Abstract
We examine here the distribution of morphological case (e.g., accusative, genitive, and dative) among object complements of monotransitive verbs in Classical Greek (CG). Accusative-marked objects are generally deemed to be direct objects (DO), while dative- and genitive-marked complements are typically treated as syntactically or semantically separate, sometimes being treated as objects bearing exceptional/semantic/quirky case and sometimes being analyzed simply as indirect objects (IO). Restricting our focus to verbs which have a single complement, we can observe that the distribution of accusative (ACC), genitive (GEN), and dative (DAT) marking on these in CG is atypical. CG productively places DAT and GEN NP s alongside ACC NP s as a singular complement to monotransitive verbs, allowing them to occupy what would normally be thought of as the direct-object position, but for their GEN and DAT case-marking. We offer an analysis of these verbs and their semanto-syntactic collocations, seeking to understand what is communicated through the marking of either ACC, GEN, or DAT on complement NP s. We find first that ACC and GEN-marking verbs interact in a transitivity hierarchy, being set apart by the change of state of the object (following an analysis laid out by Luraghi 2010). Second, we find that DAT-marking verbs exist outside of this hierarchy, making up their own productive class of interaction verbs, those which denote a complex series of overlapping subevents (first laid out by Blume 1998). Thus, this study offers an analysis of a wide array of ACC, GEN, and DAT case-marking verbs collected from a corpus of nine Classical Greek authors, providing the first statistical analysis of the conundrum of ‘atypical’ case-selection patterns of Classical Greek monotransitive verbs, wherein non-ACC cases are used to mark what appear to be DO s.
1 Introduction
We examine here the distribution of morphological case (e.g., accusative, genitive, and dative) among object complements of monotransitive verbs in Classical Greek (CG). Accusative-marked objects are generally deemed to be direct objects (DO), while dative- and genitive-marked complements are sometimes treated as syntactically or semantically distinct, sometimes being considered as objects bearing exceptional/semantic/quirky case, sometimes being analyzed as indirect objects (IO), and sometimes having the status of obliques. Restricting our focus to verbs that have a single complement, we can observe that the distribution of accusative- (ACC), genitive- (GEN), and dative- (DAT) marking on these in CG is confounding. CG productively places DAT and GEN NP s alongside ACC NP s as a potential singular complement to monotransitive verbs, allowing them to occupy what would normally be thought of as the direct-object position, but for their GEN and DAT case-marking (see ex. 1–2).
(1)
καὶ
πολλ -ῶν
ἦρξε
τριήρ -ων and
many-gen.pl
command.aor.act.3s
war.ship-gen.pl
‘and he commanded many war ships.’
Isocrates, Against Alcibiades 1.14.36
(2)
ὅτι
μετ᾽
ἀνδρ -ῶν
νῦν
ἀρίστ -ων …
τοῖς πολεμί -οις
μάχεσθε that
with
men-gen.pl
now
best-gen.pl
the enemy-dat.pl
fight.2pl.ipfv.act
‘that you are now with the best men … fighting the enemies.’
Lysias, Against Eratosthenes 12.94
Not only is there a class of verbs in CG which productively take GEN and DAT direct objects, but there is also a class of verbs which may optionally alternate between ACC and GEN. Therefore, the attested verb-classes are as follows: i) ACC-Object verbs, ii) GEN-Object verbs, iii) DAT-Object verbs, and iv) ACC/GEN-Object verbs. The present research explores the first three, seeking to understand what is communicated in the selection of either an ACC-, GEN-, or DAT-marked DO.
Greek grammars generally tend to analyze GEN and DAT objects as traditional ‘indirect objects’ and apply these explanations across the whole of Ancient Greek (AG, 900 BCE–500 CE). However, it is clear that a more complex approach is required (and one that considers the distribution of exceptional object case in a more circumscribed time period), if we are to fully understand the range of syntagmatic roles assigned to GEN and DAT objects. Here, Grimm’s (2011) point stands out: “despite the frequency with which labels such as ‘dative’ are used, often what is termed a dative in one language only shares a few of the functions of a case in another language with the same label dative” (517). Though the AG GEN and DAT nominals certainly bear semantic roles that are similar to analogously marked nominals in other languages—e.g., GEN complements sometimes being partitive and DAT sometimes serving to mark locatives—there is more to be said about them both, particularly when they mark complements of transitive verbs. As an effort in this direction, we investigate this phenomenon through a corpus-driven analysis that seeks to reveal the precise semantic roles of DO s marked with one of these three cases, ACC, GEN, and DAT, tying the nuances of difference to the meaning of the verbs that select them.
The data collected and analyzed in the present study confirms that Luraghi’s (2010) Transitivity Hierarchy makes correct predictions regarding the case-marking of some objects, such that objects of high transitivity verbs get ACC case and those of medium transitivity verbs get GEN case. In this regard, we agree with Luraghi that high transitivity correlates with Change of State [COS] of the direct object, and that ACC objects undergo a COS, but GEN objects do not. In explaining the distribution of DAT objects, however, we find reason to believe that a Transitivity Hierarchy cannot fully account for them, and that additional factors are involved. With respect to these, it turns out that verbs’ selection of DAT objects is best explained in terms of Blume’s (1998) interaction verbs.
In accounting for the distribution of object case, we provide a more insightful analysis of the conditions under which GEN case and DAT case are assigned to the objects of monotransitive verbs than that which is typically given in traditional grammars. These grammars generally and inaccurately tend to claim that all GEN objects are partitive and mostly ignore the distribution of DAT objects (Smyth & Messing 1956, Hansen & Quinn 1992, van Emde Boas et al. 2019).
This study is intended to present an initial investigation into the questions here posed, focusing on the behavior of classes (i–iii). Given what we have determined about these classes, we propose that these findings may subsequently be taken up to explore the final, alternating, ACC/GEN class of verbs, though we do not yet tackle that subject herein. Section 2 reviews prior work on this topic, primarily that of Luraghi (2003, 2010), and situates the present research within the framework that she lays out. Section 3 then presents the data domain and methodology that figure in our study. Section 4 introduces Dowty’s (1991) conception of Proto-Roles and discusses the usefulness of these, particularly in terms of the goals of the present study. Section 5 investigates the behavior of the non-alternating classes (i.e. verbs that consistently select one case for their direct objects), presenting first some preliminary (pre-statistical) observations, followed by statistical results of our examination of the distribution of ACC, GEN, and DAT case-marking on objects. We present these first through the lens of Luraghi’s featural analysis, and then using a revised set of features, and a revised approach which we contend yields superior results. A conclusion, in section 6, provides some directions for future research, given these findings, especially regarding the final class of ACC/GEN alternating verbs, and also makes suggestions for broadening this research to include a wider range of the historical stages of Ancient Greek.
2 Review of previous research
Outside of Classical Greek (CG) pedagogical grammars, there have been few linguistic treatments of CG case assignment or argument structure, particularly in reference to the atypical behavior of dative and genitive direct objects. A largely general description of the distribution of ACC, DAT, and GEN case is provided in Luraghi 2003, with a more specific description of their distribution on direct objects in Luraghi 2010, equating this with semantic “levels of transitivity”. Lavidas (2009) also provides a comprehensive, diachronic overview of verb transitivity, from Homeric to Modern Greek.
According to Luraghi (2010: 64), ACC objects (those whose semantic role is characterized as “theme”) are “wholly affected patients, which undergo a change of state” and which canonically occur with the most highly transitive verbs. It is claimed that ACC case is nearly always assigned in highly transitive contexts, and that GEN case is exceptionally assigned to objects having a partitive interpretation. In Luraghi’s terms, GEN objects that are complements of highly transitive verbs are “partitive genitive” and thereby seen to be less affected (although still “somewhat” affected) than are ACC objects. This analysis mirrors the explanation put forth by most pedagogical grammars, claiming that GEN objects are partitives and are relics of GEN indirect objecthood (Hansen & Quinn 1992, van Emde Boas et al. 2019). Verbs subcategorized for DAT objects are, according to Luraghi, even less transitive than those subcategorized for ACC or GEN objects.
Luraghi’s proposed Transitivity Hierarchy, intended to account for the mapping of verb meaning to case, distinguishes three levels of transitivity: High transitivity (HT), medium transitivity (MT), and low transitivity (LT). These levels are distinguished on basis of (i) whether the verb’s object undergoes a Change of State (COS), and (ii) whether the object is affected.
Table 1
Luraghi’s (2010) Transitivity Hierarchy
Change of State (COS) |
Affected |
Case-assignment |
|
---|---|---|---|
High transitivity |
+ |
+ |
ACC |
Medium transitivity |
– |
+ |
GEN |
Low transitivity |
– |
– |
DAT |
Luraghi (2003, 2010) presents her result as an analysis of Ancient Greek (AG), a corpus spanning some 1400 years (encompassing the period from 900 BCE to 500 CE). However, because her analysis utilizes data principally from Classical Greek (~500–300 BCE), it runs the risk of trying to capture generalizations about varieties of Greek that are separated by many centuries, if not a millennium.1 Utilizing a range of data that is as diachronically distant as Old English and Modern English can lead to a conflation of meaning-case correlations that may not be consistent across time. Accordingly, we first aim here to test Luraghi’s Hierarchy against a much smaller stretch of Ancient Greek, i.e., over only Classical Greek texts. Since our study examines a corpus spanning only 2 centuries (~500–300 BCE), it is likely to be systematically more consistent than one based on a period of language which spans over a millennium.
Second, as explored in further detail below in Section 5, we find reason to doubt the reliability of using Affectedness as a feature in this hierarchy, depending as it does on the same kinds of semantic changes better marked by COS alone. Finally, where Luraghi (2010) only considers direct object semantic properties in framing the Transitivity Hierarchy (COS and Affectedness), the present study expands the range of semantic properties considered in the analysis by examining all the Subject and Object Proto-role Properties proposed in Dowty (1991).
Much like Luraghi, Lavidas (2009) also notes the importance of COS as a property of objects that correlates with ACC case-marking and indicates enhanced transitivity. Lavidas also provides an overview of language change across the historical development of Greek, with a particular focus on how verbs’ meanings condition object case. Lavidas 2009 is specifically focused on the mechanisms by which verbal transitivity and meaning change over time, providing an overview of verbal transitivity across the development of Greek. Therein it is claimed that verbs taking COS object arguments represent the “central or prototypal class of transitive verbs,” (p. 2), in agreement with Luraghi (2003, 2010). Pivotally, Lavidas also recognizes the important role that verb meaning plays in determining the morphological and syntactic structures that accompany the use of any verb. Lavidas is concerned in particular with understanding changes in DO case-marking across periods of AG—especially with respect to the semantic roles that correlate with GEN and DAT DO case-marking. He notes the tendency toward an extension of ACC case, which is gradually extended to objects with semantic roles previously marked by GEN, DAT, or various prepositions. It should be noted that, unlike Luraghi, Lavidas does not stipulate any hierarchy for Greek verbal transitivity, taking transitivity as he does not to be “a unified phenomenon” (p. 9) which can be described in such terms (even though he does take COS verbs to be the most prototypically transitive).
Of case-marking in Classical Greek. Lavidas does not address the plethora of available case-markings for DO s, saying only (p. 64) that
… the accusative case was the usual case of the subjects of infinitives and the typical case for direct objects; therefore, the accusative case was a particularly frequent case. Some verbs idiosyncratically governed objects in other cases, of course. The dative case marked indirect objects, arguments that are interested in the action described by the verb, possession with the verb ‘to be,’ agents with some passive verbs, or partial effect on the object.
So, while Lavidas (2009) provides a foundational description of diachronic changes to transitive verbal constructions, he does not contribute much to an understanding of why CG marks particular DO s with GEN and DAT case. In fact, we find from our own data that his description of DAT case-marked objects fails to adequately describe the range of cases wherein DAT marking of objects does arise (we also note the absence of any description by Lavidas of GEN marked objects). Furthermore, in his description of CG’s DO cases, Lavidas falls victim to the mistake of taking an aerial approach that spans several periods of Ancient Greek, rather than pursuing an examination of specific periods. As before, this approach often results in broad generalizations that obfuscate important facts about any given stage.
Nonetheless, Lavidas (2009) provides a fundamental understanding of the construction of transitivity across the temporal cline of Greek, and Luraghi (2003, 2010) provides a more specific look at the way this phenomenon informs case-selection properties across Ancient Greek. The present research then builds on these works by applying these principles to an even more specific data set, in analyzing how such processes can be understood in terms of Classical Greek only.
3 Data domain and data collection methodology
While previous considerations of CG case have attempted to generalize across all of Ancient Greek, we concern ourselves only with Classical Greek (c. 500–300 BCE). By doing this, we can examine a data domain that is internally consistent and avoid potentially confounding semantic changes that might arise over a longer time span. Our study is also restricted to works of prose, excluding poetic and theatrical works. This is done in order to avoid the anomalies that might arise in works that are stylistically fashioned (and distorted) by meter and which often involve violations of canonical grammatical form.2 Prose works, e.g., historical and rhetorical texts, tend to adhere more faithfully to grammatical norms and provide more reliable indicators of DO case-marking parameters of CG. The following authors then make up the source material for our investigation: Herodotus (c. 484–425 BCE), Thucydides (c. 460–400 BCE), Lysias (c. 445–380 BCE), Isocrates (c. 436–338 BCE), Xenophon (c. 431–354 BCE), Plato (c. 428–348 BCE), Aeschines (c. 389–314 BCE), Demosthenes (c. 384–322 BCE), and Aristotle (c. 384–322 BCE). While the writings of these authors do involve a small range of dialect variation, these dialectal differences are not sufficiently large as to impact the canonical case marking patterns of verbs’ objects.
To preclude confounds that might arise from an examination of multiple classes of verbs (e.g., ditransitives and experiencer verbs), the study was limited to an examination of sentences containing monotransitive predicates in active constructions with a single direct object complement. Accordingly, psychological predicates were excluded from consideration, since the subject-object relationship of verbal complements in these constructions tends to be rather fluid, as in example (3). Filip (1996: 3) asserts, apropos of this concern, that “linking in the domain of psychological predicates is problematic if we assume that there is a direct and uniform association between thematic (or lexical semantic) arguments and syntactic arguments”.
(3) a. Snakes frightened Sam.
b. Sam feared snakes.
Propositional attitude verbs were also excluded from the study, since these predicates typically take clausal (propositional) complements rather than direct object NP s, and do not usually assign object case, as in example (4).
(4) Tom believes [Sam fears snakes].
Data that conformed to the above-mentioned constraints was collected using the Perseus Online Digital Library (Crane 2005–2019). We note that this corpus is not searchable by grammatical marking, only by lexemes. Thus, once verbs were identified in preliminary research, they were then searched for in the corpus and items that were both (i) attributable to Classical Greek prose authors and (ii) active monotransitive constructions were added into the data set for analysis. Each verb identified as selecting an ACC-, GEN-, or DAT-marked direct object was searched for in all of its possible forms (i.e., in all six principal parts and inflections). Thirty-seven verbs were initially identified, six of which were excluded for a lack of tokens, resulting in the analysis of 300 instances of direct object sentences across 31 verbs.3
4 Theoretical background: argument structure
In our study, we reassess the properties used in Luraghi’s Transitivity Hierarchy, and find both that Affectedness is not a sufficiently precise feature on which to base such a hierarchy and that the properties of a verb’s subject can be just as important as its object in determining the transitivity of the clause as a whole. In framing our methodology, we have thus been led to consider a wider range of semantic features (and only semantic features that are precise enough to measure). We have also determined to examine, simultaneously, the semantic properties of both the subject and object arguments of the transitive clause, to ensure that subject properties are fairly considered alongside the object ones.
In this regard, our coding of subject and object semantic features cannot rely on the traditional inventory of theta-roles as they are usually conceived of in Generative Grammar. These thematic/semantic roles (i.e., theta-roles or
To date, there is no reliable, completely consistent inventory of thematic roles from which one might build a coherent and complete lexical semantic framework for a language, and the inventories most commonly invoked do not adequately account for the full range of observable data (Jackendoff, 1987; Dowty, 1991). There is disagreement on the commonly proposed theta role inventories in terms of the number of roles, the role labels, and the linkage of these roles to grammatical functions. Jackendoff (1987: 371), for instance, argues against the unnecessary conflation of syntactic arguments and semantic theta-roles, referring to the reliance on theta-roles as a “thinly disguised wild card to meet the exigencies of syntax”. Eschewing any isomorphism between syntax and semantics, Jackendoff (p. 372) suggests that the three “autonomous levels of structure: phonological, syntactic, and semantic/conceptual” each have their own “characteristic primitives and principles of combination, and [their] own organization into subcomponents”. Dowty (1991) extrapolates on such primitives in his explanation of “thematic proto-roles,” and departs from the strict view of theta-roles as primitives and as one-to-one, absolute correlates of syntactic roles.
For this reason, we appeal to accounts of lexical semantic properties that are both more nuanced and more precisely measured. One of the more carefully constructed accounts of these properties is found in Dowty (1991), wherein an inventory of “Proto-role Properties” (i.e., a set of entailments) is proposed. Rather than relying on discrete theta-roles, Dowty (1991) proposes a group of semantic properties that can serve as ‘tendency-makers’ that push semantic participants into grammatical slots based on those properties. This relationship is one that is more fluid than traditionally rigid theta-role assignments. Rather than giving a list of autonomous theta-role primitives, Dowty (1991) posits semantic role prototypes, in which there are different degrees of membership in two primary categories—(i) proto-agent and (ii) proto-patient. Proto-roles serve as entailments proceeding from the relation of a verb with a particular argument of that verb (see Table 2).
To instrumentalize these properties, Dowty proposes an argument selection principle, which is again more fluid than previous conceptions of syntactic and semantic argument structure. This principle states that “the argument for which the predicate entails the greatest number of Proto-Agent properties will be lexicalized as the subject of the predicate; the argument having the greatest number of Proto-Patient entailments will be lexicalized as the direct object” (pp. 576). With this selection principle in mind, Ackerman & Moore (2001) provide an extension to Dowty’s theory, supporting its use as a theoretical apparatus, and providing the Paradigmatic Argument Selection Principle, described by Hovav (2003: 648) as dealing “with cases in which there is an alternation in the encoding of a specific argument, accompanied by a change in interpretation”. Ackerman and Moore’s (2001) approach, in which sets of arguments are compared, further emphasizes the importance of both subjects and objects simultaneously determining the relevant roles in the determination of object case-marking. Thus, Dowty’s Proto-role theory and research emanating from it serves as the foundation on which the present study rests, taking relevant properties of both the subjects and objects in CG constructions to yield an analysis of DO case-marking.
Table 2
Dowty’s (1991) Proto-role Properties [pp. 571–574]
i. |
Dowty’s Proto-Agent roles: |
a.Volitional involvement in the event or state |
|
b.Sentience (and/or perception) |
|
c.Causing an event or change of state in another participant |
|
d.Movement (relative to the position of another participant) |
|
e.Exists independently of the event named by the verb |
|
ii. |
Dowty’s Proto-Patient roles: |
a.Undergoes change of state |
|
b.Incremental theme |
|
c.Causally affected by another participant |
|
d.Stationary relative to movement of another participant |
|
e.Does not exist independently of the event, or not at all |
Utilizing Dowty’s Proto-roles, a number of researchers have delved more deeply into their significance and use, and have endeavored to make them more precise. Among those who have worked to make these proto-roles more explanatory are Ackerman & Moore (2001), Hovav (2003), Næss (2007), Beavers (2010, 2011), and Grimm (2011).
Næss (2007) takes a closer look at Dowty’s (i-a) volitionality and (i-b) sentience, showing both that sentience covers a wider range of cases than volitionality, and that volitionality is more nuanced and context dependent. While both are deemed to be inherent properties of agents, it is volitionality which figures as a more useful distinction and more critical to the concept of agentivity. Essential to this, as Næss notes, is that volitionality is preserved under negation, while sentience need not be; cf. John didn’t listen to the song (as he didn’t want to) vs. John didn’t hear the song (as he had died that morning). It also holds up if an agent refuses to act, as in John wouldn’t break the glass. Næss (pp. 187–188) also reports on the importance of volition for case-marking, especially regarding psychological predicates such as hear, above. In Kannada, the verb ‘see’ takes a NOM subject when the action described a volitional seeing (similar to English look at or watch). However, when ‘see’ is understood as a psychological experiencer predicate, and the subject is not volitional, it takes a DAT subject. All this leaves volition as a more consequential semantic feature than sentience.
Dowty’s (ii-a) change of state (COS) and (ii-c) affectedness are two other Proto-role Properties which overlap to some degree and have generated closer examination in the literature, particularly in Beavers (2010, 2011) and Grimm (2011). Observations noted in both Beavers’ and Grimm’s papers complicate Luraghi’s Hierarchy, since her hierarchy relies on both COS and Affectedness being discrete, binary features. Beavers and Grimm both contend that Affectedness cannot be adequately captured as a binary and is at the very least tertiary. Grimm (2011: 521–522) challenges the supposed “binary distinction” between affected and unaffected, on the grounds that it obfuscates instances of something being “partially affected,” a distinction that he argues is lost in most typological studies invoking the feature. For his part, Beavers (2010, 2011) suggests that Affectedness is best captured as a degree or scale of COS.
To properly address the matter of affectedness, Beavers (2010) proposes an Affectedness Hierarchy, which involves three types of change and four degrees of affectedness. The types of change are: change of state, change of location, and creation/consumption. The degrees of affectedness in the hierarchy are quantized change > non-quantized change > potential change > unspecified change. With both quantized and non-quantized change, affectedness accompanied by change is entailed, but only in the case of quantized change is it measured, with the degree of change reported. COS is not entailed by potential change, and this degree of affectedness implies an action having taken place which affects an object in a manner which may or may not lead to a change in the object. To display the difference between potential change and unspecified change, Beavers (2010) points to the difference between John hit the rope and John hit at the rope (838), wherein the first entails that the rope receives the brunt of an action which may or may not change it, while the latter does not entail that the object is affected in any way, let alone changed.
Given that Dowty’s proto-roles provide a more highly articulated set of metrics by which to assess the semantics of subject and object arguments, along with the research pursuant to his proposal since that time, we determined to use them as a basis from which to approach the question of DO case-selection, testing the range of meaning-relationships indicated by object case-marking in CG. It is important to understand, as Dowty suggests, that the properties are not completely determinative in mapping arguments to subject and object positions. Rather, subjects tend to exhibit more (rather than always exhibiting all) agent Proto-role Properties, and objects tend to exhibit more patient Proto-role Properties. It is therefore possible (and actually common) for subjects to exhibit some patient-like properties, and for objects to exhibit some agent-like properties. Different verbs may then illustrate unique trends across the assignment and implication of such roles. For this reason, in our examination of the data, we sought to test the full range of both agent and patient Proto-role Properties.
5 Statistical analysis
In this section, we provide a statistical examination of the CG, to determine (i) whether the explanatory device of Luraghi’s transitivity hierarchy is borne out in a more carefully curated set of CG data and (ii) whether a differently constructed hierarchy (feature-wise) might be more predictive. Collected tokens were tested first in accordance with Luraghi’s Hierarchy (Section 5.2.1) and then through the lens of Dowty’s proto-roles (Section 5.2.2).
From this examination we found that Luraghi’s predictions for a COS-based hierarchical distinction between the ACC and GEN marked objects are borne out, but that her predictions for an affect-based distinction between the GEN and the DAT do not. In fact, we find, quite surprisingly, that DAT objects do not fit into this hierarchy at all. Accordingly, while the first two levels of Luraghi’s Hierarchy (High Transitivity being indicated by +COS and selecting the ACC, and Medium Transitivity by -COS and selecting the GEN) are confirmed, DAT objects are unaccounted for and have no place in the hierarchy, regardless of what features are applied. In other words, DAT objects cannot be made to fit into the transitivity hierarchy through the invocation of the COS-feature and something else.
5.1 Preliminary observations
Before coding the entire collection of CG examples and applying a statistical analysis to that, we provide here some preliminary observations and note descriptive trends in the data. We find, first of all, that ACC case-marking verbs typically denote events that are telic and which clearly affect the object. Such verbs typically denote events wherein there is a clear distinction between the state of affairs before and the state of affairs after. The subjects and objects of such verbs align well with Dowty’s subject and object Proto-roles—that is, their subjects have Proto-Agent Properties, and their objects have Proto-Patient Properties. This observation accords with descriptions given in Luraghi 2003 and 2010, our typical understanding of “theme”, and the canonical direct object semantic role. Example (5) illustrates a typical ACC case-marking verb,
(5)
τοὺς ὄρτυγ -ας
καὶ
τοὺς ἀλεκτρυόν -ας …
ἀπέκτειναν the quail-acc.pl
and
the rooster-acc.pl
kill.3pl.aor.act
‘They killed the quails and the roosters.’
Aeschines, Against Timarchus 1.59
Contrasting with ACC case-marking verbs, GEN4 case-marking verbs typically denote states or activities (i.e., are atelic). Their effect on the object is not always clear or particularly important to the action described, and it is often the case that the verb’s effect on its subject is more important and focused than its effect on the GEN object. The semantic properties of the arguments of GEN case-marking verbs tend to be less consistent than those of ACC case-marking verbs. This is not unexpected and perhaps predicted by Luraghi’s Transitivity Hierarchy, which places ACC-marking verbs higher on the transitivity scale. In terms of Proto-role Properties this would lead to the expectation that subjects and objects of ACC case-marking verbs would have, respectively, more proto-agent and proto-patient properties, while proto-agent and proto-patient properties might be less predictably distributed among the subject and object arguments of GEN case-marking verbs. An example of a GEN case-marking verb,
(6)
τοῖς
δὲ
σπουδαί -οις
οὐχ
οἷόν
τε
τῆς ἀρετ -ῆς
ἀμελεῖν the. dat.pl
but
earnest-dat.pl
neg
such
conj
the virtue-gen.sg
neglect.pres.act
‘But the good cannot neglect such virtue.’
Isocrates, To Demonicus 1.48
The verbs in the third class, the DAT case-marking verbs, tend to denote events that are directed towards the object, although there is often no measurable effect upon the object … Much like GEN case-marking verbs, agent and patient Proto-role Properties are not canonically distributed to the subject and object arguments of DAT case-marking verbs. An example of a DAT case-marking verb,
(7)
πολλὰ
ἀπειλήσας
τοῖς Χίοις mightily
threaten.nom.sg.aor.act.ptcpl
the Chian-dat.pl
‘… having mightily threatened the Chians.’
Thucydides, The Peloponnesian War 8.33
5.2 Statistical analysis
This section presents the results of two statistical analyses of object case-marking drawn from the CG data that we collected and coded for semantic properties. First, we tested whether Luraghi’s Hierarchy can account for the distribution of ACC, GEN, and DAT case-marking. Finding this not to be the case, we next tested the distribution of case against Dowty’s Proto-role Properties, to see if any subset of these semantic features could be used to devise a workable hierarchy similar to Luraghi’s, which could predict levels of transitivity and through case-marking. In our examination of the 2010 Transitivity Hierarchy, we did find support for the correlation of (ACC object marking) high transitivity and (GEN object marking) medium transitivity levels with the presence or absence of the COS property. However, we also did not find support for the inclusion of DAT-marked objects in the Hierarchy on the basis of a correlation with an Affectedness feature as the 2010 Heirarchy would have it. Thus, the present study devises a revision of the Transitivity Hierarchy that proposes only two levels of transitivity and which places DAT object-marking verbs outside of it for reasons that become clear below.
To test Luraghi’s Hierarchy against the CG data, all sentence tokens were coded for the object properties +/−COS and +/−affected, and the transitivity score of each sentence was based on the following arrangement of these features: +COS/+affected = high transitivity; −COS/+affected = medium transitivity; and −COS/−affected = low transitivity. We then determined to what extent the transitivity scores reliably predicted object case-marking in accordance with Luraghi’s claims: high transitivity sentences have ACC objects, medium transitivity sentences have GEN objects, and low transitivity sentences have DAT objects. This analysis was performed with a Chi-square test, using the chi.square function in R Studios (R Core Team, 2018). Since Chi-square tests are suitable for determining whether there is a significant interdependence between two categorical variables, the test was used to find out whether the determinative features used in the Transitivity Hierarchy correctly predict the case-marking of objects.
Finding that COS is predictive but that Affectedness is not, the CG data was then re-examined to determine whether the COS feature might be coupled with other Proto-role Properties to successfully predict the ACC>GEN>DAT Hierarchy. For this purpose, the CG data was coded for the full set of Dowty’s Proto-role Properties (excepting, of course, for affect), to determine whether any of these might interact in a significant way with the data and predict the case marking of objects. By using both subject and object semantic properties, we aimed to test the predictive capacity of each of them, on the understanding that both subject and object properties can collectively determine case marking of the object. Each verb-token was coded +/− for the five Agent Proto-role features of their subjects (i.e., triggering COS, volitionality, movement, independent existence, and sentience) and +/− four Patient Proto-role features of their direct objects (i.e., undergoing COS, incremental theme, lack of movement, and dependent existence). Note that only nine of Dowty’s ten Proto-role Properties are used, because (as discussed in Section 4) Affectedness is not a reliably binary property and because it was already shown to not be predictive (to the extent that it could be coded properly). We also note, in regard to the coding of COS properties, that we only counted the first two stages of Beaver’s (2010, 2011) COS hierarchy (Quantized Change and Non-quantized Change). Accordingly, constructions which entailed quantized change or non-quantized change were coded as +COS, and constructions which entailed potential change or unspecified were coded as −COS.
With this coding in place, Multinomial Logistical Regressions (MLR s) were performed on the full range of data via the multinom function (Venables & Ripley 2002). As MLR s use the Maximum Likelihood Parameter to test for the best fitting predicative model for a categorical Dependent Variables with 3+ levels (here, DO case) across multiple Independent Variables (here, Dowty’s nine Proto-role Properties), we find this to be the best approach to the current data—the MLR s thus helped to determine which features were relevant to the prediction of case-marking on the DO. The results of the MLR are discussed below in Section 5.2.1. The data was coded by the two authors separately, and then discussed. Any discrepancies between coding were discussed and clarified; any discrepancies that could not be resolved were discarded from the data set.
From this examination, we find that COS is predictive of ACC and GEN case-marking, but none of the other semantic features were found to DAT-marking on objects in interaction with COS. We found instead, in addition to being −COS, that DAT objects can also indicate subject movement towards a goal. However, as discussed in section 5.3, this turns out to be reason to believe that DAT-selecting verbs are not best represented within the same hierarchy as ACC and GEN, and are better understood in terms of Blume’s (1998) interaction verbs.
5.2.1 Results: Chi-Square test
This section presents the results of the first step of our analysis, i.e., testing whether predictions made by Luraghi’s Hierarchy are confirmed by a Chi-Square test. It turns out that they are not. While High Transitivity (+COS/+affected) strongly correlates with ACC case-marking, Medium Transitivity (−COS/+affected) does not correlate with the GEN-case, but in fact correlates far more strongly with the DAT case-marking. Furthermore, we find that Low Transitivity (−COS/−affected) better correlates with GEN case-marking and has no correlation at all with the DAT. This indicated that while +COS does in fact set ACC apart from the GEN and DAT case-marking verbs, +/−COS and +/−affected coding does not predictably distinguish between GEN and DAT case-marking verbs. These results call into question the use of +/−affected as a binary feature by which to predict CG case-marking of objects.
If Luraghi’s Hierarchy and the features that are said to underlie it were correct, then the number of instances of ACC-case verb constructions should be highest in the first column under (+COS, +Affected), the number of instances of GEN-case verb constructions should be highest in the second column under (−COS, +Affected), and the number of instances of DAT-case verb constructions should be highest in the last column under (−COS, −Affected). However, our findings disconfirm Luraghi’s predictions. Table 3 shows the largest number of ACC-case verb constructions in the first column (n=30), the largest number of GEN-case verb constructions split across columns two (n=31) and three (n=32), and the largest number of DAT-case verb constructions in column two (n=46) with just a few in columns one (n=2) and three (n=4).
Luraghi’s Hierarchy thus appears, descriptively, to be disconfirmed by the data. Our descriptive assessment is confirmed through statistical analysis. A Chi-Square analysis reveals a highly significant interaction between transitivity and the assignment of case ([X2(4, 154)=130.7, p < .0001]). However, these findings do not fully support Luraghi’s Hierarchy. The Chi-Square residuals in Table 4 contradict Luraghi’s claim that GEN objects are more transitive than DAT objects, where a positive value communicates a positive factor by which the case-marking and level of transitivity can be correlated, and a negative value indicates lack thereof. Thus, while the interaction is highly significant, the results show DAT case-assigning verbs to be more transitive than GEN case-assigning verbs, contrary to the ranking proposed in Luraghi 2010. The correlation plot of the residuals in Figure 1 further illustrates this problem with Luraghi’s predictions.
Table 3
Luraghi’s Transitivity Hierarchy
High |
Medium |
Low |
|
---|---|---|---|
+COS/+Affected |
−COS/+Affected |
−COS/−Affected |
|
ACC |
30 |
8 |
0 |
GEN |
1 |
31 |
32 |
DAT |
2 |
46 |
4 |
Table 4
Chi-Square Pearson’s Residuals (Luraghi’s Hierarchy Transitivity)
ACC |
GEN |
DAT |
|
---|---|---|---|
High |
7.660 |
–3.433 |
–2.739 |
Medium |
–2.833 |
–0.728 |
3.229 |
Low |
–2.980 |
4.405 |
–2.339 |
Accordingly, it must be either that the transitivity ranking (ACC > GEN > DAT) is incorrect or that the properties +/−COS and +/−Affected do not together determine the ranking. Not only does the analysis result in the unexpected hierarchy ACC > DAT > GEN, but it also splits GEN case-marking verbs across two levels of transitivity, Medium and Low. Given these results, along with doubts about using +/−Affected as a binary feature, we are inclined to find more fault with the features than with the hierarchy.
There is also an additional reason to trust the hierarchy above the features, namely the fact that there are CG verbs which optionally mark their objects with ACC or GEN case. This, combined with the fact that there are no CG verbs that display alternating ACC/DAT case-marking of their objects, suggests that ACC and GEN marking are more closely aligned than are ACC and DAT marking. In fact, verbs which case-mark their objects with DAT case only mark them with DAT, suggesting perhaps that DAT case-marking itself lies outside of the transitivity hierarchy altogether.
5.2.2 Results: Multinomial Logistic Regression
This section reports a test of the nine of Dowty’s Proto-role features that we used in coding the CG sentence data, in order to determine if any subset of them can be used to construct a hierarchy similar to that of Luraghi’s, one which accurately predicts case-marking patterns found in CG prose. To best test this, we employed Multinomial Logistic Regressions (MLR s). In performing various MLR s across the possible combinations of identified features, we found the two most interpretable models and the two with the lowest Akaike Information Criterion (AIC) scores5 to be: first, a model which tests the interaction between COS, volition, and object lack of movement (called here MLR-A, AIC = 172.3508), and second, a model which tests COS, subject movement, and object lack of movement (MLR-B, AIC = 188.0661). Reducing our regression model to only two of the above-mentioned features, we find the best-fitting model to be that of COS and subject movement (MLR-C, AIC = 191.0066).6
Though the reduction of features in MLR-C leads to a slightly higher AIC than MLR-A, we find it more compelling because volition in MLR-A is not independently predictive at all, and is only predictive when interacting with COS. Despite this, COS is equally predictive with or without volition, indicating that with or without volitionality, the determinate feature remains COS (P-test values show that COS alone has exactly the same p-value as both COS and volitionality, and volitionality alone is not predictive at all). The same can be said for MLR-B concerning object lack of movement, which is no more predictive than COS alone. As such, MLR-A and -B work only to reaffirm what we already know: COS correlates with ACC case-marking, and a lack of COS correlates to non-ACC. However, these two tests do not provide any information as to what sets GEN and DAT case-marking predicates apart?
Testing for MLR-C, we finally find interactions that set the ACC, GEN, and DAT cases apart from each other. COS, as predicted by Luraghi and MLR-A and MLR-B, continues to demarcate the distinction between highly transitive ACC and the other cases. GEN case-marking verbs are 99.99 % less likely to have objects that undergo COS than ACC case-marking verbs (p < .0001). However, alongside that, we also find that subject movement can distinguish DAT from both GEN and ACC. While subject movement is not a significant feature of GEN case-marking verbs, DAT case-marking verbs are 99.93 % less likely to have subjects which do not move than ACC case-marking subjects are at a rate that is significant (p = .013).
Thus, the only feature which consistently and reliably differentiates the case-marking of CG objects is that of COS, setting apart the ACC case-marked DO s from those marked with either GEN or DAT case. COS is always present in the most interpretable models having the relatively lowest AIC scores, and even when models include other variables, those variables are only as significant as COS is alone. The only exception to this is the interaction seen with the variable of DAT case-marking. However, it cannot even be said that DAT case-marking verbs most often have subjects which exhibit subject movement, only that they have them more often than do ACC or GEN case-marking verbs. While this does lead to a successful featural analysis of the distribution of these three object cases, it does not permit us to establish the three-tiered hierarchy of transitivity based on these two features.
Table 5
MLR-C Exponentiated Coefficient Values
Object Case |
COS |
Subject Move |
COS: Move |
---|---|---|---|
GEN |
.000521 |
9.479 e-08 |
1 |
DAT |
3.569 e-08 |
.0635 |
1 |
5.3 Discussion
The results presented herein confirm the importance of COS to the selection of certain object-cases in CG, but do not support the construction of a hierarchy for all three case-marking classes with this property alone, or even with this property in combination with some other. While we find that COS indeed distinguishes highly transitive ACC from not-as-transitive GEN, we find reason to conclude that DAT does not belong in the hierarchy at all. Essentially, GEN and DAT are not readily distinguished from each other as belonging to distinct levels of a transitivity hierarchy. While this might not be satisfying to anyone in search of a better hierarchy (or of any hierarchy), the results do make much clearer how semantic features determine CG object cases. The results also serve to call into question any use of Affectedness as a binary feature that (partly) determines transitivity or case-marking classes.7 In this regard, it is worth recalling both Beaver’s (2010, 2011) and Grimm’s (2011) contention that affectedness and COS are actually parts of one dynamic feature, rather than two distinct features.
We are still left here with the important question of determining how CG distinguishes between the GEN and DAT case-marking verb classes (both being predicates which do not necessitate COS of their objects). Here, we can say that although DAT case-marking verbs cannot be included on a transitivity scale that otherwise characterizes the distribution of ACC and GEN, DAT case-marking is clearly an indicator of other aspects of verb meaning. Blume (1998) examines DAT-selecting two-place verbs, giving them special attention and remarking on the unique behavior of DAT case-marked objects across a variety of languages (German, Polish, Hungarian, Romanian, Tongan, and Samoan). In this analysis, Blume argues for a class of interaction verbs, verbs which denote a series of overlapping subevents,
“in s[ubevent]1 one participant is presupposed to strive consciously for a certain aim … and in s[ubevent]2 the other participant performs an unspecified action that contributes to the aim of the first one”.
Blume 1998: 255
In this analysis, DAT case-marking verbs denote types of events not well captured by typical subject-object, or agent-patient, relationships, since both the subject and object each present some properties typical of agents (268). For instance, movement (an Agent proto-role) is found only with DAT case-marked objects and never with ACC or GEN case-marked objects (although not with a sufficient number of DAT case-marking verbs for the feature to be independently significant in our MLR). We also find subject movement to be relevant for DAT-marked objects where it is not especially relevant for ACC or GEN-marking verbs.
Unsurprising then, we find that verbs whose action entails reciprocity of movement or action (i.e., verbs whose meaning involves subjects and objects which both undergo movement or are active participants) are found in the class of DAT case-marking verbs. Examples of these are:
The property of being interactional also figures into the classification of other, less obvious, instances of DAT case-marking verbs. For instance, Blume presents German helfen ‘help’ to be representative of this proposed verb class, and predictably CG
(8)
ὦναξ ,
αὐτ -ὸς
μὲν
οὕτω
τοῖσι ἱκέτῃσ -ι
βοηθέεις …;Lord.voc,
self-nom.sg
indeed
thus
the suppliants-dat.pl
aid-2s.pres.act
‘Lord, will you indeed rescue the suppliants?’
Herodotus, The Histories 1.159
In this regard, consider also the difference between the verb
DAT case-marking verbs might be said to occupy a lexical semantic space outside of the hierarchy, with the hierarchy being orthogonal for these verbs. If this is true, then it might explain the lack of any verb-class which alternates between the DAT-marking and another case, in contrast with ACC and GEN verbs which do engage in these alternations. We would conjecture that DAT case is lexically assigned by any verb which does so, as indexing a very specific type of complicated event, as described by Blume. Verbs that assign lexical DAT case to their objects would not therefore have the capacity to have this case alternate with some structural case, nor would any +/−COS alternation lead to a difference in the case-marking of such verbs’ objects. A full analysis of DAT verbs thus needs further study, with an examination of their behavior in other environments, such as in passives. Such study is outside of the purview of the present work (though cf. Alexiadou et al. 2010, 2014; Anagnostopoulou & Sevdali 2015).
The present research appears to support the analysis of transitivity proposed by Lavidas (2009), in which a complex picture of transitivity, more reliant on COS, is put forward. While +/−COS verbs consistently set themselves apart in terms of case-selection, we find the situation with DAT case-marking verbs much more complicated. ACC and GEN case-assigning verbs are simply and clearly distinguished by the feature +/−COS. Separately, DAT case-marking verbs represent an interesting, and complex, relationship best described under Blume’s (1998) analysis of interaction verbs.
6 Conclusions and directions for further research
The observations, analyses, and conclusions we have presented here are by no means the last word on this topic. Further analysis is warranted into other Classical Greek texts and genres and other syntactic environments, expanding on the data-domain presented herein. What we have hopefully accomplished is to present a coherent, corpus-driven analysis of the semantic correlates of object case marking for one period of Ancient Greek (i.e., Classical Greek). In delimiting our corpus to a 200–300 year range of texts, we hope to have avoided the confounding contributions of language change, which might have affected and blurred our analysis were we to have included texts over the entire ~1000-year period of Ancient Greek.
The observations made here confirm the basic thesis of Luraghi (2003, 2010) which posits a “transitivity hierarchy” determining the case of transitive verbs’ objects, though we find reason to believe it does not operate in the exact ways that she details. Our observations for, and analysis of, Classical Greek do show, however, that (i) this hierarchy is sensitive to COS, (ii) it is most appropriate to apply this hierarchical relationship to the ACC and GEN only, given the behavior of both non-alternating and alternating ACC- and GEN-marking verb classes, and (iii) DAT-marked objects seem to interact differently from ACC- and GEN-marked objects relative to this hierarchy.
Thus, we propose that this research can and should be taken a step further in order to investigate the case of case-marking alternations in CG verbs, in order to answer in certain terms, whether this alternation can be said to reflect the same sorts of relationships first posed by Luraghi and then further developed herein. If such answers can be provided, it may be possible to then apply these results to close readings of CG texts, texts which display verbs having alternating case-selection patterns. This might lead to a better understanding of the contextual or pragmatic implications of such case alternations that have been previously unrecognized (as Danesi et al., 2018 find, regarding the use of oblique cases to mark subjects in certain CG modal constructions). Turning these results back onto a reexamination of the corpus data may also give way to insights into what might otherwise be anomalous instances of case-marking alternations seen with a small number of verbs, and which indeed have, until now, been considered as such.
This study breaks new ground in its careful application of Dowty’s 1991 thematic proto-role features to the variable case-marking on verbal objects, and in applying this analysis to a large-enough body to yield statistically significant results. In terms of CG, we can attest to the relevance of COS, but can also point to the lack of determinacy of Affectedness as might be predicted by Beaver (2010, 2011) and Grimm (2011).
What remains to be accomplished, and what is well outside the scope of this study, is to apply this method to other periods and other varieties of Ancient Greek. Doing so could provide evidence that the transitivity hierarchy (as a correlation between semantic features and grammatical cases) is stable over time or possibly that it is subject to change. While our present research has taken a synchronic approach, it is our recommendation that further research on this topic might strengthen the findings presented herein by applying these methods to other periods of Greek, thus taking a diachronic perspective. The methods and conclusions of this study also beg application to other languages that might have regular correlations between semantic features and case marking, to discover whether the transitivity hierarchy might be cross-linguistically generalizable and whether it is semantically stable, feature-wise. In such an approach, one hopes to gain insight not only into the development and interaction of semantic and syntactic case within Greek itself, but, perhaps, to shed light on this interaction at large.
Appendix A
Classical Greek verbs analyzed under the present analysis
Appendix B
Table B1
Agent Proto-role Property Raw Counts
Volitional |
Non-Volitional |
|
---|---|---|
Sentience |
Non-Sentient |
|
Movement |
No Movement |
|
Independent |
Dependent |
|
ACC |
38 |
0 |
GEN |
64 |
1 |
DAT |
31 |
18 |
ACC |
36 |
2 |
GEN |
64 |
1 |
DAT |
50 |
2 |
ACC |
7 |
31 |
GEN |
0 |
65 |
DAT |
16 |
36 |
ACC |
38 |
0 |
GEN |
65 |
0 |
DAT |
52 |
0 |
Table B2
Patient Proto-role Property Raw Counts
COS |
No COS |
|
---|---|---|
Incremental |
Non-Incremental |
|
Stationary |
Movement |
|
Dependent |
Independent |
|
ACC |
30 |
8 |
GEN |
1 |
64 |
DAT |
0 |
52 |
ACC |
6 |
32 |
GEN |
5 |
60 |
DAT |
0 |
52 |
ACC |
38 |
0 |
GEN |
65 |
0 |
DAT |
42 |
10 |
ACC |
9 |
29 |
GEN |
1 |
64 |
DAT |
0 |
52 |
Using the term Classical Greek in this work, we are referencing a time period which includes Attic and Ionic Greek. While Attic and Ionic do represent two different dialects of Classical Greek, they are very closely related, and we do not believe that there are sufficient differences between them to present any problem for the research results reported here. Their typology is discussed at length by Colvin (2010), wherein Attic and Ionic are collapsed together as “East Greek” (p. 205), as the “differences between [Attic and Ionic] are relatively trivial” (p. 209). The two also share an extensive list of similarities, innovations, and retentions, which set them apart from other contemporary dialects of CG. Lavidas (2009) also discusses the importance of Attic and Ionic Greek in particular to this time period, naming them as particularly influential over their other contemporary varieties. They are also the best-attested varieties as far as prose texts are concerned.
For more on this, see Golston & Riad (2000), wherein they discuss the differential role of prosody and meter in prose and poetic works, with syntactic constraints outranking prosodic constraints in speech and prose, but being outranked by prosody in poetry. They explain that this is “especially true” in dramatic works of tragedy and comedy in Classical Greek, citing Aeschylus, Euripides, Sophocles, and Aristophanes (all authors who would otherwise fit within our data domain, excepting their genre or work). Within the works of these authors, Golston and Riad report that there is evidence of “prosodic concerns in meter [forcing] syntactic constraints to be violated” (p. 106). For this reason, we exclude these authors from our corpus of study.
For a list of the verbs examined for this study, see Appendix A (proto-role raw counts in Appendix B). These verbs were gathered from an Ancient Greek textbook (Hansen & Quinn 1992) and an authoritative grammar (van Emde Boas et al. 2019). We focused on verbs listed in these sources as taking non-ACC objects. However, some of these verbs were accompanied by a specific explanation for their having anomalous case selection, and those verbs were not considered. For example, verbs of consumption are typically understood to take GEN case because GEN case functions as a partitive marker, so that these were not considered for that reason.
It was suggested to us during the 2019 LSA meeting that perhaps the Genitive of Negation in Russian could shed light on the assignment of Genitive in Classical Greek. While we did look through our data with this perspective in mind, our descriptive analysis noted no uniformity in the negation of a proposition and the subsequent case-marking of ACC, GEN, or DAT; thus negation was not considered a meaningful variable under our statistical analysis.
For readers unfamiliar with MLR s, let us briefly explain that, unlike p-values, AIC scores are interpretable and relevant only in context of a single dataset and the set of MLR s run on that data. There is no fixed ‘correct’ or ‘best’ AIC score, only those AIC scores generated in each data set by the range of MLR s tested. Thus, given a full range of MLR s run on any dataset, the most reliable regression is ostensibly the one with the lowest relative AIC score, though this must be considered in concert with the interpretability of a model.
While these models were those with by far the lowest AIC scores, and therefore the only ones mentioned herein, we did test the complete range of possible combinations of all nine features.
For further discussion of Luraghi’s use of COS and Affectedness, see Murphy et al. (2019), which presents the findings that even when the secondary feature of Affectedness is invoked, Luraghi’s Hierarchy is not borne out in the way that is predicted.
References
Ackerman, Farrell, & John Moore. 2001. Proto-properties and grammatical encoding: A correspondence theory of argument selection. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.
Alexiadou, Artemis, Elena Anagnostopoulou, & Christina Sevdali. 2010. Patterns of dative-nominative alternations. Proceedings of the North Eastern Linguistics Society (NELS) 41 (University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia PA).
Alexiadou, Artemis, Elena Anagnostopoulou, & Christina, Sevdali. 2014. Opaque and transparent datives, and how they behave in passives. The Journal of Comparative Germanic Linguistics 17.1.1–34.
Anagnostopoulou, Elena, & Christina Sevdali. 2015. Case alternations in Ancient Greek passives and the typology of Case. Language 91.2.442–481.
Beavers, John. 2010. The structure of lexical meaning: why Semantics really matters. Language 86.4.821–864.
Beavers, John. 2011. On affectedness. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 29.2.335–370.
Blume, Kerstin. 1998. A contrastive analysis of interaction verbs with dative complements. Linguistics 36.2.253–280.
Crane, Gregory R. (ed.). 2005–2019. Perseus digital library (Perseus 4.0). Medford, MA: Tufts University. http://www.perseus.tufts.edu (accessed December 7, 2019)
Colvin, Stephen. 2010. Greek Dialects in the Archaic and Classical Ages. A companion to the Ancient Greek language, ed. by Egbert J. Bakker, 200–212. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell Publishing.
Danesi, Serena, Cynthia Johnson, & Jóhanna Barðdal. 2018. Where does the modality of Ancient Greek modal verbs come from? The relation between modality and oblique case marking. Journal of Greek Linguistics 18.1.45–92.
Dowty, David. 1991. Thematic proto-roles and argument selection. Language 67.3.547–619.
Filip, Hannah. 1996. Psychological predicates and the syntax-semantics interface. Conceptual structure, discourse, and language, ed. by Adele E. Goldberg, 131–147. Stanford, CA: Center for the Study of Language and Information.
Golston, Chris, & Tomas Riad. 2000. The phonology of Classical Greek meter. Linguistics 38.1.99–167.
Grimm, Scott. 2011. Semantics of case. Morphology 2.3/4.515–544.
Hansen, Hardy, & Gerald M. Quinn. 1992. Greek: An intensive course (2nd Edition). New York: Fordham University Press.
Hovav, Malka Rappaport. 2003. Review of Proto-properties and grammatical encoding: a correspondence theory of argument selection by Farrell Ackerman and John Moore. Journal of Linguistics 39.3.657–652.
Jackendoff, Ray. 1987. The status of thematic relations in linguistic theory. Linguistic Inquiry 18.3.369–411.
Lavidas, Nikolaos. 2009. Transitivity alternations in diachrony. Changes in argument structure and voice morphology. Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.
Liddell, Henry George, Robert Scott, Henry Stuart Jones, & Roderick McKenzie. 1996. Greek-English lexicon with a revised supplement (9th Edition). Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Luraghi, Silvia. 2003. On the meaning of prepositions and cases: The expression of semantic roles in Ancient Greek. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Luraghi, Silvia. 2010. The extension of the transitive construction in Ancient Greek. Acta Linguistica Hafniensia 42.60–74.
Næss, Åshild. 2007. Prototypical transitivity. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
RStudio Team. 2018. RStudio: Integrated development for R. Boston, MA: RStudio. http://www.rstudio.com/
Siegal, Elitzur Bar-Asher & Nora Boneh. 2015. Decomposing affectedness: Truth-conditional non-core datives in Modern Hebrew. Proceedings of IATL30. MIT Working Papers in Linguistics 78. Cambridge, MA: MITWPL.
Smyth, Herbert & Gordon Messing. 1956. Greek grammar. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
van Emde Boas, Evert, Albert Rijksbaron, Luuk Huitink, & Mathieu de Bakker. 2019. The Cambridge grammar of Classical Greek. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Venables, William N. & Brian D. Ripley. 2002. Modern Applied Statistics with S. Fourth Edition. New York: Springer.
Warnes, Gregory, Ben Bolker, Lodewijk Bonebakker, Robert Gentleman, Wolfgang Huber, Andy Liaw, Thomas Lumley, Martin Maechler, Arni Magnusson, Steffen Moeller, Marc Schwartz, & Bill Venables. 2019. gplots: Various R programming tools for plotting data. R package version 3.0.1.1. https://CRAN.R-project.org/package=gplots
Williams, Edwin. 1995. Theta Theory. Government and binding theory and the minimalist program: Principles and parameters in syntactic theory, ed. by Gert Webelhuth, 97–124. Cambridge, MA: Wiley Blackwell Limited.
Wei, Taiyun, & Viliam Simko. 2017. R package “corrplot”: Visualization of a Correlation Matrix (Version 0.84). https://github.com/taiyun/corrplot
Zaenen, Annie & Joan Maling. 1990. Unaccusative, passive, and quirky case. Proceedings of 3rd West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, Stanford University, ed. by Mark Cobler, Susannah MacKaye, and Michael T. Wescoat, 317–329. Stanford, CA.: CSLI Publications.