Save

Time’s Arrow and Simultaneity

In: Timing & Time Perception
Author:
Julian Barbour College Farm, South Newington, Banbury, OX 15 4JG, UK

Search for other papers by Julian Barbour in
Current site
Google Scholar
PubMed
Close
Open Access

Abstract

In his paper ‘Bridging the neuroscience and physics of time’ with Dean Buonomano () in a forthcoming book Rovelli makes claims that I question because they rely uncritically on theoretical frameworks employed when the laws of thermodynamics and general relativity were discovered. Their reconsideration suggests growth of entropy is not the origin of time’s arrow and identifies a notion of universal simultaneity within general relativity.

1. Introduction

The great discoveries in physics — Copernican revolution, Newton’s laws, thermodynamics, quantum mechanics, and relativity — were all made in a prevailing framework of concepts and knowledge. Thus, forces played no role in Copernicus’s reformulation of Ptolemy’s astronomy; it was first Kepler and then Newton who introduced them. For his part, Newton formulated his laws in the now rejected framework of absolute space and time. It was Carnot’s study of steam engines that led to the discovery of thermodynamics in 1850, when virtually nothing was known about the universe at large. Finally, the spacetime form in which Einstein created general relativity (GR) obscured critical aspects of its dynamical structure that came to light decades later. The contexts in which these discoveries were made need to be taken into account in their modern interpretation and cast doubt on Rovelli’s claims.

2. Thermodynamics

Of thermodynamics, Einstein (1979) said. “It is the only physical theory of universal content which I am convinced that, within the framework of applicability of its basic concepts, will never be overthrown.” Einstein did not spell out the framework of applicability. It is hard to find in textbooks but history suggests what it is. Steam engines fail if their steam is not confined. In their atomistic explanation of the laws of thermodynamics the creators of statistical mechanics always assumed particles which collide with each other and bounce elastically off the walls of a box. Thermodynamics is the science of confined systems. In them growth of entropy (usually interpreted as a measure of disorder) from a special low-entropy state is readily explained. What is impossible to explain by the known time-reversal symmetric laws of nature is the origin in confined systems of the special initial state.

In the theory of dynamical systems, those ‘in a box’ correspond formally to ones that have a phase space of bounded Liouville measure; to my knowledge systems with phase spaces of unbounded measure have never been seriously studied in statistical mechanics. This is a remarkable lacuna since it is only in confined systems that the Poincaré recurrence theorem holds and is the main reason why a satisfactory explanation for time’s arrow eluded Boltzmann (1896) and so many since. We need to see if lifting the phase space bound gives the sine qua non for solution to the problem of time’s arrow: time-irreversible behaviour in generic solutions of time-reversal symmetric equations without invocation of a special condition.

I will show this is the case in the oldest dynamical theory, the Newtonian N -body problem of gravitating point particles of masses mi, i = 1,…, N. It has an unbounded phase space since its scale variable
rms = 1Mi<jmimjrij2,  rij= | rirj |,   M = iNmi,
the root-mean-square length, is unbounded above. As shown in Barbour (2020), Barbour et al. (2014), and Mercati (2018), this leads to behaviour quite different from confined systems. If the energy is non-negative and does not vanish, then as a function of Newton’s absolute time t (1) is concave upwards and tends to infinity either side of a unique minimum or ‘Janus point’. Moreover, D=drms/dt is monotonic, tending from −∞ to in both time directions; D is therefore a Lyapunov variable, which rules out Poincaré recurrence: N -body statistics cannot be ‘box statistics’.
To see this, consider the Newton potential energy
VNew=i<jmimjrij
made scale-invariant as the shape potential Vshape through multiplication by rms:
Vshape=rmsVNew.
With its sign reversed Vshape may, as in Barbour et al. (2014) and Barbour (2020), be called the shape complexity since, independently of gravitational theory, it is a sensitive measure of the extent to which mass points in Euclidean space have a uniform or clustered distribution. Indeed mhl1 αVNew where
mhl1=1m2i<jmimjrij
is the mean harmonic length, which means that
Cshape=rmsmhl
has an absolute minimum when the particles are most uniformly distributed and increases rapidly when they cluster because that changes rms relatively little but greatly reduces mhl. Note that Cshape depends only on the shape of the particle distribution. In fact, the entire objective content in any N -body solution resides entirely in the shapes it contains. They could all be jumbled up in a random heap without any physical information being lost. For the ‘shape-dynamic’ representation of gravitational theory see Mercati (2016).

Provided E ≥ 0 and zero-measure solutions to be discussed below are excluded, the qualitative behaviour of Cshape shown in Fig. 1 for a numerical N -body solution of 1000 particles is universal: Cshape grows with fluctuations between linearly rising bounds either side of the Janus point, where (as in the ‘artist’s impression’) the particle distribution is uniform and becomes clustered either side. The existence of the Janus point owes nothing to a special condition added to Newton’s laws. It is present in every generic solution with E ≥ 0 (see Note 1).

Figure 1.
Figure 1.

From Barbour et al. (2014).

Citation: Timing & Time Perception 12, 2 (2024) ; 10.1163/22134468-bja10077

The behaviour either side of the Janus point justifies its moniker: on the N -body timeline it lies between bidirectional arrows of time that the secular growth of Cshape defines. Observers must be present on one or other side of the Janus point and even though Newton’s laws are time-reversal symmetric, will experience an arrow of time. The arrow does not arise from statistical behaviour of an ensemble of solutions and is secular, not a fluctuation. What is more, the increased clustering that Cshape measures reflects the formation of more or less isolated systems that virialise and then generally decay. Their ‘birth–virialisation–death’ arrows, the hallmark of self-confined thermodynamic systems like stars, all align with the master complexity arrow. It is noteworthy that subsystem decay often leaves two particles in elliptical orbits around their centre of mass. These ‘Kepler pairs’ generally live forever and become ever better rods, clocks and compasses all in one, each of them perfectly synchronised with all the others (Barbour et al., 2014; Barbour, 2020). Unlike growth of entropy, which is associated with increase of disorder, growth of complexity reflects increase of order.

It is particularly interesting that the zero-measure N -body solutions mentioned above (and discussed in Barbour, 2020, chs. 16–18), model ‘big bangs’ in GR: they begin with zero size as measured by rms. In them the behaviour of Cshape matches what is seen on either side of the Janus point in Fig. 1. Finally, the solutions with negative energy either have a ‘Janus region’ with bidirectional arrows of time either side of it or remain permanently bound and are virialised within a bounded region as is typical of statistical–mechanical systems with phase spaces of bounded measure. Moreover, the relational Machian form of Newtonian gravity (Barbour and Bertotti, 1982) that models GR allows only solutions with E = L = 0 and ensures there are always dynamical arrows of time.

Thus, the complete set of solutions of the N -body problem divide into those that never leave a bounded region of their phase space and those that explore an unbounded region. The former exhibit typical thermodynamic behaviour while the latter always have master dynamical arrows of time and secondary thermodynamic behaviour in emergent subsystems that the master arrow entails. This is all a direct consequence of Newton’s laws. Despite being time-reversal symmetric, they are fully capable of having solutions that are time-asymmetric on one or both sides of a distinguished point that has a dynamical as opposed to ad hoc origin and show that time-reversal symmetric dynamics is perfectly compatible with a dynamical (not statistical) arrow of time.

Let me compare these rigorous results in the N -body problem with some of the comments of Rovelli, who represents the physics side of Buonomano and Rovelli (2021) and says: “For a theoretical physicist […] the distinction between past and future requires thermodynamics, hence is statistical only.” Further, from the time-reversal invariance of ‘all elementary mechanical laws’ it follows that “the manifest time orientation of the world around us can only be a macroscopic phenomenon that is accounted for in terms of the distinction between micro- and macrophysics, and caused by low entropy in the early universe.” Despite Einstein’s caveat, there is no discussion on Rovelli’s part of the conditions of applicability of the basic concepts of thermodynamics. Along with virtually all physicists who have written about the arrow of time he retains the conceptual framework created by the discovery of thermodynamics through the study of steam engines and the associated restriction to dynamical systems with phase spaces of bounded Liouville measure. If, as is certainly the case for a model N -body universe, the phase space of the universe is unbounded, we must surely be prepared to re-examine dogmas from the 1850s.

3. General Relativity and Simultaneity

In the form in which Einstein formulated GR in 1915, there is no distinguished notion of simultaneity in spacetime, which can be foliated completely freely by three-dimensional hypersurfaces provided they are spacelike. However, decades later important insights were gained into the structure of GR when treated as a dynamical theory of evolving curved three-dimensional geometry. Dirac (1958) cast GR into its simplest possible Hamiltonian form by eliminating all nonphysical degrees of freedom. He came to the remarkable conclusion that this could be done “only at the expense of giving up four-dimensional symmetry” (Dirac’s emphasis) and continued “I am inclined to believe from this that four-dimensional symmetry is not a fundamental feature of the physical world.” In contrast to Einstein’s great insight that “each individual solution [in classical GR] […] exhibits four-dimensional symmetry” Dirac argued this need not apply in a quantum theory because “the individual solution has no quantum analogue”. Therefore “Hamiltonian methods [needed for quantisation], if expressed in their simplest form, force one to abandon the four-dimensional symmetry”.

Dirac (1959) introduced a condition which ensured this, but only valid for universes of infinite spatial extent. In the same year Arnowitt et al. (2008) published the first of a series of papers that also cast GR into Hamiltonian form but, by not insisting on the simplest possible form, did so in a way that left open four-dimensional symmetry. It was the ADM form that Astekhar, Rovelli, and Smolin adopted in their attempt to create a discrete form of quantum gravity they called loop quantum gravity (LQG). However, despite some early success, the key problem in LQG — the quantum treatment of what is called the Hamiltonian constraint — has defied resolution for more than 30 years. The difficulty arises precisely because ADM retained four-dimensional symmetry. More evidence that it might be abandoned with advantage comes from important work of York (1972) in the early 1970s on the initial-value problem in GR. This showed that three-dimensional spatial symmetry is an integral part of GR and introduced a notion of universal simultaneity that differs from Dirac’s choice in being applicable if the universe is spatially closed.

I do not claim Dirac’s and York’s work definitively restores universal simultaneity but it does suggest need for a qualification of Rovelli’s categoric statement “Objectively defined global simultaneity surfaces are not defined in general relativity.” Moreover, since the currently observed accelerated expansion of the universe suggests that, like the N -body problem, it too has an unbounded phase space, Dirac’s maximally simple form of GR and N -body big-bang solutions have very similar dynamical forms, and there are analogues of the complexity both for vacuum GR (Barbour, 2020; Yamabe, 1960) and GR coupled to a scalar field Choquet-Bruhat et al, 2007) it seems likely that, pace Rovelli, the arrow of time in our universe has a dynamical and not statistical origin.

Finally, the complexity (Barbour, 2020) has remarkable properties with radical possibilities I have not been able to address in this note and are discussed in Barbour (2022).

Note

1.

Figure 1 (from Barbour et al., 2014) is for equal-mass particles with vanishing energy and angular momentum, E = L = 0. These Machian conditions (Barbour and Bertotti, 1982) match the dynamical structure of spatially closed general-relativistic solutions (Mercati, 2018) and merely enhance the Janus-point behaviour always present when E ≥0.

References

  • Arnowitt, R., Deser, S., & Misner, C. W. (2008). Republication of: The dynamics of general relativity. Gen. Rel. Grav., 40, 19972027. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10714-008-0661-1.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Barbour, J. (2020). The Janus Point: A new theory of time. New York, NY, USA: Hachette Book Group.

  • Barbour, J. (2022). Complexity as time. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=vskzeQc9XpI, 2022.

  • Barbour, J., Koslowski, T., & Mercati, F. (2014). Identification of a gravitational arrow of time, Phys Rev Lett. 113, 181101; https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevLett.113.181101.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Barbour, J. B. & Bertotti, B. (1982). Mach’s principle and the structure of dynamical theories. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. A Math. Phys. Sci., 382, 295306. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspa.1982.0102.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Boltzmann, L. (1896). Über Hrn. Zermelo’s Abhandlung “Über die mechanischer Erkl¨arung irreversibler Vorgange”. Ann. Phys., 60, 392–398. (Translation in S. Brush (2003). The Kinetic Theory of Gases: An anthology of classical papers with historical commentary. London, United Kingdom: Imperial College Press.).

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Buonomano, D., & Rovelli, C. (2021). Bridging the neuroscience and physics of time. arXiv preprint. https://doi.org/10.48550/arXiv.2110.01976.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Choquet-Bruhat, Y. Isenberg, J., & Pollack, D. (2007). The constraint equations for the Einstein-scalar field system on compact manifolds, Class. Quantum Gravity, 24, 809. https://doi.org/10.1088/0264-9381/24/4/004.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Dirac, P. A. M. (1958). The theory of gravitation in Hamiltonian form. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. A Math. Phys. Sci., 246, 333343. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspa.1958.0142.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Dirac, P. A. M. (1959) Fixation of coordinates in the Hamiltonian theory of gravitation Phys. Rev., 114, 924. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRev.114.924.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Einstein, A. (1979). Autobiographical notes. In: P. A. Schilpp & A. Einstein (Eds), Autobiographical notes. A centennial edition (pp.). La Salle, IL, USA: Open Court.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation
  • Mercati, F. (2018). Shape dynamics: Relativity and relationism. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.

  • Yamabe, H. (1960). On a deformation of Riemannian structures on compact manifolds. Osaka Math. J., 12, 2137.

  • York, J. W. (1972). Role of conformal three-geometry in the dynamics of gravitation. Phys. Rev. Lett., 28, 1082. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevLett.28.1082.

    • Search Google Scholar
    • Export Citation

Content Metrics

All Time Past Year Past 30 Days
Abstract Views 0 0 0
Full Text Views 132 132 13
PDF Views & Downloads 239 239 56