Denken om shalom: De praktische filosofie van Nicholas Wolterstorff, edited by Robert van Putten, Bart Cusveller and Rob Nijhoff

In: Philosophia Reformata
View More View Less
  • 1 Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam, Amsterdam, The Netherlands, woutbisschop@gmail.com

If the inline PDF is not rendering correctly, you can download the PDF file here.

Buijten & Schipperheijn Motief, Amsterdam, 2017. 288 pages. isbn 978-90-5881-955-0.

Readers of Dutch are being served with a new access to the practical philosophy of Nicholas Wolterstorff. Two of the book’s fifteen chapters are translations of Wolterstorff’s works, to wit, a short autobiography, and a newly written exposé in which he explains why he is a Kuyperian, but not a Dooyeweerdian. The other thirteen chapters are generally introductory and appreciative in kind, with limited critical engagement. Although his epistemological work receives hardly any attention, the book provides a good introduction to a large part of Wolterstorff’s oeuvre.

Denken om shalom is divided into five parts. In the first part, Herman Veenhof reflects on Wolterstorff’s autobiographical essay and his writings on grief after the loss of his son. He concurs with Wolterstorff on the need for lament and the appropriation of one’s grief and notes that, even though Wolterstorff thinks the image of an empathetic but helpless God is theologically unsatisfying, his ideas on the suffering love of God in fact approach it closely.

The second part is on justice and politics, and opens with an essay by Geert Jan Spijker on Wolterstorff’s defense of an “equal political voice” in the public sphere. Against widely shared liberal views that the public domain should only allow for views acceptable to all reasonable people, Wolterstorff maintains that citizens should have an equal opportunity to participate in lawful democratic debate with contributions that suit their particularities, including religious ones.

Govert Buijs is more critical in raising the question of what exactly Wolterstorff was aiming for with his book-length argument that the only sound justification of human rights is a theistic one that sees human rights as inherent to human beings. Would it not have been better, especially as a Christian philosopher, to search for traces of God’s human dignity bestowing presence in other traditions as well, rather than joining the choir of the contemporary debunking discourse on human rights? If Wolterstorff’s aim was apologetic, Buijs is concerned about the risk of lacking common ground with people who do not share his Christian presuppositions. Buijs is more sympathetic to two other possible aims. First, Wolterstorff seems to try to convince his fellow Christians that the idea of human rights is in line with the earlier Christian tradition and deserves their support. Second, in a secular world where human rights are a threatened species, Wolterstorff rightly articulates a deep concern regarding our understanding of them.

Robert van Putten explains how for Wolterstorff the authority of the state is limited by rights. Wolterstorff argues that the government is appointed by God—contra Yoder and Hauerwas—but does not have its authority in virtue of being the state (“positional authority”)—a mistaken view he ascribes to Calvin, among others. Rather, the state has “performance authority”; that is, an authority limited to its tasks and function. The government’s authority can also be derived from the right not to be harmed. Its tasks are not limited to punishment of wrongdoers but also concern—to some extent—the support of human flourishing, contributing to the realization of social goods. In doing so, the state should acknowledge the rights of all religions and religious institutions. Wolterstorff therefore objects to the two-rules doctrine of Aquinas and Calvin, according to which the state has a supportive function in relation to the church.

Part 3 is concerned with social practices: education, science, and art. Roel Kuiper explains Wolterstorff’s view on Christian education and poses a number of critical questions regarding his Responsibility Theory of Education, according to which education serves to form students in such a way that they tend to act responsibly. Education may serve to attain a more humane world; but should that be its prime aim?

René van Woudenberg introduces Wolterstorff’s view on science and contrasts it to the views of Kuyper and Dooyeweerd, as well as to the view that science and religion are non-overlapping magisteria. Various developments in the philosophy of science have shown the inadequacy of the once dominant view that science is an objective, neutral, general, rational, value-free, and presuppositionless endeavor. In response to the demise of this view, rather than embrace relativism, Wolterstorff concluded that science works differently from the way it often was supposed to work. We all are “cloaked in beliefs,” and traditions, culture, education, faith, etc., inevitably and positively contribute to our theorizing. Christians, therefore, need not ignore their faith when doing science—rather, they should participate in it as Christians. According to Wolterstorff, scientific theories are built from various kinds of beliefs: data beliefs, data background beliefs, and control beliefs. Faith can and should function as a control belief in the design and evaluation of theories.

Hans Teerds reflects in a personal voice on Wolterstorff’s criticism of the institution that art has become in modernity, as if art were something useless and separated from ordinary life. On the contrary, and from a Christian perspective, art is the way in which people relate to the world. They are like gardeners of that world, cultivating and constructing culture.

The fourth part of the book concentrates on issues pertaining to faith and the church. Rob Nijhoff reflects sympathetically on Wolterstorff’s view of liturgy as being primarily focused on God and engaging the church in the cause for justice and shalom. However, he finds little gain in Wolterstorff’s radical attempt to use only gender-neutral language when speaking of God.

Hans Burger presents Wolterstorff’s view on divine discourse as the divine deputization of human beings to speak on behalf of God, or as divine appropriation of human discourse. On this approach, a double hermeneutics is required: both the authorial discourse of the human author and that of the divine author need to be interpreted. Acknowledging the strengths of the proposal, Burger also notes how it raises new questions. For example, what exactly does the process of appropriation look like, and how should this determine our interpretation of the biblical text? The less we know about divine involvement in the genesis of biblical texts, the more difficult the question is what, for instance, Paul’s remarks on woman church leadership imply for Christians today.

Gijsbert van den Brink considers Wolterstorff’s philosophical-theological work and emphasizes in particular the significance of Wolterstorff’s contribution to the discussion on whether theology is still possible “after Kant.” Against the idea that knowledge of God is impossible due to the limits of our cognitive capacities, Wolterstorff indicates problems for Kant’s view and defends an alternative to the Kantian story along the lines of Reid, saying that, although our experiences are conceptually interpreted, we do perceive objects rather than mental representations. Van den Brink is critical about Wolterstorff’s sketch of the theological tradition and his arguments in evaluating a number of such traditional theological concepts as divine simplicity, immutability, eternity in the sense of “outside of time,” and impassibility.

The fifth and final part is labeled “Christian Philosophy” and is concerned with Wolterstorff’s relation to the neo-Calvinist tradition in philosophy. Readers unfamiliar with Wolterstorff’s philosophical and theological roots in this tradition may be surprised to find him at ease with a vocabulary and range of ideas quite different from what he employs in his other work. As one of the Kuyperian influences on his thought Wolterstorff identifies the idea that Christians are called to participate from a Christian perspective in social practices and institutions. Dooyeweerd’s concerns about the possibility of and problems with referring to God, however, he does not share. Bas Hengstmengel responds to this essay and, having described Wolterstorff’s relation to Dutch philosophers in the neo-Calvinist tradition, criticizes Wolterstorff’s reading of Dooyeweerd on this particular point. Wolterstorff’s relation to reformational philosophy is further explicated in Sander Griffioen’s examination of Wolterstorff’s view on the meaning and use of the term worldview in Dutch and American reformational philosophy—a notion that Griffioen likes much better than Wolterstorff but that he sees still operative in Wolterstorff’s ideas on, e.g., control beliefs.

According to Bart Cusveller, the practices of faith, theology, politics, justice, ethics, education, art, culture, liturgy, science, knowledge, and rationality are all interrelated in Wolterstorff’s oeuvre as various dimensions of shalom. He sought to develop a specifically Christian perspective on all of them: no part of human existence is neutral, and the various practices of life have their own aims and standards. This places him in the line of neo-Calvinist philosophers in particular, and of Christian thinkers in general.

If the inline PDF is not rendering correctly, you can download the PDF file here.

Content Metrics

All Time Past Year Past 30 Days
Abstract Views 174 123 0
Full Text Views 164 12 0
PDF Downloads 19 11 0