Aristotle takes practical wisdom and arts or crafts to be forms of knowledge which, we argue, can usefully be thought of as ‘empiricist’. This empiricism has two key features: knowledge does not rest on grasping unobservable natures or essences; and knowledge does not rest on grasping logical relations that hold among propositions. Instead, knowledge rests on observation, memory, experience and everyday uses of reason. While Aristotle’s conception of theoretical knowledge does require grasping unobservable essences and logical relations that hold among suitable propositions, his conception of practical and productive knowledge avoids such requirements and is consistent with empiricism.
Purchase
Buy instant access (PDF download and unlimited online access):
Institutional Login
Log in with Open Athens, Shibboleth, or your institutional credentials
Personal login
Log in with your brill.com account
Allen, J. (2001). Inference from Signs: Ancient Debates About the Nature of Evidence. Oxford.
Allen J. (2015). Practical and Theoretical Knowledge in Aristotle. In: Henry and Nielsen 2015, 49-70.
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1963). Intention. 2nd edn. Oxford.
Broadie, S. (1991). Ethics With Aristotle. Oxford.
Broadie, S. and Rowe, C. J. (2002). Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford.
Deichgräber, K. (1965). Die Griechische Empirikerschule: Sammlung der Fragmente und Darstellung der Lehre. Berlin / Zürich.
Frede, M. (1988). The Empiricist Attitude Towards Reason and Theory. Apeiron 21, pp. 79-97.
Frede, M. (1990). An Empiricist View of Knowledge: Memorism. In: S. Everson, ed., Epistemology, Cambridge, pp. 225-250.
Henry, D. (2015). Holding for the Most Part: The Demonstrability of Moral Facts. In: Henry and Nielsen, 2015, 169-90.
Henry, D. and Nielsen, K. M., eds. (2015). Bridging the Gap Between Aristotle’s Science and Ethics. Cambridge.
Irwin, T. (1999). Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics. 2nd edn. Indianapolis.
Kenny, A. J. P. (1966). The Practical Syllogism and Incontinence. Phronesis 11, pp. 163-184.
Leunissen, M. (2015). Aristotle on Knowing Natural Science for the Sake of Living Well. In: Henry and Nielsen 2015, 214-31.
Nielsen, K. M. (2015). Aristotle on Principles in Ethics: Political Science as the Science of the Human Good. In: Henry and Nielsen, 2015, 29-48.
Nussbaum, M. (1978). Aristotle’s De Motu Animalium. Princeton.
Price, A. W. (2011). Virtue and Reason in Plato and Aristotle. Oxford.
Schiefsky, M. (2005). Hippocrates: On Ancient Medicine. Leiden.
Scott, D. (1995). Recollection and Experience: Plato’s Theory of Learning and its Successors. Cambridge.
Walzer, R. and Frede, M. (1985) Galen: Three Treatises on the Nature of Science. Indianapolis.
All Time | Past Year | Past 30 Days | |
---|---|---|---|
Abstract Views | 1843 | 468 | 30 |
Full Text Views | 254 | 24 | 2 |
PDF Views & Downloads | 299 | 91 | 5 |
Aristotle takes practical wisdom and arts or crafts to be forms of knowledge which, we argue, can usefully be thought of as ‘empiricist’. This empiricism has two key features: knowledge does not rest on grasping unobservable natures or essences; and knowledge does not rest on grasping logical relations that hold among propositions. Instead, knowledge rests on observation, memory, experience and everyday uses of reason. While Aristotle’s conception of theoretical knowledge does require grasping unobservable essences and logical relations that hold among suitable propositions, his conception of practical and productive knowledge avoids such requirements and is consistent with empiricism.
All Time | Past Year | Past 30 Days | |
---|---|---|---|
Abstract Views | 1843 | 468 | 30 |
Full Text Views | 254 | 24 | 2 |
PDF Views & Downloads | 299 | 91 | 5 |