net.51 Thus, only a plurality of children’s voices on social injustice will adequately indicate where interventions are most relevant, and where human rights, on both societal and family levels, have not been realized.
3 Concluding Remarks
In this chapter, I have argued that 1) in order to challenge existing views about children, we need to be aware that anti-sexist and anti-racist lenses on human rights do not necessarily harmonize with anti-childist lenses on human rights that confront adultist norms; 2) cooperation between institutions for children’s rights is not helped by a formal notion of age equality that disregards the difference between children and adults, whereas child equity questions how adultism as a power structure is maintained through adult and ableist normativity; 3) the right to participation requires changes in how social, legal, and political processes that affect children have been handled thus far in order to accommodate differences and enable children’s decision-making capacity; 4) addressing the barriers faced by children in education require age-based harassment, assault, and discrimination against children in school to be named and faced; 5) patriarchal hierarchies that have denied women political agency by premising laws supporting political freedoms and autonomy on men alone can be analysed to shed light on discriminatory discourses of patriarchal structures that today deny children civil rights through paternalistic attitudes toward children’s voices; and 6) resistance against the rights of the child in the form of reservations to the crc indicate that, due to childism children are not regarded as rights subjects. Studies on racism, sexism, and ableism have shown how biased use of language serves to perpetuate the idea that not all human beings are equal or regarded as legal subjects with rights and freedoms.
A conceptual move from formal equality to child equity will enable analysis of the extent to which ‘child friendly’, ‘child adapted’, and ‘best interests’ initiatives and standards conceal more than paternalistic perspectives. Child
This normative conceptualization needs to be tested through future empirical studies on instances of age discrimination against children, and statistics are needed on crimes targeting children (for example, crimes in the home, where we might encounter the problem of hidden statistics, and unfair treatment by social services of children that could be labelled as discrimination). Further studies into systemic childism would also provide us with a framework for understanding poverty and other social inequalities among children.
See Christensen, P., and Prout, A., ‘Working with Ethical Symmetry in Social Research with Children’, Childhood 9 (2002): 477–97.
See Bessell, S., ‘Rights-Based Research with Children: Principles and Practice’. In Skelton, T., Evans, R., and Holt, V. (Ed.), Methodological Approaches Geographies of Children and Young People, vol. 2 (Singapore: Springer, 2017): 223–40.
Aitken, S., Lund, R., and Kjornholt, A., ‘Why Children? Why Now?’, Children’s Geographies 1–2, no. 3 (2007): 3–14; Punch, S., ‘Research with Children: The Same or Different from Research with Adults?’, Childhood 9, no. 3 (2002): 321–41; Tisdall, K. and Punch, S., ’Not so New? Looking Critically at Childhood Studies‘, Children’s Geographies 10, no. 3 (2012): 249–64; Reynolds, P., Nieuwenhuys, O., and Hanson, K., ’Refractions of Children’s Rights in Development Practice: A View from Anthropology’, Childhood 13, no. 3 (2006): 291–302. See also Karlsson, Chapter 10 in this volume.
One can find parallels between childist, racist, sexist and ableist prejudice that disadvantage children.
Young-Bruehl, E. The Anatomy of Prejudices (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1996); Childism: Confronting Prejudice against Children (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2012).
Wall, J., ‘From Childhood Studies to Childism: Reconstructing the Scholarly and Social Imaginations’, Children’s Geographies 20, no. 83 (2022): 257–270.
Wall, J. (2022), 7.
Ibid., 7.
Ibid., 7.
See Bach, M., and Kerzner, L., A New Paradigm for Protecting Autonomy and the Right to Legal Capacity: Advancing Substantive Equality for Persons with Disabilties through Law, Policy and Practice (Law Commission of Ontario, October 2010); Federle, K., ‘On the Road to Reconceiving Rights for Children: A Postfeminist Analysis of the Capacity Principle’, DePaul Law Review 42, no. 3 (1993): 983–1028.
Adultism is here referred to as the order of power of adult supremacy whereby adults hold privileges, status and primary power of moral authority, property and social privilege. Childism consists of the prejudice and discriminatory structures that serve to uphold adult order of power, as sexism serves to uphold the power of male supremacy and racism serves to uphold the power of white supremacy.
Violence here includes epistemic violence which concerns the harm caused children due to how adults speak about them in belittling and negative and stereotypical ways. Epistemic injustice refers to how some people, children for example, are not seen as valid sources of knowledge, giving testimony of injustices, drawing on Fricker, M. Epistemic injustice: Power and the ethics of knowing. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).
See Article 1 in the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women, cedaw, and Article 1 in the Convention on the Elimination of Racial Discrimination, cerd.
Hanson, K. and Peleg, N., ‘Waiting for Children’s Rights Theory’, The International Journal of Children’s Rights 28, no. 1 (2020): 15–35, 23.
Contrarily, one could claim that labelling children as a minority group and naming stereotypes against children reinforce such categorizations that we might want to move beyond through notions of uniqueness. However, not acknowledging how children are already treated unfairly due to prejudice and stereotyping would be expressing adult ignorance about children’s subordination. Discussions about adult-child relationality that neglect power, and when faced with questions concerning social justice, thus risk obscuring privilege.
Freeman, M. Children’s Rights, vol. I, 2 vols. (Wiltshire: Ashgate Darmouth, 2004).
Laura Lundy, ‘Editorial: A Lexicon for Research on International Children’s Rights in Troubled Times’, International Journal of Children’s Rights, no. 27 (2019): 595.
See Laura Lundy and Noam Peleg in this volume.
See Tobin, J., Justifying Children’s Rights’, The International Journal of Children’s Rights 21, no. 3 (2013): 395–441.
See Wald, M., ‘Children’s Rights: A Framework for Analysis’. In Freeman, M. (Ed.), Children’s Rights, vol. I, 2 vols. (USA: Ashgate Darmouth, 2004): 113–140; Freeman, M. (2004).
See
See Daly, A., Thorburn Stern, R. & Leviner, P., UN Convention on the Rights of the Child, Article 2 and Discrimination on the basis of Childhood: The crc Paradox?, Nordic Journal of International Law, Volume 91, 2022, s. 419–452.
David, P., ‘Implementing the Rights of the Child: Six Reasons Why the Human Rights of Children Remain a Constant Challenge’, International Review of Education 48, no. 3–4 (2002): 259–263.
Sköld, J., Sandin, B., and Schiratzki, J., ‘Historical Justice through Redress Schemes?’, Scandinavian Journal of History 45, no. 2 (2020): 178–201.
Sköld, Sandin, and Schiratzki (2020), 182.
Ibid., 179.
Ibid., 180.
Adami, R. and Dineen, K., ‘Discourses of Childism: How covid-19 Has Unveiled Prejudice, Discrimination and Social Injustice against Children in the Everyday’, The International Journal of Children’s Rights 29 (2021): 353–370.
Lindblad, F. and Lainpelto, K., ‘Sexual Abuse Allegations by Children with Neuropsychiatric Disorders’, Journal of Child Sexual Abuse, no. 20 (2011): 182–195, 183.
Lindblad, F. and Lainpelto, K. (2011), 183.
Child equity is a structural and systemic concept that focuses the process for reaching equality when a system or structure in itself is unfair, biased, and discriminatory. See similar distinctions in relation to other forms of discrimination such as racial equity and gender equity;
See Zillén, K., Chapter 5 in this volume; Leviner, P., and Holappa T. Chapter 2 in this volume; Holmqvist, A. ‘The Rights to Physical Integrity for Child Patients Jeopardized in Health and Medical Care?: A Blind Spot in the Patient Act and a Non-Issue for Patient Organisations in Sweden’, The International Journal of Children’s Rights 30, no.1 (2022): 98–119.
See
For further moral discussions on similar issues of taking into consideration the rights of the child in legal penalties, see Bülow, W., ‘The Harms Beyond Imprisonment: Do We Have Special Moral Obligations towards the Families and Children of Prisoners?’, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 17, no.4 (2014): 775–789. On the importance of including moral considerations in terms of social justice other than imprisonment and punishment, see Vedananda, N., ‘Learning to Heal: Integrating Restorative Justice into Legal Education’, New York Law School Law Review 64 (2019/20): 95–114.
See the Juvenile Law Center,
For a legal discussion about the best interests of the child and the limitations thereof in criminal proceedings, see Kaldal, A., ‘Barnets Bästa Vid Våld Mot Barn – Kan Eller Bör En Förälder Ges Behandling i Stället För Straff?’. In Åhman, K., Leviner, P., and, Zillén, K. (Eds.), Barnkonventionen i praktiken. Rättsliga utmaningar och möjligheter (Stockholm: Norstedts Juridik, 2020): 331–356.
David, P. (2002), 260.
Thorburn Stern, R., Implementing Article 12 of the UN Convention on the Rights of the Child: Participation, Power and Attitudes, vol. 2, Stockholm Studies in Child Law and Children’s Rights (Leiden: Brill, 2017), 163.
See similar arguments by Kaldal, A., Chapter 3 in this volume.
UN Committee on the Rights of the Child. General comment No.12 (2009): The right of the child to be heard. crc/c/gc/12, para. 9.
See for example the empirical study by Klara Dolk about adult-steered child influence in preschool settings, and how child participation was limited to deciding on which transport to take for school trips, not on issues concerning social justice and discrimination; Dolk, Bångstyriga Barn: Makt, Normer Och Delaktighet i Förskolan [Unruly Children: Power, Norms and Participation in the Preeschool] (Stockholm: Ordfront, 2013).
If we read Article 2 crc together with Article 29 crc, discrimination facing children due to their own position (unrelated to their family, such as sexuality) and age-based discrimination is still not covered in the crc. For a more progressive reading of the crc, we can turn to the Committee on the Rights of the Child. General Comment No.1 (2001) Article 29 (1): The aims of education crc/gc/2001/1 17April 2001 which states that ‘Discrimination on the basis of any of the grounds listed in article 2 of the Convention, whether it is overt or hidden, offends the human dignity of the child and is capable of undermining or even destroying the capacity of the child to benefit from educational opportunities’.
Isenström, L., ‘Children as Growing Rights Subjects – The Significance of Teachers’ Actions’, The International Journal of Children’s Rights 28, no. 2 (2020): 258–287.
Young Equals, Making the Case: Why Children Should Be Protected from Age Discrimination and How It Can Be Done, Proposals for the Equality Bill (UK: Children’s Rights Alliance for England, 2009), 6.
Young Equals, 7.
David, P. (2002), 261.
Moller Okin, S., Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women? (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999).
‘Harmful practices are persistent practices and behaviours that are grounded on discrimination on the basis of sex, gender, age and other grounds as well as multiple and/or intersecting forms of discrimination that often involve violence and cause physical and/or psychological harm or suffering’. UN Committee on the Elimination of Discrimination against Women and UN Committee on the Rights of the Child. Joint general comment No.31 of the Committee on the Elimination of Discrimination against Women and No.18 of the Committee on the Rights of the Child on harmful practices, 4 November 2014, cedaw/c/gc/31-crc/c/gc/18, 6.
We have seen a strengthening of the child’s right to be heard individually in the Swedish legislation the last decade, which may align with changes in beliefs and attitudes towards children over time. How the child’s right to participation is to be understood is continuously debated and the potential conflict of parental rights and interests versus children’s rights in such instances is still important to note. Kaldal and Leviner (2007). ‘Silencing the conflict of interests between parental rights and the rights of the child – legal requirements for the social services to interview children’, Scandinavian Studies in Law 50, (2007): 381–392. See Kaldal chapter 3 in this volume.
For further discussions on patriarchal violence against children, see Adami and Dineen, ‘Discourses of Childism: How covid-19 has Unveiled Prejudice, Discrimination and Social Injustice against Children in the Everyday’ The International Journal of Children’s Rights 29, no.2 (2021): 353–370.
See Hill Collins, P., and Bilge, S., Intersectionality (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2016).
See for example
References
Adami, Rebecca, and Katy Dineen. 2021. “Discourses of Childism: How covid-19 Has Unveiled Prejudice, Discrimination and Social Injustice against Children in the Everyday”, The International Journal of Children’s Rights 29: 1–17.
Aitken, Stuart, Ragnhild Lund, and Anne Trine Kjornholt. 2007. “Why Children? Why Now?”, Children’s Geographies 1–2(3): 3–14.
Bach, Michael, and Lana Kerzner. 2010. “A New Paradigm for Protecting Autonomy and the Right to Legal Capacity: Advancing Substantive Equality for Persons with Disabilities through Law, Policy and Practice”, Law Commission of Ontario, October.
Bessell, Sharon. 2017. “Rights-Based Research with Children: Principles and Practice”, in Tracey Skelton, Ruth Evans, and Louise Holt (Eds.), Methodological Approaches Geographies of Children and Young People, 223–40. Singapore: Springer.
Bülow, William. 2014. “The Harms Beyond Imprisonment: Do We Have Special Moral Obligations towards the Families and Children of Prisoners?”, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 17(4): 775–89.
Christensen, Pia, and Alison Prout. 2002. “Working with Ethical Symmetry in Social Research with Children”, Childhood 9: 477–97.
Daly, Aoife, Rebecca Thorburn Stern, & Pernilla Leviner. 2022. “UN Convention on the Rights of the Child, Article 2 and Discrimination on the basis of Childhood: The crc Paradox?”, Nordic Journal of International Law 91: 419–452.
David, Paulo. 2002. “Implementing the Rights of the Child: Six Reasons Why the Human Rights of Children Remain a Constant Challenge”, International Review of Education 48(3–4): 259–63.
Dolk, Klara. 2013. Bångstyriga Barn: Makt, Normer Och Delaktighet i Förskolan [Unruly Children: Power, Norms and Participation in the Preeschool]. Stockholm: Ordfront.
Federle, Katherine. 1993. “On the Road to Reconceiving Rights for Children: A Postfeminist Analysis of the Capacity Principle”, DePaul Law Review 42(3): 983–1028.
Freeman, Michael. 2004. Children’s Rights. Vol. I. 2 vols. Wiltshire: Ashgate Darmouth.
Hanson, Karl, and Noam Peleg. 2020. “Waiting for Children’s Rights Theory”, The International Journal of Children’s Rights 28(1): 15–35.
Isenström, Lisa. 2020. “Children as Growing Rights Subjects – The Significance of Teachers’ Actions”, The International Journal of Children’s Rights 28(2): 258–87.
Kaldal, Anna. 2020. “Barnets Bästa Vid Våld Mot Barn – Kan Eller Bör En Förälder Ges Behandling i Stället För Straff?”, in Karin Åhman, Pernilla Leviner, and Kavot Zillén (Eds.), Barnkonventionen i Praktiken: Rättsliga Utmaningar Och Möjligheter, 331–56. Nordstedts Juridik.
Lindblad, Frank, and Katrin Lainpelto. 2011. “Sexual Abuse Allegations by Children with Neuropsychiatric Disorders”, Journal of Child Sexual Abuse 20: 182–95.
Lundy, Laura. 2019. Editorial: “A Lexicon for Research on International Children’s Rights in Troubled Times”, International Journal of Children’s Rights 27: 595–601.
Moller Okin, Susan. 1999. Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women? Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Punch, Samantha. 2002. “Research with Children: The Same or Different From Research with Adults?”, Childhood 9(3): 321–41.
Reynolds, Pamela, Olga Nieuwenhuys, and Karl Hanson. 2006. “Refractions of Children’s Rights in Development Practice: A View From Anthropology”, Childhood 13(3): 291–302.
Sköld, Johanna, Bengt Sandin, and Johanna Schiratzki. 2020. “Historical Justice through Redress Schemes?”, Scandinavian Journal of History 45(2): 178–201.
Stern, Rebecca. 2017. Implementing Article 12 of the UN Convention on the Rights of the Child: Participation, Power and Attitudes. Vol. 2. Stockholm Studies in Child Law and Children’s Rights. Leiden: Brill.
Tisdall, Kay, and Samantha Punch. 2012. “Not so New? Looking Critically at Childhood Studies”, Children’s Geographies 10(3): 249–64.
Tobin, John. 2013. “Justifying Children’s Rights”, The International Journal of Children’s Rights 21(3): 395–441.
Vedananda, Natasha S. 2019. “Learning to Heal: Integrating Restorative Justice into Legal Education”, New York Law School Law Review 64: 95–114.
Wald, Michael. 2004. “Children’s Rights: A Framework for Analysis”, in Michael Freeman (Ed.), Children’s Rights, I: 113–40. USA: Ashgate Darmouth.
Wall, John. 2019. “From Childhood Studies to Childism: Reconstructing the Scholarly and Social Imaginations”, Children’s Geographies 20(3): 257–270.
Young Equals. 2009. “Making the Case: Why Children Should Be Protected from Age Discrimination and How It Can Be Done, Proposals for the Equality Bill”. UK: Children’s Rights Alliance for England.
Young-Bruehl, Elisabeth. 2012. Childism: Confronting Prejudice against Children. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Young-Bruehl, Elisabeth. (1996). The Anatomy of Prejudices. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
United Nations Committee on the Elimination of Discrimination against Women (cedaw) and the UN Committee on the Rights of the Child (crc). Joint general comment No.31 of the Committee on the Elimination of Discrimination against Women and No. 18 of the Committee on the Rights of the Child on harmful practices. cedaw/c/gc/31-crc/c/gc/18 (4 November 2014).
United Nations Convention on the Elimination of Racial Discrimination cerd.
United Nations Committee on the Rights of the Child. General comment No. 12 (2009). The right of the child to be heard. crc/c/gc/12 (20 July 2009).